Results for 'Charles Côte-Bouchard'

996 found
Order:
  1. Knowledge, Reasons, and Errors about Error Theory.Charles Cote-Bouchard & Clayton Littlejohn - 2018 - In Christos Kyriacou & Robin McKenna (eds.), Metaepistemology: Realism & Antirealism. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.
    According to moral error theorists, moral claims necessarily represent categorically or robustly normative facts. But since there are no such facts, moral thought and discourse are systematically mistaken. One widely discussed objection to the moral error theory is that it cannot be true because it leads to an epistemic error theory. We argue that this objection is mistaken. Objectors may be right that the epistemic error theory is untenable. We also agree with epistemic realists that our epistemological claims are not (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2. Can the aim of belief ground epistemic normativity?Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (12):3181-3198.
    For many epistemologists and normativity theorists, epistemic norms necessarily entail normative reasons. Why or in virtue of what do epistemic norms have this necessary normative authority? According to what I call epistemic constitutivism, it is ultimately because belief constitutively aims at truth. In this paper, I examine various versions of the aim of belief thesis and argue that none of them can plausibly ground the normative authority of epistemic norms. I conclude that epistemic constitutivism is not a promising strategy for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  3. Epistemic Instrumentalism and the Too Few Reasons Objection.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2015 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (3):337-355.
    According to epistemic instrumentalism, epistemic normativity arises from and depends on facts about our ends. On that view, a consideration C is an epistemic reason for a subject S to Φ only if Φ-ing would promote an end that S has. However, according to the Too Few Epistemic Reasons objection, this cannot be correct since there are cases in which, intuitively, C is an epistemic reason for S to Φ even though Φ-ing would not promote any of S’s ends. After (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  4. Is Epistemic Normativity Value-Based?Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2017 - Dialogue 56 (3):407-430.
    What is the source of epistemic normativity? In virtue of what do epistemic norms have categorical normative authority? According to epistemic teleologism, epistemic normativity comes from value. Epistemic norms have categorical authority because conforming to them is necessarily good in some relevant sense. In this article, I argue that epistemic teleologism should be rejected. The problem, I argue, is that there is no relevant sense in which it is always good to believe in accordance with epistemic norms, including in cases (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  5. Belief's own metaethics? A case against epistemic normativity.Charles Cote-Bouchard - 2017 - Dissertation, King's College London
    Epistemology is widely seen as a normative discipline like ethics. Just like moral facts, epistemic facts – i.e. facts about our beliefs’ epistemic justification, rationality, reasonableness, correctness, warrant, and the like – are standardly viewed as normative facts. Yet, whereas many philosophers have rejected the existence of moral facts, few have raised similar doubts about the existence of epistemic facts. In recent years however, several metaethicists and epistemologists have rejected this Janus-faced or dual stance towards the existence of moral and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Two types of epistemic instrumentalism.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2019 - Synthese 198 (6):5455-5475.
    Epistemic instrumentalism views epistemic norms and epistemic normativity as essentially involving the instrumental relation between means and ends. It construes notions like epistemic normativity, norms, and rationality, as forms of instrumental or means-end normativity, norms, and rationality. I do two main things in this paper. In part 1, I argue that there is an under-appreciated distinction between two independent types of epistemic instrumentalism. These are instrumentalism about epistemic norms and instrumentalism about epistemic normativity. In part 2, I argue that this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. ‘Ought’ implies ‘can’ against epistemic deontologism: beyond doxastic involuntarism.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2019 - Synthese 196 (4):1641-1656.
    According to epistemic deontologism, attributions of epistemic justification are deontic claims about what we ought to believe. One of the most prominent objections to this conception, due mainly to William P. Alston, is that the principle that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ rules out deontologism because our beliefs are not under our voluntary control. In this paper, I offer a partial defense of Alston’s critique of deontologism. While Alston is right that OIC rules out epistemic deontologism, appealing to doxastic involuntarism is not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  24
    Harry Frankfurt peut-il sauver le blâme doxastique? Possibilités alternatives épistémiques et involontarisme doxastique.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2012 - Ithaque 10:137-157.
    Peut-on être blâmé pour ses croyances? Bien qu’il s’agisse d’une pratique courante et en apparence légitime, le blâme doxastique entre en conflit avec deux thèses intuitivement plausibles. D’un côté, il semble que nous puissions seulement être blâmés pour ce qui est sous notre contrôle volontaire. Mais de l’autre, il est largement admis que la croyance est un état fondamentalement passif et involontaire. Il s’ensuit que nous ne pouvons jamais être blâmés pour nos croyances. Le présent article examine la réponse que (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  32
    Epistemic deontologism and the voluntarist strategy against doxastic involuntarism.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2011 - Ithaque 8:1-16.
