Results for 'pollachus legetai'

8 found
Order:
  1. πολλαχῶς ἔστι; Plato’s Neglected Ontology.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    This paper aims to suggest a new approach to Plato’s theory of being in Republic V and Sophist based on the notion of difference and the being of a copy. To understand Plato’s ontology in these two dialogues we are going to suggest a theory we call Pollachos Esti; a name we took from Aristotle’s pollachos legetai both to remind the similarities of the two structures and to reach a consistent view of Plato’s ontology. Based on this theory, when (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  20
    Geschlecht pollachos legetai.Geoffrey Bennington - 2020 - Philosophy Today 64 (2):423-439.
    At an important moment in his reading of Heidegger in Geschlecht III, Derrida wields a pair of semi-technical terms from his own earlier work, and uses them to identify a classical, indeed Aristotelian, vein in Heidegger’s reading of Trakl. This gesture is complex, both in that, in spite of appearances, the Mehrdeutigkeit Heidegger identifies in Trakl is not essentially to do with the term Geschlecht, and in that Derrida’s presentation of Aristotle’s views about polysemia is perhaps over-simplified, or at least (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Über das aristotelische "pollachos légetai tò on" [Greek].H. Wagner - 1961 - Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 53 (1):75.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On the scholastic or aristotelian roots of “intentionality” in Brentano.Edmund Runggaldier - 1989 - Topoi 8 (2):97-103.
    The early Brentano identifies intentionality with intentional inexistence, i.e., with a kind of indwelling of the intentional object in the mind. The latter concept cannot be grasped apart from its scholastic background and the Aristotelian—Thomistic doctrine of the multiple use of being (to on legetai pollachos). The fact that Brentano abandoned the theory of the intentional inexistence in the course of time does not contradict the thesis that it is intentional inexistence and not the modern conception of reference or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  8
    Aristotle on the Real Object of Philia and Aretē.Maciej Smolak - 2024 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 72 (1):115-151.
    In the opening remark of Nicomachean Ethics VIII 1 Aristotle notices that the next step would be a discussion of philia, since it is a certain aretē or is associated with aretē (NE VIII 1 1155a 1–2). This article is an attempt to determine how the real object of philia and aretē are related from Aristotle’s point of view. The author performs a study into two sections. The first section is focused on the analysis of aretē and its various types, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Aristotle on the Irreducible Senses of the Good.Jurgis Brakas - 2003 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 6.
    There is a passage in the Nicomachean Ethics that holds out the promise of giving us a profound insight into Aristotle’s view of the good, A6: 1096a23-29. Unfortunately, the passage - where Aristotle argues, contra Plato, that the good cannot be one thing - has proven remarkably resistant to satisfactory interpretation, defying the efforts of scholars over the last nine decades or so. This essay offers an interpretation which, while attempting both to be true to Aristotle’s text and to avoid (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  57
    Different kinds of equivocation in Aristotle.Jaakko Hintikka - 1971 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (3):368-372.
    The interrelations of (1) synonymy, (2) homonymy, And (3) the intermediate class of "pollakhos legetai" in aristotle are studied here. The independence of (3) "vis-A-Vis" (2) is defended against g. E. L. Owen. The role of amphiboly (ambiguity of phrases as distinguished from that of words) in the development of (3) is emphasized. In aristotle, (3) "owes its genesis as much to the breakdown of the homonymy-Amphiboly distinction as to the breakdown of the synonymy-Homonymy dichotomy".
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  57
    Thales of Miletus: The Beginnings of Western Science and Philosophy (review).Kevin Robb - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):107-108.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Thales of Miletus: The Beginnings of Western Science and PhilosophyKevin RobbPatricia F. O’Grady. Thales of Miletus: The Beginnings of Western Science and Philosophy. Aldershot, England: Ashgate, 2002. Pp xxii + 310. Paper, $84.95.This book has a consistent thesis: Thales of Miletus was the first Western scientist and philosopher not just for what he began, but for what he himself said (or, as O'Grady believes, wrote). On this view, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation