Results for 'knowledge and reasons'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Knowledge and reasons for belief.Alan Millar - 2011 - In Andrew Reisner & Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen (eds.), Reasons for Belief. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  2.  92
    Faculties, Knowledge, and Reasons for Doubt in the Cartesian Circle.Matthew Clark - 2019 - Mind 128 (511):647-672.
    This paper argues for a novel solution to the Cartesian Circle by emphasising the important epistemic role of the Second Meditation and Descartes’ faculty epistemology. I argue that, for Descartes: doubt requires a ‘good reason’ to doubt ; whether a reason qualifies as a ‘good reason’ depends on which faculty produces that reason ; and for distinct metaphysical perceptions from the faculty of the intellect, no other faculty can provide ‘good reasons’ to doubt. The upshot of §2 is that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Knowledge and reasonableness.Krista Lawlor - 2020 - Synthese 199:1435-1451.
    The notion of relevance plays a role in many accounts of knowledge and knowledge ascription. Although use of the notion is well-motivated, theorists struggle to codify relevance. A reasonable person standard of relevance addresses this codification problem, and provides an objective and flexible standard of relevance; however, treating relevance as reasonableness seems to allow practical factors to determine whether one has knowledge or not—so-called “pragmatic encroachment.” I argue that a fuller understanding of reasonableness and of the role (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  69
    Knowledge and reasoning.Mona Simion - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3):10371-10388.
    This paper develops a novel, functionalist, unified account of the epistemic normativity of reasoning. On this view, epistemic norms drop out of epistemic functions. I argue that practical reasoning serves a prudential function of generating prudentially permissible action, and the epistemic function of generating knowledge of what one ought to do. This picture, if right, goes a long way towards normatively divorcing action and practical reasoning. At the same time, it unifies reasoning epistemically: practical and theoretical reasoning will turn (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  6
    Knowledge and reasoning in program synthesis.Zohar Manna & Richard Waldinger - 1975 - Artificial Intelligence 6 (2):175-208.
  6.  33
    Knowledge and reasons.George S. Pappas - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 25 (6):423 - 428.
  7.  17
    Basic Knowledge and Reasoning Process in the Art Creation.Bambang Sunarto - 2015 - Open Journal of Philosophy 5 (5):285-296.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  5
    Scepticism, Knowledge and Reasonable Belief.Oliver Johnson - 1988 - Philosophie Et Culture: Actes du XVIIe Congrès Mondial de Philosophie 2:889-893.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Review: Knowledge and the social articulation of the space of reasons[REVIEW]Robert Brandom - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):895--908.
    In “Knowledge and the Internal” John McDowell presents a deep and interesting argument. I think everything he says is true and important. Still, there are a number of points that bear expanding on in order to be properly understood. So I want to say something about his point of departure: the idea of standings in the space of reasons. And I want to fill in further the picture at which he finally arrives, by saying how I think we (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  10. Definite Descriptions and the Gettier Example.Christoph Schmidt-Petri & London School of Economics and Political Science - 2002 - CPNSS Discussion Papers.
    This paper challenges the first Gettier counterexample to the tripartite account of knowledge. Noting that 'the man who will get the job' is a description and invoking Donnellan's distinction between their 'referential' and 'attributive' uses, I argue that Smith does not actually believe that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Smith's ignorance about who will get the job shows that the belief cannot be understood referentially, his ignorance of the coins in his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Introspective Self-Knowledge and Reasoning: An Externalist Guide.Thomas Grundmann - 2009 - Erkenntnis 71 (1):89-105.
    According to the received view, externalist grounds or reasons need not be introspectively accessible. Roughly speaking, from an externalist point of view, a belief will be epistemically justified, iff it is based upon facts that make its truth objectively highly likely. This condition can be satisfied, even if the epistemic agent does not have actual or potential awareness of the justifying facts. No inner perspective on the belief-forming mechanism and its truth-ratio is needed for a belief to be justified. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Knowledge and practical reason.Jessica Brown - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (6):1135-1152.
    It has become recently popular to suggest that knowledge is the epistemic norm of practical reasoning and that this provides an important constraint on the correct account of knowledge, one which favours subject-sensitive invariantism over contextualism and classic invariantism. I argue that there are putative counterexamples to both directions of the knowledge norm. Even if the knowledge norm can be defended against these counterexamples, I argue that it is a delicate issue whether it is true, one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  13. Knowledge and practical reasoning.Igor Douven - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (1):101–118.
    The idea that knowledge is conceptually related to practical reasoning is becoming increasingly popular. In defending this idea, philosophers have been relying on a conception of practical reasoning that drastically deviates from one which has been more traditionally advocated in analytic philosophy and which assigns no special role to knowledge. This paper argues that these philosophers have failed to give good reasons for thinking that the conception of practical reasoning they have been assuming is the right one, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  14.  17
    Knowledge and Practical Reasoning.Igor Douven - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (1):101-118.
    The idea that knowledge is conceptually related to practical reasoning is becoming increasingly popular. In defending this idea, philosophers have been relying on a conception of practical reasoning that drastically deviates from one which has been more traditionally advocated in analytic philosophy and which assigns no special role to knowledge. This paper argues that these philosophers have failed to give good reasons for thinking that the conception of practical reasoning they have been assuming is the right one, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  15. Human knowledge and the infinite progress of reasoning.Peter Klein - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 134 (1):1 - 17.
    The purpose of this paper is to explain how infinitism—the view that reasons are endless and non-repeating—solves the epistemic regress problem and to defend that solution against some objections. The first step is to explain what the epistemic regress problem is and, equally important, what it is not. Second, I will discuss the foundationalist and coherentist responses to the regress problem and offer some reasons for thinking that neither response can solve the problem, no matter how they are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  16. Knowledge, Practical Reasoning and Action.Peter Baumann - 2012 - Logos and Episteme 3 (1):7-26.