    According to the deontological conception of epistemic justification, a belief is justified when it is our obligation or duty as rational creatures to believe it. However, this view faces an important objection according to which we cannot have such epistemic obligations since our beliefs are never under our voluntary control. One possible strategy against this argument is to show that we do have voluntary control over some of our beliefs, and that we therefore have epistemic obligations. This is what I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  11
    Sosa, E. , Knowing Full Well.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2011 - Ithaque 9:159-163.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  37
    Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism.Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2010 - Ithaque 7:131-135.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  58
    Epistemological closed questions: A reply to Greco.Charles Côte-Bouchard - 2017 - Manuscrito 40 (4):97-111.
    ABSTRACT According to G.E. Moore’s ‘Open Question’ argument, moral facts cannot be reduced or analyzed in non-normative natural terms. Does the OQA apply equally in the epistemic domain? Does Moore’s argument have the same force against reductionist accounts of epistemic facts and concepts? In a recent article, Daniel Greco has argued that it does. According to Greco, an epistemological version of the OQA is just as promising as its moral cousin, because the relevant questions in epistemology are just as ‘open’ (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. The Motivation Problem of Epistemic Expressivists.Alexandre Duval & Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 10.
    Many philosophers have adopted epistemic expressivism in recent years. The core commitment of epistemic expressivism is that epistemic claims express conative states. This paper assesses the plausibility of this commitment. First, we raise a new type of problem for epistemic expressivism, the epistemic motivation problem. The problem arises because epistemic expressivists must provide an account of the motivational force of epistemic judgment (the mental state expressed by an epistemic claim), yet various features of our mental economy seem to show that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Epistemic Consequentialism, Veritism, and Scoring Rules.Marc-Kevin Daoust & Charles Côté-Bouchard - 2023 - Erkenntnis 88 (4):1741-1765.
    We argue that there is a tension between two monistic claims that are the core of recent work in epistemic consequentialism. The first is a form of monism about epistemic value, commonly known as veritism: accuracy is the sole final objective to be promoted in the epistemic domain. The other is a form of monism about a class of epistemic scoring rules: that is, strictly proper scoring rules are the only legitimate measures of inaccuracy. These two monisms, we argue, are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  62
    Littérature et histoire du christianisme ancien.Timothy Pettipiece, Tuomas Rasimus, Charles Mercure, Dominique Côté, Michael Kaler, Marie-Pierre Bussières, Delphine Bayona, Jean-Thomas Nicole, Paul-Hubert Poirier & Louis Painchaud - 2001 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 57 (2):337-365.
  16.  27
    From Groups to Individuals: Evolution and Emerging Individuality.Frédéric Bouchard & Philippe Huneman (eds.) - 2013 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
    Our intuitive assumption that only organisms are the real individuals in the natural world is at odds with developments in cell biology, ecology, genetics, evolutionary biology, and other fields. Although organisms have served for centuries as nature’s paradigmatic individuals, science suggests that organisms are only one of the many ways in which the natural world could be organized. When living beings work together—as in ant colonies, beehives, and bacteria-metazoan symbiosis—new collective individuals can emerge. In this book, leading scholars consider the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  17.  37
    Littérature et histoire du christianisme ancien.Jennifer K. Wees, Charles Mercure, Serge Cazelais, Marie-Pierre Bussières, Eric Crégheur, Timothy Pettipiece, Michael Kaler, Paul-Hubert Poirier, Louis Painchaud & Dominique Côté - 2001 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 57 (3):563-604.
  18.  55
    Littérature et histoire du christianisme ancien.Tuomas Rasimus, C. Kazadi, Claude Bégin, Timothy Janz, Dominique Côté, Paul-Hubert Poirier, Timothy Pettipiece, Robert Hurley, Annick Thibault, Anne Pasquier, Louis Painchaud, Charles Mercure, Marie-Pierre Bussières & Andrius Valevicius - 2001 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 57 (1):121-182.
  19.  46
    Littérature et histoire du christianisme ancien.Eric Crégheur, Steve Bélanger, Serge Cazelais, Dominique Côté, Lucian Dîncã, Steve Johnston, Michael Kaler, Jean Labrecque, Charles Mercure, Louis Painchaud, Timothy Pettipiece, Paul-Hubert Poirier & Jennifer Wees - 2003 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 59 (3):541-582.
  20. Côté’s ‘Siger and the Skeptic'.Charles Bolyard - 2011 - In Medieval Skepticism, and the Claim to Metaphysical Knowledge. pp. 27-31.
