Results for 'language conventionalism'

999 found
Order:
  1. Ordinary Language, Conventionalism and a priori Knowledge.Henry Jackman - 2001 - Dialectica 55 (4):315-325.
    This paper examines popular‘conventionalist’explanations of why philosophers need not back up their claims about how‘we’use our words with empirical studies of actual usage. It argues that such explanations are incompatible with a number of currently popular and plausible assumptions about language's ‘social’character. Alternate explanations of the philosopher's purported entitlement to make a priori claims about‘our’usage are then suggested. While these alternate explanations would, unlike the conventionalist ones, be compatible with the more social picture of language, they are each (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2. Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance: We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a (...) that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in fact has a more limited scope; but within that scope the analogy between tolerance and geometric conventionalism is quite tight. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Logical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - unknown - In Filippo Ferrari, Elke Brendel, Massimiliano Carrara, Ole Hjortland, Gil Sagi, Gila Sher & Florian Steinberger (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Once upon a time, logical conventionalism was the most popular philosophical theory of logic. It was heavily favored by empiricists, logical positivists, and naturalists. According to logical conventionalism, linguistic conventions explain logical truth, validity, and modality. And conventions themselves are merely syntactic rules of language use, including inference rules. Logical conventionalism promised to eliminate mystery from the philosophy of logic by showing that both the metaphysics and epistemology of logic fit into a scientific picture of reality. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Necessity and language: In defence of conventionalism.Hans-Johann Glock - 2007 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (1):24–47.
    Kalhat has forcefully criticised Wittgenstein's linguistic or conventionalist account of logical necessity, drawing partly on Waismann and Quine. I defend conventionalism against the charge that it cannot do justice to the truth of necessary propositions, renders them unacceptably arbitrary or reduces them to metalingustic statements. At the same time, I try to reconcile Wittgenstein's claim that necessary propositions are constitutive of meaning with the logical positivists’ claim that they are true by virtue of meaning. Explaining necessary propositions by reference (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  5.  75
    Necessity and language: in defence of conventionalism.Hans Johann Https://Orcidorg909X Glock - 2008 - .
    Kalhat has forcefully criticised Wittgenstein's linguistic or conventionalist account of logical necessity, drawing partly on Waismann and Quine. I defend conventionalism against the charge that it cannot do justice to the truth of necessary propositions, renders them unacceptably arbitrary or reduces them to metalingustic statements. At the same time, I try to reconcile Wittgenstein's claim that necessary propositions are constitutive of meaning with the logical positivists' claim that they are true by virtue of meaning. Explaining necessary propositions by reference (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  15
    Naturalism and Conventionalism in Plato’s Dialogues and Nativistic Theories of Language.Pavlo Sodomora - 2020 - Filozofia i Nauka. Studia Filozoficzne I Interdyscyplinarne 2 (8):47-57.
  7.  99
    Naturalism, Conventionalism, and Forms of Life: Wittgenstein and the "Cratylus".Paul M. Livingston - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (2):7-38.
    I consider Plato’s argument, in the dialogue Cratylus, against both of two opposed views of the “correctness of names.” The first is a conventionalist view, according to which this relationship is arbitrary, the product of a free inaugural decision made at the moment of the first institution of names. The second is a naturalist view, according to which the correctness of names is initially fixed and subsequently maintained by some kind of natural assignment, rooted in the things themselves. I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Plato on conventionalism.Rachel Barney - 1997 - Phronesis 42 (2):143 - 162.
