Results for 'reverse Sobel sequences'

991 found
Order:
  1. Incomplete descriptions and (reverse) Sobel sequences.Mirja Annalena Holst - 2013 - Analysis 73 (1):26-32.
    A challenge for theories of incomplete descriptions is to capture the consistency of ‘Sobel sequences’ and to account for an asymmetry in the acceptability of utterances of Sobel sequences and ‘reverse Sobel sequences’. David Lewis’s theory of incomplete descriptions answers, unlike many other theories, the challenge from Sobel sequences, but it does not answer the challenge from reverse Sobel sequences. This article presents another asymmetry in the availability of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  74
    Lessons from Sobel sequences.Malte Willer - 2017 - Semantics and Pragmatics 10 (4):1-57.
    Folklore has it that Sobel sequences favor a variably strict analysis of conditionals over its plainly strict alternative. While recent discussions for or against the lore have focussed on Sobel sequences involving counterfactuals, this paper draws attention to the fact that indicative Sobel sequences are just as felicitous as are their counterfactual cousins. The fact, or so I shall argue here, disrupts the folklore: given minimal assumptions about the semantics and pragmatics of indicative conditionals, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  3.  38
    Varieties of Sobel sequences.Michela Ippolito - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (6):633-671.
    In this paper I provide a unified analysis of a number of pragmatic anomalies that have been discussed in the literature. The paper’s main goal is to account for Sobel sequences of conditionals and sequences of disjunctive sentences, but I will also propose that this analysis can be extended to sequences of sentences with superlatives. The starting point is the observation that, while all these sequences are felicitous in one order, they are infelicitous when the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  29
    Varieties of Sobel sequences.Michela Ippolito - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (6):633-671.
    In this paper I provide a unified analysis of a number of pragmatic anomalies that have been discussed in the literature. The paper’s main goal is to account for Sobel sequences of conditionals and sequences of disjunctive sentences, but I will also propose that this analysis can be extended to sequences of sentences with superlatives. The starting point is the observation that, while all these sequences are felicitous in one order, they are infelicitous when the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  12
    Varieties of Sobel sequences.Michela Ippolito - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (6):633-671.
    In this paper I provide a unified analysis of a number of pragmatic anomalies that have been discussed in the literature. The paper’s main goal is to account for Sobel sequences of conditionals and sequences of disjunctive sentences, but I will also propose that this analysis can be extended to sequences of sentences with superlatives. The starting point is the observation that, while all these sequences are felicitous in one order, they are infelicitous when the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  16
    Varieties of Sobel sequences.Michela Ippolito - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (6):633-671.
    In this paper I provide a unified analysis of a number of pragmatic anomalies that have been discussed in the literature. The paper’s main goal is to account for Sobel sequences of conditionals and sequences of disjunctive sentences, but I will also propose that this analysis can be extended to sequences of sentences with superlatives. The starting point is the observation that, while all these sequences are felicitous in one order, they are infelicitous when the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. Presuppositional Anaphora Is The Sobel Truth.Daniel Dohrn - 2017 - In Salvatore Pistoia-Reda & Filippo Domaneschi (eds.), Linguistic and Psycholinguistic Approaches on Implicatures and Presuppositions. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 199-238.
    Sobel sequences have had a huge impact on the discussion of counterfactuals. They can be composed of conditionals and mere descriptions. What is especially puzzling about them is that they are often felicitously uttered when their reversal is not. Up to now, there is no unified explanation. I examine two strategies. We might begin with conditionals and proceed to descriptions. Or we might begin with descriptions and proceed to conditionals. I argue for the latter variant and outline a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Heim Sequences and Why Most Unqualified ‘Would’-Counterfactuals Are Not True.Yael Loewenstein - 2021 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 99 (3):597-610.
    ABSTRACT The apparent consistency of Sobel sequences famously motivated David Lewis to defend a variably strict conditional semantics for counterfactuals. If Sophie had gone to the parade, she would have seen Pedro. If Sophie had gone to the parade and had been stuck behind someone tall, she would not have seen Pedro. But if the order of the counterfactuals in a Sobel sequence is reversed—in the example, if is asserted prior to —the second counterfactual asserted no longer (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  35
    On the Consistency and Reversibility of Certain Sequences of Counterfactual Assertions.Peter Klecha - 2022 - Mind 131 (521):1-33.