  21. La Nouvelle Rhétorique Introduction À l'Œvre de Charles Perelman.Guy Bouchard - 1980 - Université Laval, Institut Supérieur des Sciences Humaines.
    Une première partie décrit la théorie générale de l'argumentation en délimitant les cadres de celle-ci (accent sur les divers types d'auditoire, depuis la délibération intime jusqu'à l'auditoire universel), en examinant son point de départ (choix et présentation des prémisses) et en faisant l'inventaire des techniques argumentatives (types d'arguments, étude de l'ensemble du discours). La seconde partie applique la théorie générale de l'argumentation à l'analyse du discours philosophique pour finalement relever comment Perelman tente de donner un nouveau souffle à la philosophie (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  32
    Art and Human Emotions. Par Egon Weiner. Springfield, Charles C. Thomas, 1975. 90 p.Guy Bouchard - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (4):754-755.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Gérard Deledalle, "Charles S. Peirce, phénoménologue et sémioticien". [REVIEW]Guy Bouchard - 1989 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 25 (1):61.
    If Peirce was a "backwoodsman" of semiotic, Deledalle is a pioneer in presenting Peirce to francophone readers. His new book aims at introducing them to a global reading of Peirce's thought according to three periods:nominalistic (1851-70), logico-mathematical and methodological (1870-87), and metaphysical (1887-1914). Given Peirce's writing output, to synthesize, systematize and periodize his works would have been a colossal endeavor. However, Deledalle limited himself to the "Collected Papers" and to an already existing periodization. But the decision not to take into (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  26
    Esthétique et sémiologie.Guy Bouchard - 1974 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 30 (1):63.
    L'article présente d'abord les principales tendances de l'esthétique: centrées sur les arts du beau (peinture, sculpture, littérature, etc.: définition extensionnelle ouverte), elles divergent en termes de rattachement à un champ d'étude plus vaste (l'expérience sensible, l'art ou la beauté en général, etc.). Les principales tendances de la sémiologie, de leur côté, correspondent à une science ou doctrine générale des signes, à une science des signaux (signes servant à communiquer), voire à une science des seuls signaux non linguistiques, à l'exclusion des (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  41
    Maine de Biran: une anthropologie transcendantale.Roch Bouchard - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (1):1-13.
    Maine de Biran passe à raison pour avoir rénové l'empirisme. Mais il semble qu'on n'ait pas toujours aperçu à quelle distance il a porté de son origine la méthode issue de Locke et de Condillac. Nous voudrions montrer ici comment il a pu infléchir la tradition empiriste dans un sens complètement opposé aux doctrines de ses fondateurs, comment il en a pu tirer une anthropologie tout à fait nouvelle, où l'homme n'apparaissait plus comme un élément de la nature, non plus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  29
    Une explication cognitive des effets attribués à la c-commande dans les contraintes sur la coréférence.Denis Bouchard - 2009 - Corela. Cognition, Représentation, Langage 7 (HS).
    On retrouve la notion de c-commande dans plusieurs contraintes linguistiques sur l’interprétation d’éléments qui sont dépendants pour leur interprétation référentielle. À bien y penser, il est assez étonnant d’avoir une relation syntaxique comme contrainte sur ce type d’interprétation : cela semble tout à fait accidentel, on n’en voit pas la motivation. Cette relation syntaxique correspond en fait le signifiant d’un signe combinatoire, et en regardant le côté signifié plutôt que signifiant de cette relation, sa présence dans une contrainte sur la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  2
    La philosophie des religions de John Hick: la continuité des principes philosophiques de la période "chrétienne orthodoxe" à la période "pluraliste".Charles Morerod - 2006 - Paris: Parole et silence.
    Depuis la publication en 1957 de sa thèse de philosophie, sous le titre Faith and Knowledge, John Hick a publié plus de vingt-cinq livres et d'innombrables articles de philosophie de la religion. Que cette abondante production ait été traduite en au moins dix-sept langues montre son importance dans la philosophie de la religion contemporaine. Toute son œuvre vise à offrir un cadre d'interprétation du phénomène religieux qui soit crédible aujourd'hui, à côté de visions non-religieuses qui ont aussi leur crédibilité mais (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  14
    Penser la danse avec Mikel Dufrenne.Charles Bobant - 2022 - Noesis 37:43-53.