    A new reading of Plato's account of conventionalism about names in the Cratylus. It argues that Hermogenes' position, according to which a name is whatever anybody 'sets down' as one, does not have the counterintuitive consequences usually claimed. At the same time, Plato's treatment of conventionalism needs to be related to his treatment of formally similar positions in ethics and politics. Plato is committed to standards of objective natural correctness in all such areas, despite the problematic consequences which, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  9. Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - 2020 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    What is the source of logical and mathematical truth? This book revitalizes conventionalism as an answer to this question. Conventionalism takes logical and mathematical truth to have their source in linguistic conventions. This was an extremely popular view in the early 20th century, but it was never worked out in detail and is now almost universally rejected in mainstream philosophical circles. Shadows of Syntax is the first book-length treatment and defense of a combined conventionalist theory of logic and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  10.  29
    The scientific world-perspective and other essays, 1931–1963, by Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. Edited and with an introduction by Giedymin Jerzy. Synthese library, vol. 108. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston 1978, LIII + 378 pp.Giedymin Jerzy. Editor's preface. Pp. IX–XII.Giedymin Jerzy. Ajdukiewicz's life and personality. Pp. XIII–XVI.Giedymin Jerzy. Radical conventionalism, its background and evolution: Poincaré, LeRoy, Ajdukiewicz. Pp. XIX–LIII.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the meaning of expressions. Pp. 1–34. English translation by Jerzy Giedymin of XXXVIII 536.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. Language and meaning. Pp. 35–66. English translation by John Wilkinson of 2259.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. The world-picture and the conceptual apparatus. Pp. 67–89. English translation by John Wilkinson of XXXVIII 537.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the applicability of pure logic to philosophical problems. Pp. 90–94. English translation by Jerzy Giedymin of XXXVIII 536.Ajdukiewicz Kazimierz. On the probl.C. Lejewski - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):457-463.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Legal conventionalism in the U.s. Constitutional law of privacy*: Mark Tushnet.Mark Tushnet - 2000 - Social Philosophy and Policy 17 (2):141-164.
    Drawing on themes important in moral and political philosophy, much of the scholarship on the constitutional law of privacy in the United States distinguishes between privacy understood as a person's control over information and privacy understood as a person's ability to make autonomous decisions. For example, Katz v. United States established the framework for analyzing whether police activity constituted a “search” subject to the Fourth Amendment's requirement that the police either obtain a warrant before conducting a search or otherwise act (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Against Depictive Conventionalism.Catharine Abell - 2005 - American Philosophical Quarterly 42 (3):185 - 197.
    In this paper, I discuss the influential view that depiction, like language, depends on arbitrary conventions. I argue that this view, however it is elaborated, is false. Any adequate account of depiction must be consistent with the distinctive features of depiction. One such feature is depictive generativity. I argue that, to be consistent with depictive generativity, conventionalism must hold that depiction depends on conventions for the depiction of basic properties of a picture’s object. I then argue that two (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  62
    Conventionalism, Truth, and CosmologicaI Furniture.J. O. Wisdom - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):441-457.
    The problem to be discussed here concerns ontology so far as it may not be formed by scientific theory. In brief terms, the problem arises in the following way. On the one hand, the world surely consists of whatever is there, irrespective of whether human beings are around or not, and irrespective especially of whether human beings have constructed any scientific theories depicting the nature of the world; on the other hand, scientific theories are subject to the limitation that we (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. What is Carnap's conventionalism after all?Norma Yunez-Naude - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):261 - 272.
    As is well known, Carnap's conventionalism was a rejection to Kant's view ofmathematics and was fully developed in his Logische Syntax der Sprache.The purpose of this article is to step back to Der Logische Aufbau der Weltto show that the Logical Syntax of Language is an attempt to solve difficultiesfound in the earlier construction. I first clarify the notion of conventionalism, whichplays a central role in the application of mathematics to the reconstruction of empiricalknowledge. By not strictly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  16
    Extreme and Modest Conventionalism in Plato’s Cratylus.C. G. Healow - 2020 - Apeiron 54 (1):1-28.
    The Cratylus’ main concern is to outline and evaluate the competing views of language held by two characters, Hermogenes and Cratylus, who disagree about whether convention or nature (respectively) are the source of onomastic correctness. Hermogenes has been thought to hold two radically different views by different scholars, one extreme conventionalism whereby all names are correct relative to their speakers, and another modest conventionalism according to which distinct naming actions – establishment and employment – explain why some (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Carnap's metrical conventionalism versus differential topology.Thomas Mormann - 2004 - Proc. 2004 Biennial Meeting of the PSA, vol. I, Contributed Papers 72 (5):814 - 825.
    Geometry was a main source of inspiration for Carnap’s conventionalism. Taking Poincaré as his witness Carnap asserted in his dissertation Der Raum (Carnap 1922) that the metrical structure of space is conventional while the underlying topological structure describes "objective" facts. With only minor modifications he stuck to this account throughout his life. The aim of this paper is to disprove Carnap's contention by invoking some classical theorems of differential topology. By this means his metrical conventionalism turns out to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  17
    Carnap’s Metrical Conventionalism versus Differential Topology.Thomas Mormann - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):814-825.
    Geometry was a main source of inspiration for Carnap's conventionalism. Taking Poincaré as his witness, Carnap asserted in his dissertation Der Raum that the metrical structure of space is conventional while the underlying topological structure describes ‘objective’ facts. With only minor modifications he stuck to this account throughout his life. The aim of this paper is to disprove Carnap's contention by invoking some classical theorems of differential topology. It is shown that his metrical conventionalism is indefensible for mathematical (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  33
    Legal positivism, conventionalism, and the normativity of law.Torben Spaak - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (2):319-344.
    ABSTRACTThe aim of this article is to see whether we can account for the normativity of law within the framework of legal positivism and whether the idea of a social convention could be of help in this endeavour. I argue, inter alia, that we should distinguish between the problem of accounting for the normativity of law, conceived as a necessary property of law, and the problem of accounting for the use of normative legal language on the part of legal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  24
    Carnap's conventionalism : logic, science, and tolerance.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2014 - Dissertation, University of St Andrews
    In broadest terms, this thesis is concerned to answer the question of whether the view that arithmetic is analytic can be maintained consistently. Lest there be much suspense, I will conclude that it can. Those who disagree claim that accounts which defend the analyticity of arithmetic are either unable to give a satisfactory account of the foundations of mathematics due to the incompleteness theorems, or, if steps are taken to mitigate incompleteness, then the view loses the ability to account for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Historicism, Entrenchment, and Conventionalism.Nathaniel Jason Goldberg - 2009 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 40 (2):259-276.
    W. V. Quine famously argues that though all knowledge is empirical, mathematics is entrenched relative to physics and the special sciences. Further, entrenchment accounts for the necessity of mathematics relative to these other disciplines. Michael Friedman challenges Quine’s view by appealing to historicism, the thesis that the nature of science is illuminated by taking into account its historical development. Friedman argues on historicist grounds that mathematical claims serve as principles constitutive of languages within which empirical claims in physics and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21. Artificial Language Philosophy of Science.Sebastian Lutz - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (2):181–203.
    Abstract Artificial language philosophy (also called ‘ideal language philosophy’) is the position that philosophical problems are best solved or dissolved through a reform of language. Its underlying methodology—the development of languages for specific purposes—leads to a conventionalist view of language in general and of concepts in particular. I argue that many philosophical practices can be reinterpreted as applications of artificial language philosophy. In addition, many factually occurring interrelations between the sciences and philosophy of science are (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22. Carnap's conventionalism: The problem with p-rules.Thomas Oberdan - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    Rudolf Carnap's 'Principle of Tolerance' was undoubtedly one of the most infl uential precepts in 20th Century philosophy. Introduced in The Logical Syntax of Language, Carnap's Principle suffered from ambiguities which aroused important philosophical questions from Moritz Schlick and Alberto Coffa. Specifi cally, their questions arise from the application of the Principle to the matter of including extra-logical transformation rules in the defi nition of a language, which Carnap regarded as an important difference between his own conventionalist philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Unconventional, but Conventionalist, Legacy of Lewis’s “Convention”.Olivier Favereau - 2008 - Topoi 27 (1-2):115-126.
    The philosopher David Lewis is credited by many social scientists, including mainstream economists, with having founded the modern (game-theoretical) approach to conventions, viewed as solutions to recurrent coordination problems. Yet it is generally ignored that he revised his approach, soon after the publication of his well-known book. I suggest that this revision has deep implications (probably not perceived by Lewis himself) on the analytical links between coordination, uncertainty and rationality. Thinking anew about these issues leads me to map out an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  26
    An Argument Against the Conventionalist Interpretation of Images.Eduardo Neiva - 2001 - American Journal of Semiotics 17 (3):69-90.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. A Defence of Conventionalism.Paul Horwich - 1986 - In Graham Macdonald Crispin Wright (ed.), Fact, Science and Morality: Essays on A. J. Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. Blackwell.