    This paper is about Sobel sequences, which are sequences of counterfactuals that supposedly display two interesting properties: first, they are consistent, as accounted for by the famous Lewis-Stalnaker analysis; but second, they are not consistent in the reverse order, which is not accounted for by Lewis-Stalnaker. I argue that there has been an empirical oversight in the literature on these sequences: there are consistent sequences, and there are irreversible sequences, but no sequence is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. On the Pragmatics of Counterfactuals.Sarah Moss - 2010 - Noûs 46 (3):561-586.
    Recently, von Fintel (2001) and Gillies (2007) have argued that certain sequences of counterfactuals, namely reverse Sobel sequences, should motivate us to abandon standard truth conditional theories of counterfactuals for dynamic semantic theories. I argue that we can give a pragmatic account of our judgments about counterfactuals without giving up the standard semantics. In particular, I introduce a pragmatic principle governing assertability, and I use this principle to explain a variety of subtle data concerning reverse (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  11. Conversation and conditionals.J. Robert G. Williams - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 138 (2):211 - 223.
    I outline and motivate a way of implementing a closest world theory of indicatives, appealing to Stalnaker's framework of open conversational possibilities. Stalnakerian conversational dynamics helps us resolve two outstanding puzzles for a such a theory of indicative conditionals. The first puzzle -- concerning so-called 'reverse Sobel sequences' -- can be resolved by conversation dynamics in a theoryneutral way: the explanation works as much for Lewisian counterfactuals as for the account of indicatives developed here. Resolving the second (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  12. Strict conditional accounts of counterfactuals.Cory Nichols - 2017 - Linguistics and Philosophy 40 (6):621-645.
    von Fintel and Gillies : 329–360, 2007) have proposed a dynamic strict conditional account of counterfactuals as an alternative to the standard variably strict account due to Stalnaker and Lewis. Von Fintel’s view is motivated largely by so-called reverse Sobel sequences, about which the standard view seems to make the wrong predictions. More recently Moss :561–586, 2012) has offered a pragmatic/epistemic explanation that purports to explain the data without requiring abandonment of the standard view. So far the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13. A Uniform Theory of Conditionals.William B. Starr - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (6):1019-1064.
    A uniform theory of conditionals is one which compositionally captures the behavior of both indicative and subjunctive conditionals without positing ambiguities. This paper raises new problems for the closest thing to a uniform analysis in the literature (Stalnaker, Philosophia, 5, 269–286 (1975)) and develops a new theory which solves them. I also show that this new analysis provides an improved treatment of three phenomena (the import-export equivalence, reverse Sobel-sequences and disjunctive antecedents). While these results concern central issues (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  14. The case of the missing ‘If’: Accessibility relations in Stalnaker’s theory of conditionals.Matthew Mandelkern - forthcoming - Semantics and Pragmatics.
    A part of Stalnaker (1968)’s influential theory of conditionals has been neglected, namely the role for an accessibility relation between worlds. I argue that the accessibility relation does not play the role intended for it in the theory as stated, and propose a minimal revision which solves the problem, and brings the theory in line with the formulation in Stalnaker & Thomason 1970.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  37
    A logic for the natural language conditional.Monique Whitaker - 2018 - South African Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):261-283.
    Ordinary speakers intuitively assign truth-values to conditional utterances in everyday conversation, but, despite the general ease with which this occurs, it is notoriously difficult to give an account of the implicit logic that is followed in making these truth-value assignments. I propose a twofold logic of the conditional – a relatively simple “factual” logic for conditionals interpreted with regard to what is actually the case, largely following the logic of the material conditional; combined with a variably strict possible-worlds counterfactual logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Counterfactual Discourse in Context.Karen S. Lewis - 2018 - Noûs 52 (3):481-507.
