Results for 'responsiveness to reasons'

999 found
Order:
  1.  23
    Reincarnation and Karma.Paul Reasoner - 2010 - In Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper & Philip L. Quinn (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 639–647.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Reincarnation/Rebirth Karma Causality Problem of Evil Determinism, Freedom, and Moral Responsibility Karma and Release Transfer of Merit Recent Developments Works cited.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. From Responsibility to Reason-Giving Explainable Artificial Intelligence.Kevin Baum, Susanne Mantel, Timo Speith & Eva Schmidt - 2022 - Philosophy and Technology 35 (1):1-30.
    We argue that explainable artificial intelligence (XAI), specifically reason-giving XAI, often constitutes the most suitable way of ensuring that someone can properly be held responsible for decisions that are based on the outputs of artificial intelligent (AI) systems. We first show that, to close moral responsibility gaps (Matthias 2004), often a human in the loop is needed who is directly responsible for particular AI-supported decisions. Second, we appeal to the epistemic condition on moral responsibility to argue that, in order to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3. Situations and Responsiveness to Reasons.Carolina Sartorio - 2017 - Noûs 52 (4):796-807.
    Some classical studies in social psychology suggest that we are more sensitive to situational factors, and less responsive to reasons, than we normally recognize we are. In recent years, moral responsibility theorists have examined the question whether those studies represent a serious threat to our moral responsibility. A common response to the “situationist threat” has been to defend the reasons-responsiveness of ordinary human agents by appeal to a theory of reasons-responsiveness that appeals to patterns of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. A Place for Philosophers in Applied Ethics and the Role of Moral Reasoning in Moral Imagination: A Response to Richard Rorty.Patricia H. Werhane - 2006 - Business Ethics Quarterly 16 (3):401-408.
    This article presents a response to Richard Rorty's paper "Is Philosophy Relevant to Business Ethics?" The author questions Rorty's views on the depreciation of the role of philosophy in applied ethics, and outlines four reasons why philosophy retains its relevance. The author addresses the role of moral reasoning in the development of the moral imagination. The author also concludes that humans have the means necessary to make moral progress and are capable of moral reasoning, and need only to develop (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  5. What shall we make of the human brain?Responses to Niels Gregersen - 1999 - Zygon 34:202.
  6.  32
    Response to Gert on Practical Reason.Alan H. Goldman - 2012 - The Journal of Ethics 16 (1):35-37.
    This is a response to Joshua Gert’s criticisms of my book Reasons from Within and defense of his own contrasting position.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  80
    A Response to the Argument From the Reasonableness of Nonbelief.Robert T. Lehe - 2004 - Faith and Philosophy 21 (2):159-174.
    According to J. L. Schellenberg’s argument from the reasonableness of nonbelief, the fact that many people inculpably fail to find sufficient evidence for the existence of God constitutes evidence for atheism. Schellenberg argues that since a loving God would not withhold the benefits of belief, the lack of evidence for God’s existence is incompatible with divine love. I argue that Schellenberg has not successfully defended his argument’s two controversial premises, that God’s love is incompatible with his allowing some to remain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  8.  13
    Who detects and why: how do individual differences in cognitive characteristics underpin different types of responses to reasoning tasks?Nikola Erceg, Zvonimir Galić, Andreja Bubić & Dino Jelić - 2023 - Thinking and Reasoning 29 (4):594-642.
    One of the most famous problems in the decision-making literature is the “bat and a ball” problem from the cognitive reflection test (CRT; Frederick, 2005). The problem goes as follows: „A bat and...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Setting priorities fairly in response to Covid-19: identifying overlapping consensus and reasonable disagreement.David Wasserman, Govind Persad & Joseph Millum - 2020 - Journal of Law and the Biosciences 1 (1):doi:10.1093/jlb/lsaa044.