  26. The stuff of conventionalism.Thomas A. Blackson - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (1):65 - 81.
  27.  22
    Language, logic, and causation: philosophical writings of Douglas Gasking.Tim Oakley & L. J. O'Neill (eds.) - 1996 - Melbourne, Australia: Melbourne University Press.
    This volume is a collection of ten essays by Douglas Gasking (1911–1994), a significant figure in Australian philosophy. There are three previously published papers, “Mathematics and the World” (proposing a form of conventionalism), “Causation and Recipes” (expounding a manipulation account of causation), and “Clusters”, (an account of certain varieties of class-membership). The seven previously unpublished papers include further work on causation, some epistemological issues, subjective probability, a carefully worked out account of the sense in which observable behaviour can be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  99
    Pierre Duhem's the aim and structure of physical theory: A book against conventionalism.Roberto Maiocchi - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):385 - 400.
    I reject the widely held view that Duhem's 1906 book La Théorie physique is a statement of instrumentalistic conventionalism, motivated by the scientific crisis at the end of the nineteenth century. By considering Duhem's historical context I show that his epistemological views were already formed before the crisis occured; that he consistently supported general thermodynamics against the new atomism; and that he rejected the epistemological views of the latter's philosophical supporters. In particular I show that Duhem rejected Poincaré's account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  29.  18
    The Intensionality behind Legal Concepts and Their Extensional Boundaries: Between Conventionalism and Interpretivism.Alexandra Arapinis & Angela Condello - 2016 - Ratio Juris 29 (4):439-459.
    This article constitutes an attempt to reexamine a crucial issue of legal theory from the perspective of philosophy of language and of social ontology: by analyzing a jurisprudential case recently decided by the U.S. Supreme Court, we explain how Searle's account on rules in The Construction of Social Reality constitutes an important starting point for the clarification of the old jurisprudential debate between conventionalism and interpretivism. In a nutshell, we show that Searle's framework, while strictly conventionalist, makes it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  42
    The Methodological Roles of Tolerance and Conventionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics: Reconsidering Carnap's Logic of Science.Emerson P. Doyle - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Western Ontario
    This dissertation makes two primary contributions. The first three chapters develop an interpretation of Carnap's Meta-Philosophical Program which places stress upon his methodological analysis of the sciences over and above the Principle of Tolerance. Most importantly, I suggest, is that Carnap sees philosophy as contiguous with science—as a part of the scientific enterprise—so utilizing the very same methods and subject to the same limitations. I argue that the methodological reforms he suggests for philosophy amount to philosophy as the explication of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  18
    Language as a Way to Cognition.Pavlo Sodomora - 2018 - Sententiae 37 (2):159-164.
    The translator of the first Ukrainian version of Plato’s Cratylus (see above, p. ..) indicates the difficulties in translating the dialogue, emphasizing the external and internal aspects of those difficulties. The external aspect consists in the different etymology of Greek and Ukrainian words, and the internal one lays in the problem of choice between “Latinization” and “Ukrainization” of the translated text. The author made one of his translation principles to avoid excessive Latinization and justifies his decision.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Coordination, Triangulation, and Language Use.Josh Armstrong - 2016 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 59 (1):80-112.
    In this paper, I explore two contrasting conceptions of the social character of language. The first takes language to be grounded in social convention. The second, famously developed by Donald Davidson, takes language to be grounded in a social relation called triangulation. I aim both to clarify and to evaluate these two conceptions of language. First, I propose that Davidson’s triangulation-based story can be understood as the result of relaxing core features of conventionalism pertaining to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  33.  42
    Social Conventions: From Language to Law: From Language to Law.Andrei Marmor - 2009 - Princeton University Press.
    Social conventions are those arbitrary rules and norms governing the countless behaviors all of us engage in every day without necessarily thinking about them, from shaking hands when greeting someone to driving on the right side of the road. In this book, Andrei Marmor offers a pathbreaking and comprehensive philosophical analysis of conventions and the roles they play in social life and practical reason, and in doing so challenges the dominant view of social conventions first laid out by David Lewis. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  34.  53
    Plato’s Theory of Language: the Isomorphism of Kosmos and Logos in the Timaeus.Alexey Pleshkov - 2017 - Problemos 91:128.