    The classic Lewis-Stalnaker semantics for counterfactuals captures that Sobel sequences are consistent sequences, for example: a.If Sophie had gone to the parade, she would have seen Pedro dance. b.But if Sophie had gone to the parade and been stuck behind someone tall, she would not have seen Pedro dance. But reverse a sequence like this one and it no longer sounds so good, which is surprising on the classic semantics. This observation motivated Kai von Fintel and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  17.  34
    Sequences of real functions on [0, 1] in constructive reverse mathematics.Hannes Diener & Iris Loeb - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (1):50-61.
    We give an overview of the role of equicontinuity of sequences of real-valued functions on [0,1] and related notions in classical mathematics, intuitionistic mathematics, Bishop’s constructive mathematics, and Russian recursive mathematics. We then study the logical strength of theorems concerning these notions within the programme of Constructive Reverse Mathematics. It appears that many of these theorems, like a version of Ascoli’s Lemma, are equivalent to fan-theoretic principles.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  18.  25
    Derived sequences and reverse mathematics.Jeffry L. Hirst - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):447-453.
    One of the earliest applications of transfinite numbers is in the construction of derived sequences by Cantor [2]. In [6], the existence of derived sequences for countable closed sets is proved in ATR0. This existence theorem is an intermediate step in a proof that a statement concerning topological comparability is equivalent to ATR0. In actuality, the full strength of ATR0 is used in proving the existence theorem. To show this, we will derive a statement known to be equivalent (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  35
    Implicit Transfer of Reversed Temporal Structure in Visuomotor Sequence Learning.Kanji Tanaka & Katsumi Watanabe - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (3):565-579.
    Some spatio-temporal structures are easier to transfer implicitly in sequential learning. In this study, we investigated whether the consistent reversal of triads of learned components would support the implicit transfer of their temporal structure in visuomotor sequence learning. A triad comprised three sequential button presses ([1][2][3]) and seven consecutive triads comprised a sequence. Participants learned sequences by trial and error, until they could complete it 20 times without error. Then, they learned another sequence, in which each triad was reversed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  16
    Cancer progression as a sequence of atavistic reversions.Charles H. Lineweaver, Kimberly J. Bussey, Anneke C. Blackburn & Paul C. W. Davies - 2021 - Bioessays 43 (7):2000305.
    It has long been recognized that cancer onset and progression represent a type of reversion to an ancestral quasi‐unicellular phenotype. This general concept has been refined into the atavistic model of cancer that attempts to provide a quantitative analysis and testable predictions based on genomic data. Over the past decade, support for the multicellular‐to‐unicellular reversion predicted by the atavism model has come from phylostratigraphy. Here, we propose that cancer onset and progression involve more than a one‐off multicellular‐to‐unicellular reversion, and are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  20
    The role of reversal frequency in learning noisy second order conditional sequences.Thomas Pronk & Ingmar Visser - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (2):627-635.
    The hallmark of implicit learning is that complex knowledge can be acquired unconsciously. The second order conditionals of Reed and Johnson were developed to be complex, and they are popular materials for implicit learning research. Recently, it was demonstrated that in a sequence made noisy , shared features of the SOCs may be learned explicitly . What are these shared features? We hypothesized that low reversal frequency may play a significant role. We have varied reversal frequency, and discovered that reversal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  10
    Time reversal operations, representations of the Lorentz group, and the direction of time.Frank Arntzenius - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (1):31-43.
    A theory is usually said to be time reversible if whenever a sequence of states S 1, S 2, S 3 is possible according to that theory, then the reverse sequence of time reversed states S 3 T, S 2 T, S 1 T is also possible according to that theory; i.e., one normally not only inverts the sequence of states, but also operates on the states with a time reversal operator T. David Albert and Paul Horwich have suggested (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23.  74
    Time reversal operations, representations of the Lorentz group, and the direction of time.Frank Arntzenius - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (1):31-43.
    A theory is usually said to be time reversible if whenever a sequence of states S 1 , S 2 , S 3 is possible according to that theory, then the reverse sequence of time reversed states S 3 T , S 2 T , S 1 T is also possible according to that theory; i.e., one normally not only inverts the sequence of states, but also operates on the states with a time reversal operator T . David Albert (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24.  69
    Infinite sequences: Finitist consequence.Martin C. Cooke - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (4):591-599.