    Proposals for allocating scarce lifesaving resources in the face of the Covid-19 pandemic have aligned in some ways and conflicted in others. This paper attempts a kind of priority setting in addressing these conflicts. In the first part, we identify points on which we do not believe that reasonable people should differ—even if they do. These are (i) the inadequacy of traditional clinical ethics to address priority-setting in a pandemic; (ii) the relevance of saving lives; (iii) the flaws of first-come, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  54
    Moral rationalism and psychopathy: Affective responses to reason.Allen Coates - 2017 - Philosophical Psychology 30 (7):855-877.
    Evidence suggests that psychopaths’ notoriously immoral behavior is due to affective rather than rational deficits. This evidence could be taken to show that, contrary to moral rationalism, moral norms are not norms of reason. Rationalists could reply either that psychopaths’ behavior is in fact primarily due to rational deficits or that affects are involved in responding to rational norms. Drawing on the work of Antonio Damasio and colleagues, I argue the latter is the better defense of moral rationalism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  36
    Consumers’ Responses to Public Figures’ Transgression: Moral Reasoning Strategies and Implications for Endorsed Brands.Joon Sung Lee & Dae Hee Kwak - 2016 - Journal of Business Ethics 137 (1):101-113.
    Public figures’ transgressions attract considerable media attention and public interest. However, little is understood about the impact of celebrity endorsers’ transgressions on associated brands. Drawing on research on moral reasoning, we posit that consumers are not always motivated to separate judgments of performance from judgments of morality or simply excuse a wrongdoer. We propose that consumers also engage in moral coupling, a distinct moral reasoning process which allows consumers to integrate judgments of performance and judgments of morality. In three studies, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12. Response to “A Priority, Reason, and Induction in Hume”.Peter Millican - unknown
    Over the last three years Hume’s use of the term “a priori” has suddenly become very topical. Three discussions, by Stephen Buckle, myself, and Houston Smit, all focusing on Hume’s argument concerning induction in Section IV of the Enquiry, have independently picked up on this question, which seems previously to have gone almost unnoticed.1 That there is an issue here can be seen by examining what Hume says when considering the foundation of our inferences concerning matter of fact; why, for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  29
    Response to Critics: What is the Human Being? Kant’s Architectonic of Pure Reason and its Limitations.Lea Ypi - 2023 - Kantian Review 28 (3):477-485.
  14. Response to Kachi, Yukio review of reason and spontaneity.Ac Graham - 1990 - Philosophy East and West 40 (3):399-399.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  32
    Response to Yukio Kachi's review of "reason and spontaneity".Review author[S.]: A. C. Graham - 1990 - Philosophy East and West 40 (3):399.
  16.  21
    Response to Yukio Kachi's Review of "Reason and Spontaneity".A. C. Graham - 1990 - Philosophy East and West 40 (3):399.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  39
    Response to Tzourio-Mazoyer and Zago: yes, there is a neural dissociation between language and reasoning.Martin M. Monti, Lawrence M. Parsons & Daniel N. Osherson - 2012 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (10):495-496.
  18.  11
    Response to James Swindal and Bill Martin on Reason, History, and Politics.David Ingram - 2000 - Human Studies 23 (2):203-210.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  25
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “Analogical Reasoning in Handling Emerging Technologies: The Case of Umbilical Cord Blood Biobanking”: Analogy is Like Air—Invisible and Indispensable.Bjørn Hofmann, Søren Holm & Jan Helge Solbakk - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (6):W13-W14.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  31
    Response to Andrew Cutrofello's comments on reason, history, and politics by David Ingram.David Ingram - 1998 - Social Epistemology 12 (2):127 – 133.
  21.  9
    Response to Andrew Cutrofello's comments on Reason, History, and Politics by David Ingram.David Ingram - 1998 - Social Epistemology 12 (2):127-133.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Blame and responsiveness to moral reasons: Are psychopaths blameworthy?Matthew Talbert - 2008 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 89 (4):516-535.
    Abstract: Many philosophers believe that people who are not capable of grasping the significance of moral considerations are not open to moral blame when they fail to respond appropriately to these considerations. I contend, however, that some morally blind, or 'psychopathic,' agents are proper targets for moral blame, at least on some occasions. I argue that moral blame is a response to the normative commitments and attitudes of a wrongdoer and that the actions of morally blind agents can express the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  23.  74
    Reasons for worship: A response to Bayne and Nagasawa.Benjamin D. Crowe - 2007 - Religious Studies 43 (4):465-474.