    Cet article vise à exposer et discuter les thèses du phénoménologue Mikel Dufrenne au sujet de la danse. Dans _Phénoménologie de l’expérience esthétique_, Dufrenne interroge l’art chorégraphique aux côtés des autres arts et depuis les concepts « d’objet esthétique », « d’_a priori _existentiel » et de « monde ». Plus exactement, il soutient que l’œuvre chorégraphique déploie, par l’entremise des danseurs, de leurs mouvements et des autres éléments scéniques, une atmosphère affective qui correspond à l’attitude existentielle du chorégraphe. Après (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Paideia et Philosophie au Siècle des Lumières.Sébastien Charles - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 11:15-22.
    Parti d'une formulation maladroite de Rousseau laissant croire qu'il ne s'était rien fait sur le thème de l'éducation des Quelques pensées sur l'éducation de Locke à l'Émile, nous avons d'abord voulu montrer le côté fallacieux d'une telle proposition pour bien faire ressortir au contraire l'intérêt d'un tel sujet au siècle des Lumières, sujet qui mobilise toute l'attention des philosophes. Et cette importance accordée à l'éducation est nettement perceptible sur quatre points, qui sont au coeur de l'articulation logique de notre travail. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  6
    Lydie Bodiou, Véronique Mehl, Jacques Oulhen, Francis.Charles Delattre - 2012 - Clio 36.
    Le volume Chemin faisant réunit vingt-et-un articles rassemblés en hommage à l’historien de la Grèce classique Pierre Brulé et aux activités qu’il a développées au sein du CRESCAM-LAHM (UMR 6566). Il peut ainsi servir de pendant à La Grèce d’à côté, un recueil d’articles de P. Brulé publié en 2007 : les compagnonnages de l’historien, illustrés par la participation de P. Briant, de M.-M. Mactoux, de L. Bruit-Zaidman, de R. Parker, de S. Georgoudi, de M. Jost, de V. Dasen ou (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  2
    Les « choses humaines » selon Machiavel.Charles Boyer - 2021 - L’Enseignement Philosophique 72 (4):41-47.
    Ne lire par commodité que Le Prince nous procure une vision partielle, voire tronquée, de la philosophie politique de Machiavel. Il est donc nécessaire de la compléter par la lecture des Discours sur la première décade de Tite-Live pour en apprécier l’unité : il n’y a pas d’un côté le conseiller du prince et de l’autre le républicain. On y verra alors une conception du monde dont la modernité s’enracine paradoxalement dans des catégories anciennes comme l’astrologie et la médecine antiques, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  34
    L'évaluation : un pouvoir supposé savoir.Yves Charles Zarka - 2009 - Cités 37 (1):113.
    Il semble que, malgré les nombreuses mises en garde de ces dernières années venant de différents côtés, l’installation de dispositifs d’évaluation s’opère actuellement dans tous les secteurs de la société et les institutions : l’hôpital et le système de santé, les institutions d’éducation et de formation en général, les universités et la recherche en particulier,...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  34
    Éditorial.Yves-Charles Zarka - 2010 - Cités 42 (2):3-7.
    « En vertu de quoi la catégorie de l’Utopique possède donc à côté de son sens habituel et justement dépréciatif, cet autre sens qui, loin d’être nécessairement abstrait et détourné du monde, est au contraire centralement préoccupé du monde : celui du dépassement de la marche naturelle des événements »« Il n’y a guère, même parmi les économistes bourgeois, un savant..
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  16
    Il n’y a plus d’ailleurs.Yves Charles Zarka - 2010 - Cités 42 (2):3-7.
    « En vertu de quoi la catégorie de l’Utopique possède donc à côté de son sens habituel et justement dépréciatif, cet autre sens qui, loin d’être nécessairement abstrait et détourné du monde, est au contraire centralement préoccupé du monde : celui du dépassement de la marche naturelle des événements »« Il n’y a guère, même parmi les économistes bourgeois, un savant..
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  6
    Genèse de la réflexion québécoise sur la laïcité dans les travaux de Charles Taylor et Gérard Bouchard.Solange Lefebvre - 2011 - Philosophy, Culture, and Traditions 7:71-86.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Connaissance de soi et réflexion pratique: critique des réappropriations analytiques de Sartre.Samuel Webb - 2022 - Paris: Editions Mimésis.
    How do we know ourselves? When it comes to our states of mind, it might seem that self-knowledge enjoys a privilege: I know what I'm thinking because I have immediate access to my mind. Inspired by Sartre, two American philosophers, Richard Moran and Charles Larmore, have argued that this idea fails to account for our singular relationship with our own minds. In addition to knowing ourselves through theoretical reflection, we are also capable of practical reflection. We can answer the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  25
    Immanent Reasoning or Equality in Action A Dialogical Study.Shahid Rahman, Nicolas Clerbout, Ansten Klev, Zoe Conaughey & Juan Redmond - unknown
    PREFACEProf. Göran Sundholm of Leiden University inspired the group of Logic at Lille and Valparaíso to start a fundamental review of the dialogical conception of logic by linking it to constructive type logic. One of Sundholm's insights was that inference can be seen as involving an implicit interlocutor. This led to several investigations aimed at exploring the consequences of joining winning strategies to the proof-theoretical conception of meaning. The leading idea is, roughly, that while introduction rules lay down the conditions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  89
    The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex.Charles Darwin - 1898 - New York: Plume. Edited by Carl Zimmer.