    A simultaneous collision that produces paradoxical indeterminism (involving N0 hypothetical particles in a classical three-dimensional Euclidean space) is described in Section 2. By showing that a similar paradox occurs with long-range forces between hypothetical particles, in Section 3, the underlying cause is seen to be that collections of such objects are assumed to have no intrinsic ordering. The resolution of allowing only finite numbers of particles is defended (as being the least ad hoc) by looking at both -sequences (in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  31
    Reverse correlation in neurophysiology.Dario Ringach & Robert Shapley - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (2):147-166.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  24
    Reverse mathematics, well-quasi-orders, and Noetherian spaces.Emanuele Frittaion, Matthew Hendtlass, Alberto Marcone, Paul Shafer & Jeroen Van der Meeren - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (3):431-459.
    A quasi-order Q induces two natural quasi-orders on $${\mathcal{P}(Q)}$$, but if Q is a well-quasi-order, then these quasi-orders need not necessarily be well-quasi-orders. Nevertheless, Goubault-Larrecq (Proceedings of the 22nd Annual IEEE Symposium 4 on Logic in Computer Science (LICS’07), pp. 453–462, 2007) showed that moving from a well-quasi-order Q to the quasi-orders on $${\mathcal{P}(Q)}$$ preserves well-quasi-orderedness in a topological sense. Specifically, Goubault-Larrecq proved that the upper topologies of the induced quasi-orders on $${\mathcal{P}(Q)}$$ are Noetherian, which means that they contain no (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  10
    Constructing sequences one step at a time.Henry Towsner - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 20 (3):2050017.
    We propose a new method for constructing Turing ideals satisfying principles of reverse mathematics below the Chain–Antichain (CAC) Principle. Using this method, we are able to prove several new separations in the presence of Weak König’s Lemma (WKL), including showing that CAC+WKL does not imply the thin set theorem for pairs, and that the principle “the product of well-quasi-orders is a well-quasi-order” is strictly between CAC and the Ascending/Descending Sequences principle, even in the presence of WKL.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  14
    Sequencing the salmon genome: A deliberative public engagement.David M. Secko, Michael Burgess & Kieran O'Doherty - 2010 - Genomics, Society and Policy 6 (1):1-18.
    Salmon genomics is an emerging field that represents a convergence between socially important scientific innovation and a politically volatile topic of significant interest to the public. These factors provide a strong rationale for public input. This report describes such input from a public engagement event based on the principles of deliberative democracy. The event involved a random, demographically stratified sample of 25 British Columbians (Canada). While some participants opposed sequencing the salmon genome on principle, on the whole participants responded favourably, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. The Design Inference: Eliminating Chance through Small Probabilities.Jordan Howard Sobel - 2003 - Mind 112 (447):521-525.
  30.  15
    Predicting Outcomes in a Sequence of Binary Events: Belief Updating and Gambler's Fallacy Reasoning.Kariyushi Rao & Reid Hastie - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (1):e13211.
    Beliefs like the Gambler's Fallacy and the Hot Hand have interested cognitive scientists, economists, and philosophers for centuries. We propose that these judgment patterns arise from the observer's mental models of the sequence-generating mechanism, moderated by the strength of belief in an a priori base rate. In six behavioral experiments, participants observed one of three mechanisms generating sequences of eight binary events: a random mechanical device, an intentional goal-directed actor, and a financial market. We systematically manipulated participants’ beliefs about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  48
    Reversals of fortune: path dependency, problem solving, and temporal cases. [REVIEW]Jeffrey Haydu - 2010 - Theory and Society 39 (1):25-48.
    Historical reversals highlight a basic methodological problem: is it possible to treat two successive periods both as independent cases to compare for causal analysis and as parts of a single historical sequence? I argue that one strategy for doing so, using models of path dependency, imposes serious limits on explanation. An alternative model which treats successive periods as contrasting solutions for recurrent problems offers two advantages. First, it more effectively combines analytical comparisons of different periods with narratives of causal (...) spanning two or more periods. Second, it better integrates scholarly accounts of historical reversals with actors’ own narratives of the past. (shrink)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  40
    Algorithmic randomness, reverse mathematics, and the dominated convergence theorem.Jeremy Avigad, Edward T. Dean & Jason Rute - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1854-1864.