    Worship is a topic that is rarely considered by philosophers of religion. In a recent paper, Tim Bayne and Yujin Nagasawa challenge this trend by offering an analysis of worship and by considering some difficulties attendant on the claim that worship is obligatory. I argue that their case for there being these difficulties is insufficiently supported. I offer two reasons that a theist might provide for the claim that worship is obligatory: (1) a divine command, and (2) the demands (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  10
    Response to "ordinary reasonable care is not the minimum for engineers" (M. Davis).Professor Michael S. Pritchard - 2001 - Science and Engineering Ethics 7 (2):291-297.
  25.  31
    Response to "ordinary reasonable care is not the minimum for engineers" (m. davis).Michael S. Pritchard - 2001 - Science and Engineering Ethics 7 (2):291-297.
  26.  14
    A Response to the Open Peer Commentaries on “Young People's Experiences of Participation in Clinical Trials: Reasons for Taking Part”.Malou Luchtenberg, Els Maeckelberghe, Louise Locock, Lesley Powell & A. A. Eduard Verhagen - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (2):10-12.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. The reason why: Response to Crane.David Papineau - 1991 - Analysis 51 (1):37-40.
  28.  56
    Response to Claire Katz’s Review of Levinas and Education: At the Intersection of Faith and Reason.Denise Egéa-Kuehne - 2009 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 28 (4):383-386.
  29. A Response to Some Conceptual and Scientific Threats to Compatibilist Free Will.Robyn Repko Waller - unknown
    The aim of this dissertation is to respond to a collection of conceptual and scientific threats to compatibilist accounts of free will, particularly reasons-responsive views. Compatibilists hold that free will is compatible with the truth of determinism. Some compatibilists also claim that some actual agent at least sometimes acts freely, where it is true that she acts freely in virtue of her satisfying a specific set of control and epistemic conditions. These conditions often include the possession of certain capacities, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  18
    Response to “Dubious Premises— Evil Conclusions: Moral Reasoning at the Nuremberg Trials” by Edmund D. Pellegrino and David C. Thomasma (CQ Vol 9, No 2). [REVIEW]Michael L. Gross - 2001 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 10 (1):99-102.
    Because we are often nagged by the thought that we might not have behaved any differently than those good citizens whose respect for the law and fear of punishment led them to support the Nazi regime, we are fascinated with the behavior of ordinary Germans. Careful to first strip away the pathological explanations of German behavior, Pellegrino and Thomasma ask simply whether ordinary Germans could have reasoned and, by implication, acted differently. Although their affirmative answer is consistent with the activism (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  16
    Love and Reason: Response to McWilliams.Eva Brann - 1987 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 54.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  76
    Response to Inna Semetsky’s Review of Being Human: Semiosis and the Myth of Reason. [REVIEW]Andrew Stables - 2013 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 33 (2):223-225.
  33.  15
    Rights and Reasons: A Response to Harel.Andrew Halpin - 1998 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (3):485-495.
    This article considers a recent attempt by Alon Harel ((1997) 17 OJLS 101) to shed light on the nature of rights by examining the way derivative rights are recognized as instances of more fundamental rights. It criticizes the way Harel seeks to make a distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic reasons for rights, and so to establish a distinctive operation of practical reasoning for rights. The rationales linked to particular rights, and stated more generally within competing rights theories, are considered; (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  36
    Kant’s Response to the Principle of Sufficient Reason.Amanda Hicks - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 359-370.
    For Kant one of the goals of any critique of pure reason is to answer the question, how are a priori synthetic propositions possible? Because rationalists such as Eberhard and Wolff took the principle of sufficient reason (hereafter, the PSR) as the principle of all a priori synthetic judgments, understanding both the various formulations of this principle and arguments in favor of its use as an axiom in metaphysical reasoning provides an interesting back door to understanding The Critique of Pure (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Deliberation, Reason, and Indigestion: Response to Daniel Dombrowski's Rawls and Religion: The Case for Political Liberalism.Zandra Wagoner - 2010 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 31 (3):179-195.