  39. The Nonperformativity of Reconciliation: The Case of "Reasonable Accommodation" in Québec.Anna Carastathis - 2013 - In Pauline Wakeham & Jennifer Henderson (eds.), Reconciling Canada: Critical Perspectives on the Culture of Redress. University of Toronto Press. pp. 236-260.
    What does it mean when calls to reconciliation come from dominant social groups? Whom do these calls address? What effects do they have? I take up these questions through a case study of the public discourse on “reasonable accommodation” in Québec. When the Consultation Commission on Accommodation Practices Related to Cultural Differences concluded its tour of the regions and cities of Québec and, in the spring of 2008, the commissioners (philosopher Charles Taylor and sociologist Gérard Bouchard) issued their (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  44
    The variation of animals and plants under domestication.Charles Darwin - 1868 - Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press. Edited by Harriet Ritvo.
    The publication of Darwin's On the Origin of Species in 1859 ignited a public storm he neither wanted nor enjoyed. Having offered his book as a contribution to science, Darwin discovered to his dismay that it was received as an affront by many scientists and as a sacrilege by clergy and Christian citizens. To answer the criticism that his theory was a theory only, and a wild one at that, he published two volumes in 1868 to demonstrate that evolution was (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   184 citations  
  41.  15
    Peirce's God of Theory and Practice.Douglas R. Anderson - 1995 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 51 (1):167 - 178.
    In his "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of Goc" (1908), Charles Peirce argued for two dimensions of belief in God's reality. On the one side, he maintained that this belief would be useful for guiding the conduct of life; on the other side, he maintained that the belief could function as the first stage in a scientific inquiry. My suggestion in this paper is that we examine the last of Peirce's 1903 lectures on pragmatism at Harvard to see (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  85
    Hegel.Charles Taylor (ed.) - 1975 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is a major and comprehensive study of the philosophy of Hegel, his place in the history of ideas, and his continuing relevance and importance. Professor Taylor relates Hegel to the earlier history of philosophy and, more particularly, to the central intellectual and spiritual issues of his own time. He engages with Hegel sympathetically, on Hegel's own terms and, as the subject demands, in detail. This important book is now reissued with a fresh new cover.
  43. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form.Charles H. Kahn - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book proposes a new paradigm for the interpretation of Plato's early and middle dialogues. Rejecting the usual assumption of a distinct 'Socratic' period in the development of Plato's thought, this view regards the earlier works as deliberate preparation for the exposition of Plato's mature philosophy. Differences between the dialogues do not represent different stages in Plato's own thinking but rather different aspects and moments in the presentation of a new and unfamiliar view of reality. Once the fictional character of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  44. Constructibility and mathematical existence.Charles S. Chihara - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book is concerned with `the problem of existence in mathematics'. It develops a mathematical system in which there are no existence assertions but only assertions of the constructibility of certain sorts of things. It explores the philosophical implications of such an approach through an examination of the writings of Field, Burgess, Maddy, Kitcher, and others.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  45. “Ideal Theory” as Ideology.Charles W. Mills - 2005 - Hypatia 20 (3):165-184.
  46. Responsibility for self.Charles Taylor - 1976 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons. University of California Press. pp. 281--99.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  47. “Ideal Theory” as Ideology.Charles W. Mills - 2005 - Hypatia 20 (3):165-184.
  48.  22
    Drinking Rules! Byron and Baudelaire.Joshua Wilner - 1997 - Diacritics 27 (3):34-48.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Drinking Rules! Byron and BaudelaireJoshua Wilner (bio)This essay 1 takes up two nineteenth-century texts on the theme of intoxication in which the poetic word can no longer, if it ever could, stably figure itself as the metaphoric other of the drug, that is, as a legitimate means of imaginative transport, and in which the writer’s enthrallment by the transporting substance of words shows us its addictive and, one might (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Foucault on Freedom and Truth.Charles Taylor - 1984 - Political Theory 12 (2):152-183.
  50. Pragmatics.Charles Travis - 1997 - In Bob Hale, Crispin Wright & Alexander Miller (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 87--107.
1 — 50 / 996