    We analyze the pointwise convergence of a sequence of computable elements of L1 in terms of algorithmic randomness. We consider two ways of expressing the dominated convergence theorem and show that, over the base theory RCA0, each is equivalent to the assertion that every Gδ subset of Cantor space with positive measure has an element. This last statement is, in turn, equivalent to weak weak Königʼs lemma relativized to the Turing jump of any set. It is also equivalent to the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Parfit's Case Against Subjectivism.David Sobel - 2011 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume 6: Volume 6. Oxford University Press.
    I argue that Parfit's On What Matters does not make a compelling case against subjective accounts of reasons for action.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34. Self-Ownership and the Conflation Problem.David Sobel - forthcoming - In Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics.
    Libertarian self-ownership views in the tradition of Locke, Nozick, and the left-libertarians have supposed that we enjoy very powerful deontological protections against infringing upon our property. Such a conception makes sense when we are focused on property that is very important to its owner, such as a person’s kidney. However, this stringency of our property rights is harder to credit when we consider more trivial infringements such as very mildly toxic pollution or trivial risks such having planes fly overhead. Maintaining (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. Maxwell's Paradox: The Metaphysics of Classical Electrodynamics and its Time Reversal Invariance.Valia Allori - 2015 - Analytica: an electronic, open-access journal for philosophy of science 1:1-19.
    In this paper, I argue that the recent discussion on the time - reversal invariance of classical electrodynamics (see (Albert 2000: ch.1), (Arntzenius 2004), (Earman 2002), (Malament 2004),(Horwich 1987: ch.3)) can be best understood assuming that the disagreement among the various authors is actually a disagreement about the metaphysics of classical electrodynamics. If so, the controversy will not be resolved until we have established which alternative is the most natural. It turns out that we have a paradox, namely that the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  33
    Evidence of systematic expressed sequence tag image clone cross-hybridization on cdna microarrays.Clark Glymour - unknown
    We present evidence of a potentially serious source of error intrinsic to all spotted cDNA microarrays that use IMAGE clones of expressed sequence tags (ESTs). We found that a high proportion of these EST sequences contain 5V-end poly(dT) sequences that are remnants from the oligo(dT)-primed reverse transcription of polyadenylated mRNA templates used to generate EST cDNA for sequence clone libraries. Analysis of expression data from two single-dye cDNA microarray experiments showed that ESTs whose sequences contain repeats (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration.David Sobel - 1998 - Economics and Philosophy 14 (2):249.
    The proposal I offer attempts to remedy the inadequacies of exclusive focus on well-being for moral purposes. The proposal is this: We should allow the agent to decide for herself where she wants to throw the weight that is her due in moral reflection, with the proviso that she understands the way that her weight will be aggregated with others in reaching a moral outcome. I will call this the "autonomy principle." The autonomy principle, I claim, provides the consequentialist's best (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  38.  34
    Evidence of systematic expressed sequence tag IMAGE clone cross-hybridization on cDNA microarrays.Larry Wasserman - unknown
    We present evidence of a potentially serious source of error intrinsic to all spotted cDNA microarrays that use IMAGE clones of expressed sequence tags (ESTs). We found that a high proportion of these EST sequences contain 5V-end poly(dT) sequences that are remnants from the oligo(dT)-primed reverse transcription of polyadenylated mRNA templates used to generate EST cDNA for sequence clone libraries. Analysis of expression data from two single-dye cDNA microarray experiments showed that ESTs whose sequences contain repeats (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  48
    Unraveling the Kāvyaprakāśa: Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa’s idiosyncratic sequence of topics in the Candrāloka.David Mellins - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (3):227-251.
    In his twelfth century alaṃkāraśāstra, the Candrāloka, Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa reverses the sequence of topics found in Mammaṭa’s Kāvyapr-akāśa, an earlier and immensely popular work. With such a structural revisionism, Jayadeva asserts the autonomy of his own work and puts forth an ambitious critique of earlier approaches to literary analysis. Jayadeva investigates the technical and aesthetic components of poetry in the first part of the Candrāloka, prior to his formal semantic investigations in the latter half of the text, thus suggesting that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  13
    Unraveling the Kāvyaprakāśa: Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa’s idiosyncratic sequence of topics in the Candrāloka.David Mellins - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (3):227-251.