    Democracy requires a rather large tolerance for confusion and a secret relish for dissent. I am delighted to respond to Daniel Dombrowski’s book Rawls and Religion. Dombrowski and I share a number of what he would call comprehensive doctrine, such as the ethical treatment of animals, the relational worldview of process thought, and the idiosyncratic love of pacifism. So, immediately I was drawn in and claimed Dombrowski as a kindred spirit. With so many commonalities, including an interest in political philosophy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Exchanging Reasons: responses to critics.Lilian Bermejo Luque - 2011 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 26 (3):329-346.
    Ofrezco respuestas a lo que considero son los aspectos más destacados de las críticas de John Biro, James Freeman, David Hitchcock, Robert Pinto, Harvey Siegel y Luis Vega al modelo normativo para la argumentación que he desarrollado en Giving Reasons. Cada respuesta se articula en torno a una cuestión principal, i.e., la distinción entre normatividad constitutiva y regulativa dentro de los modelos de la Teoría de la Argumentación, la evaluación semántica de la argumentación, el concepto de justificación, las diferencias (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  56
    Kant’s Response to Hume’s Critique of Pure Reason.Karin de Boer - 2019 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 101 (3):376-406.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie Jahrgang: 101 Heft: 3 Seiten: 376-406.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  6
    A response to Innocent Enweh on Interpretative Rehabilitation of Afrocommunalism.Anthony Chinaemerem Ajah & Martin Ferdinand Asiegbu - 2023 - Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 12 (3):29-40.
    In a 2020 article published in volume 9, number 1 of [Filosofia Theoretica]_, _Martin F. Asiegbu and Anthony Chinaemerem Ajah questioned the continued relevance of Afro-communalism. They argued that nothing about communalism makes it African. They also demonstrated how the brand of communalism presented as ‘African’, is too reductive, emphasizes conformism and therefore is against the individual and counter-productive for entire societies in Africa. For the above reasons, they summed that communalism with ‘Afro-’ is irrelevant and needs to end. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  90
    Reasons of Love: Response to Wolf.Cheshire Calhoun - 2016 - Foundations of Science 21 (2):275-277.
    According to Wolf’s fitting fulfillment view, meaningfulness depends on the person’s subjective attraction to an activity being grounded in ‘reasons of love’ that concern the objective value of those activities. In this short comment, I argue that ‘reasons of love’—and thus reasons for regarding as meaningful—are not limited to those having to do with the objective value of activities and relationships, but include also what I call ‘reasons for the initiated’ and ‘reasons for me’.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  30
    Response to James Swindal and bill Martin on reason, history, and politics. [REVIEW]David Ingram - 2000 - Human Studies 23 (2):203-210.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Goodness and reasons: A response to Stratton-lake.Roger Crisp - 2009 - Mind 118 (472):1095-1099.
    This article is a response to some of Philip Stratton-Lake’s criticisms of an earlier paper of mine in this journal, on the so-called ‘buck-passing’ account of goodness. Some elucidation is offered of the ‘wrong kind of reasons’ problem and of T. M. Scanlon’s view, and the question is raised of the role of goodness in the view outlined by Stratton-Lake.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  46
    Reasons for worship: a response to Bayne and Nagasawa: BENJAMIN D. CROWE.Benjamin D. Crowe - 2007 - Religious Studies 43 (4):465-474.
    Worship is a topic that is rarely considered by philosophers of religion. In a recent paper, Tim Bayne and Yujin Nagasawa challenge this trend by offering an analysis of worship and by considering some difficulties attendant on the claim that worship is obligatory. I argue that their case for there being these difficulties is insufficiently supported. I offer two reasons that a theist might provide for the claim that worship is obligatory: a divine command, and the demands of justice (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43.  62
    Faith and Reason: A Response to Duncan Pritchard.Roberto di Ceglie - 2017 - Philosophy 92 (2):231-247.