    The paper considers Plato’s theory of language through the prism of the Timaeus’ metaphysics. It is argued that the apparent contradictions of Plato’s philosophy of language are the consequence of the two-fold nature of language, and that the metaphysical scheme proposed by Plato in the Timaeus can shed a light on his coherent theory of language. The linguo-metaphysical isomorphism of the Timaeus presupposes that (1) words and material elements have their own meaning and nature respectively; (2) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Multitude, tolerance and language-transcendence.Matti Eklund - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):833-847.
    Rudolf Carnap's 1930s philosophy of logic, including his adherence to the principle of tolerance, is discussed. What theses did Carnap commit himself to, exactly? I argue that while Carnap did commit himself to a certain multitude thesis—there are different logics of different languages, and the choice between these languages is merely a matter of expediency—there is no evidence that he rejected a language-transcendent notion of fact, contrary to what Warren Goldfarb and Thomas Ricketts have prominently argued. (In fact, it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36. Language, Communication, and the Paradox of Analysis: Some Philosophical Remarks on Plato's Cratylus.Marc Moffett - 2005 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 8.
    On the face of it, Plato’s dialogue the Cratylus has a clear and narrowly linguistic subject matter, specifically, the debate between conventionalism and naturalism in the theory of meaning. But why should this topic be of sufficient interest to Plato to warrant an entire dialogue? What philosophically was at stake for him in these seemingly recherché questions about language? I argue that at least one major motivation is a defense of Platonistic epistemology and, in particular, Plato’s Theory of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  4
    Skepticism, Rules, and Private Languages.Patricia Hogue Werhane - 1992 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
    Patricia Werhane synthesizes much of later Wittgensteinian thought, bringing together disparate arguments into a coherent text. Keeping in mind what Wittgenstein set out to accomplish in his later writings, the introduction of new material on the private language arguments, and the philosophical significance of these claims, Werhane develops the thesis that the notion of a rule is such a constitutive of language that a private language is impossible. Such a conclusion challenges many contemporary readings of the Philosphical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  72
    Does Conversation Need Shared Language? Davidson and Gadamer on Communicative Understanding.Greg Lynch - 2014 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):359-381.
    In a rare discussion of Gadamer's work, Davidson takes issue with Gadamer's claim that successful communication requires that interlocutors share a common language. While he is right to see a difference between his own views and Gadamer's on this point, Davidson appears to have misunderstood what motivates Gadamer's position, conflating it with that of his more familiar conventionalist interlocutors. This paper articulates Gadamer's view of the role of language in communicative understanding as an alternative to both Davidson's and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Necessity and language: The gap is still very real.Javier Kalhat - 2008 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (3):227–236.
    In my previous paper "Has the later Wittgenstein accounted for necessity?" I argued against the conventionalist account of necessity proposed by Wittgenstein and his followers. Glock has addressed some of my objections in his paper "Necessity and Language: In Defence of Conventionalism". This brief rejoinder considers Glock's replies to three of those objections. In the course of doing so, I revisit Wittgenstein's explanation of the special status of necessary propositions, the supposedly arbitrary nature of colour-grammatical propositions, and the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  9
    Dąmbska’s presentation of Ajdukiewicz’s conception of language.Zbigniew Orbik - 2016 - Studies in East European Thought 68 (1):75-84.
    Izydora Da˛mbska was one of the most outstanding representatives of the Lvov-Warsaw School and a disciple of both the School’s founder Kazimierz Twardowski and Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz. Interest in the School was the result of Twardowski’s program of scientific philosophy, which was adopted by the vast majority of his students. This program assumed that the basic condition for practicing philosophy in a scientific manner is the precise use of language by a philosopher. One of the scholars who devoted most attention (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  17
    Philosophical abstracts.Moral Conventionalism - 1985 - American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (1):915-933.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. The problem with p-rules Thomas Oberdan clemson university.Carnap'S. Conventionalism - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  9
    Rules, understanding and language games in mathematics.V. V. Tselishchev - forthcoming - Philosophical Problems of IT and Cyberspace.