    In his twelfth century alaṃkāraśāstra, the Candrāloka, Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa reverses the sequence of topics found in Mammaṭa’s Kāvyapr-akāśa, an earlier and immensely popular work. With such a structural revisionism, Jayadeva asserts the autonomy of his own work and puts forth an ambitious critique of earlier approaches to literary analysis. Jayadeva investigates the technical and aesthetic components of poetry in the first part of the Candrāloka, prior to his formal semantic investigations in the latter half of the text, thus suggesting that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  35
    Subjectivism and Blame.David Sobel - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (sup1):149-170.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  42. Pleasure as a Mental State.David Sobel - 1999 - Utilitas 11 (2):230.
    Shelly Kagan and Leonard Katz have offered versions of hedonism that aspire to occupy a middle position between the view that pleasure is a unitary sensation and the view that pleasure is, as Sidgwick put it, desirable consciousness. Thus they hope to offer a hedonistic account of well-being that does not mistakenly suppose that pleasure is a special kind of tingle, yet to offer a sharp alternative to desire-based accounts. I argue that they have not identified a coherent middle position.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43. Parfit's Case against Subjectivism.David Sobel - 2011 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume 6: Volume 6. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. Full information theories of the good.David Sobel - 1994 - In Peter Singer (ed.), Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 104--784.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  5
    Slicing the truth: on the computable and reverse mathematics of combinatorial principles.Denis Roman Hirschfeldt - 2015 - [Hackensack,] NJ: World Scientific. Edited by C.-T. Chong.
    1. Setting off: An introduction. 1.1. A measure of motivation. 1.2. Computable mathematics. 1.3. Reverse mathematics. 1.4. An overview. 1.5. Further reading -- 2. Gathering our tools: Basic concepts and notation. 2.1. Computability theory. 2.2. Computability theoretic reductions. 2.3. Forcing -- 3. Finding our path: Konig's lemma and computability. 3.1. II[symbol] classes, basis theorems, and PA degrees. 3.2. Versions of Konig's lemma -- 4. Gauging our strength: Reverse mathematics. 4.1. RCA[symbol]. 4.2. Working in RCA[symbol]. 4.3. ACA[symbol]. 4.4. WKL[symbol]. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  10
    What is effective transfinite recursion in reverse mathematics?Anton Freund - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (4):479-483.
    In the context of reverse mathematics, effective transfinite recursion refers to a principle that allows us to construct sequences of sets by recursion along arbitrary well orders, provided that each set is ‐definable relative to the previous stages of the recursion. It is known that this principle is provable in. In the present note, we argue that a common formulation of effective transfinite recursion is too restrictive. We then propose a more liberal formulation, which appears very natural and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  59
    Reply to Robertson.David Sobel - 2003 - Philosophical Papers 32 (2):185-191.
    Philosophical Papers Vol.32(2) 2003: 185-191.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  19
    (Extra)Ordinary Equivalences with the Ascending/Descending Sequence Principle.Marta Fiori-Carones, Alberto Marcone, Paul Shafer & Giovanni Soldà - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):262-307.
    We analyze the axiomatic strength of the following theorem due to Rival and Sands [28] in the style of reverse mathematics. Every infinite partial order P of finite width contains an infinite chain C such that every element of P is either comparable with no element of C or with infinitely many elements of C. Our main results are the following. The Rival–Sands theorem for infinite partial orders of arbitrary finite width is equivalent to $\mathsf {I}\Sigma ^0_{2} + \mathsf (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  17
    Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 3.David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne & Steven Wall (eds.) - 2017 - Oxford University Press.
    This is the third volume of Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy. The series aims to publish some of the best contemporary work in the vibrant field of political philosophy and its closely related subfields, including jurisprudence, normative economics, political theory in political science departments, and just war theory.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  61
    Michael J. Zimmerman, The Concept of Moral Obligation:The Concept of Moral Obligation.David Sobel - 1999 - Ethics 109 (2):468-470.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991