    In a recent essay Duncan Pritchard argues that there is no fundamental epistemological distinction between religious belief and ordinary or non-religious belief. Both of them – so he maintains in the footsteps of Wittgenstein's On certainty – are ultimately grounded on a-rational commitments, namely, commitments unresponsive to rational criteria. I argue that, while this view can be justified theologically, it cannot be advanced philosophically as Pritchard assumes.I offer an account of Aquinas's reflection on faith and reason to show that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  21
    Belief in fake news, responsiveness to cognitive conflict, and analytic reasoning engagement.Michael V. Bronstein, Gordon Pennycook, Lydia Buonomano & Tyrone D. Cannon - 2021 - Thinking and Reasoning 27 (4):510-535.
    For decades, technologies that ease information sharing (e.g., the wireless telegraph; Mckernon, 1925) have inspired concerns about the proliferation of misinformation. Today, these worries often c...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  60
    Responsibility for Reason-Giving: The Case of Individual Tainted Reasoning in Systemic Corruption.Emanuela Ceva & Lubomira Radoilska - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (4):789-809.
    The paper articulates a new understanding of individual responsibility focused on exercises of agency in reason-giving rather than intentional actions or attitudes towards others. Looking at how agents make sense of their actions, we identify a distinctive but underexplored space for assessing individual responsibility within collective actions. As a case in point, we concentrate on reason-giving for one's own involvement in systemic corruption. We characterize systemic corruption in terms of its public ‘unavowability’ and focus on the redescriptions to which corrupt (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Exploring the Intersection of Rationality, Reality, and Theory of Mind in AI Reasoning: An Analysis of GPT-4's Responses to Paradoxes and ToM Tests.Lucas Freund - manuscript
    This paper investigates the responses of GPT-4, a state-of-the-art AI language model, to ten prominent philosophical paradoxes, and evaluates its capacity to reason and make decisions in complex and uncertain situations. In addition to analyzing GPT-4's solutions to the paradoxes, this paper assesses the model's Theory of Mind (ToM) capabilities by testing its understanding of mental states, intentions, and beliefs in scenarios ranging from classic ToM tests to complex, real-world simulations. Through these tests, we gain insight into AI's potential for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  39
    Reasons for anger: A response to Narayan and von Hirsch's provocation theory.Jeremy Horder - 1996 - Criminal Justice Ethics 15 (2):63-69.
  48. Moral Virtues and Responsiveness for Reasons.Garrett Cullity - 2017 - In Stewart Braun & Noell Birondo (eds.), Virtue's Reasons: New Essays on Virtue, Character, and Reasons. New York: Routledge. pp. 11-31.
    Moral discourse contains judgements of two prominent kinds. It contains deontic judgements about rightness and wrongness, obligation and duty, and what a person ought to do. As I understand them, these deontic judgements are normative: they express conclusions about the bearing of normative reasons on the actions and other responses that are available to us. And it contains evaluative judgements about goodness and badness. Prominent among these are the judgements that evaluate the quality of our responsiveness to morally (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  89
    Externalist responses to skepticism.Michael Bergmann - 2008 - In John Greco (ed.), The Oxford handbook of skepticism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 504-32.
    In this paper I will be setting aside contextualists and closure-deniers and focusing solely on neo-Moorean versions of externalist responses to skepticism. I will be focusing on two prominent theses about externalist responses to skepticism, one positive and one negative. The positive thesis announces an alleged virtue of externalism: that externalism alone avoids skepticism. The negative thesis identifies an alleged defect of externalism: that externalism implausibly avoids skepticism. I will be critical of both theses, though I will try to uncover (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  50. An alternative account of epistemic reasons for action: In response to Booth.Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2008 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 76 (1):191-198.
    In a recent contribution to Grazer Philosophische Studien, Booth argues that for S to have an epistemic reason to ψ means that if S ψ's then he will have more true beliefs and less false beliefs than if he does not ψ. After strengthening this external account in response to the objection that one can improve one's epistemic state in other fashions, e.g. by having a gain in true beliefs which outweighs one's gain in false beliefs, I provide a challenge (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 999