    The article is devoted to the applicability of Wittgenstein’s following the rule in the context of his philosophy of mathematics to real mathematical practice. It is noted that in «Philosophical Investigations» and «Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics» Wittgenstein resorted to the analysis of rather elementary mathematical concepts, accompanied also by the inherent ambiguity and ambiguity of his presentation. In particular, against this background, his radical conventionalism, the substitution of logical necessity with the «form of life» of the community, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  25
    Spinoza on Language.Luis Ramos-Alarcón - unknown
    Some scholars have understood that Spinoza’s extreme rationalism, nominalism, conventionalism, and rejection of a semantic theory of truth make his philosophy incapable to use language for philosophical and scientific purposes; insofar he considered language a source of inadequate knowledge, falsity, and error. Thus Spinoza finds contradiction in his inevitable use of language to express his philosophy. This paper has four aims: first, propose an explanation on why language is inadequate knowledge for Spinoza; second, present differences (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Lexical innovation and the periphery of language.Luca Gasparri - 2021 - Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (1):39-63.
    Lexical innovations (e.g., zero-derivations coined on the fly by a speaker) seem to bear semantic content. Yet, such expressions cannot bear semantic content as a function of the conventions of meaning in force in the language, since they are not part of its lexicon. This is in tension with the commonplace view that the semantic content of lexical expressions is constituted by linguistic conventions. The conventionalist has two immediate ways out of the tension. The first is to preserve the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. The Language of Nature: An Essay in the Philosophy of Science. [REVIEW]J. M. P. - 1965 - Review of Metaphysics 19 (2):375-375.
    What is attempted in this book is a presentation of various areas of science in such ways that their attendant philosophical problems are displayed, and their philosophical relevance is made evident. Essentially, there are three parts to the book: the first, comprising chapters on the nature of number, geometry, and the mathematical treatments of motion and measurement, presents the usual problems of conventionalism in geometry, physical vs. formal geometry, but also discusses Turing machines and information theory. The next five (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  73
    Kripke, Wittgenstein, and the private language argument.Petra von Morstein - 1980 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 11 (1):61-74.
    "Agreement" is the key notion in Wittgenstein's explanation of the possibility of public language. Agreement in judgements constitutes the justification for asserting agreement in definitions. The determinates of rules are empirical; rules as determinables are transcendental. Rules are on the limit of public language, and not within it. Wittgenstein's skeptical solutions to skepticism about language and about the given are transcendentalistic. His skeptical solutions in other areas are conventionalistic. Skepticism about mental phenomena is not solved because of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  39
    Reflection on natural kinds. Introduction to the special issue on natural kinds: language, science, and metaphysics.Luis Fernández Moreno - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 12):2853-2862.
    This article is an introduction to the Synthese Special Issue, Natural Kinds: Language, Science, and Metaphysics. The issue includes new contributions to some of the main questions involved in the present philosophical debates on natural kinds and on natural kind terms. Those debates are relevant to philosophy of language, philosophy of science, and metaphysics. In philosophy of language it is highly debated what the meaning of natural kind terms is, how their reference is determined, as well as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  53
    Aristotle’s Theory of Language and Meaning. [REVIEW]Fred Miller - 2004 - Review of Metaphysics 57 (3):640-641.
    Part I deals with language and knowledge. Chapter 1: Plato’s Cratylus presents two opposing views of meaning—naturalism and conventionalism—and finds both wanting. Aristotle’s De Interpretatione offers a compromise between these views: the relations between written and spoken words and between spoken words and mental states are conventional, but that between mental states and the objects they represent is natural. Chapter 2: Aristotle holds a correspondence theory of truth, and he treats necessity as a property that a statement has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Conventions and Their Role in Language.M. J. Cain - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (1):137-158.
    Two of the most fundamental questions about language are these: what are languages?; and, what is it to know a given language? Many philosophers who have reflected on these questions have presented answers that attribute a central role to conventions. In one of its boldest forms such a view runs as follows. Languages are either social entities constituted by networks of social conventions or abstract objects where when a particular community speaks a given language they do so (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 999