    Is knowledge necessary or sufficient or both necessary and sufficient for acceptable practical reasoning and rational action? Several authors (e.g., Williamson, Hawthorne, and Stanley) have recently argued that the answer to these questions is positive. In this paper I present several objections against this view (both in its basic form as well in more developed forms). I also offer a sketch of an alternative view: What matters for the acceptability of practical reasoning in at least many cases (and in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. Human knowledge and the infinite regress of reasons.Peter D. Klein - 1999 - Philosophical Perspectives 13:297-325.
  18. Self-trust: a study of reason, knowledge, and autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The eminent philosopher Keith Lehrer offers an original and distinctively personal view of central aspects of the human condition, such as reason, knowledge, wisdom, autonomy, love, consensus, and consciousness. He argues that what is uniquely human is our capacity for evaluating our own mental states (such as beliefs and desires), and suggests that we have a system for such evaluation which allows the resolution of personal and interpersonal conflict. The keystone in this system is self-trust, on which reason, (...), and wisdom are grounded. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  19. Knowledge Beyond Reason in Spinoza’s Epistemology: Scientia Intuitiva and Amor Dei Intellectualis in Spinoza’s Epistemology.Anne Newstead - 2020 - Australasian Philosophical Review 4 (Revisiting Spinoza's Rationalism).
    Genevieve Lloyd’s Spinoza is quite a different thinker from the arch rationalist caricature of some undergraduate philosophy courses devoted to “The Continental Rationalists”. Lloyd’s Spinoza does not see reason as a complete source of knowledge, nor is deductive rational thought productive of the highest grade of knowledge. Instead, that honour goes to a third kind of knowledge—intuitive knowledge (scientia intuitiva), which provides an immediate, non-discursive knowledge of its singular object. To the embarrassment of some hard-nosed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  70
    Human Knowledge and the Infinite Regress of Reasons.Peter D. Klein - 1999 - Noûs 33 (s13):297-325.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  21.  35
    Scepticism, knowledge, and forms of reasoning.John Koethe - 2005 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Scepticism, Knowledge, and Forms of Reasoning is an attempt to resolve how best to respond to such vexing arguments, a matter on which there is no consensus ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Logical knowledge and ordinary reasoning.Corine Besson - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 158 (1):59-82.
    This paper argues that the prominent accounts of logical knowledge have the consequence that they conflict with ordinary reasoning. On these accounts knowing a logical principle, for instance, is having a disposition to infer according to it. These accounts in particular conflict with so-called ‘reasoned change in view’, where someone does not infer according to a logical principle but revise their views instead. The paper also outlines a propositional account of logical knowledge which does not conflict with ordinary (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  23. Kant on the Material Ground of Possibility: From The Only Possible Argument to the Critique of Pure Reason.Mark Fisher and Eric Watkins - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):369-396.
    KANT ARGUES AT GREAT LENGTH in the Critique of Pure Reason that the existence of God cannot be demonstrated by means of theoretical reason. For after dividing all traditional theistic proofs into three different kinds—the ontological, the cosmological, and the physico-theological—Kant argues first that the cosmological and physico-theological implicitly assume the ontological argument and then that the ontological argument is necessarily fallacious. By restricting knowledge in this manner Kant notoriously makes room for faith, that is, in this case, for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Revelation and Reason: The Christian Doctrine of Faith and Knowledge.Emil Brunner & Olive Wyon - 1949 - Philosophy 24 (90):275-276.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Perception and Reason.Bill Brewer - 1999 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Bill Brewer presents an original view of the role of conscious experience in the acquisition of empirical knowledge. He argues that perceptual experiences must provide reasons for empirical beliefs if there are to be any determinate beliefs at all about particular objects in the world. This fresh approach to epistemology turns away from the search for necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge and works instead from a theory of understanding in a particular area.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  26.  64
    Scepticism, knowledge, and forms of reasoning.Anthony Brueckner - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3):733–736.
  27. Reasons, knowledge, and probability.Fred I. Dretske - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (2):216-220.
    Though one believes that P is true, one can have reasons for thinking it false. Yet, it seems that one cannot know that P is true and (still) have reasons for thinking it false. Why is this so? What feature of knowledge (or of reasons) precludes having reasons or evidence to believe (true) what you know to be false? If the connection between reasons (evidence) and what one believes is expressible as a probability relation, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  23
    Ignorance, Knowledge, and Omniscience: At and Beyond the Limits of Faith and Reason after Shinran : Reflections on The Boundaries of Knowledge in Buddhism, Christianity, and Science, with Special Attention to Dennis Hirota.Amos Yong - 2011 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 31:201-210.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Ignorance, Knowledge, and Omniscience: At and Beyond the Limits of Faith and Reason after Shinran:Reflections on The Boundaries of Knowledge in Buddhism, Christianity, and Science, with Special Attention to Dennis HirotaAmos YongAlthough published in the series Religion, Theologie und Naturwissenschaft, Paul Numrich's edited volume is really about epistemology in religion and science, in particular about human knowing in Buddhist and Christian traditions shaped by the world of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Lotteries, Knowledge, and Practical Reasoning.Rachel McKinnon - 2011 - Logos and Episteme 2 (2):225-231.
    This paper addresses an argument offered by John Hawthorne gainst the propriety of an agent’s using propositions she does not know as premises in practical reasoning. I will argue that there are a number of potential structural confounds in Hawthorne’s use of his main example, a case of practical reasoning about a lottery. By drawing these confounds out more explicitly, we can get a better sense of how to make appropriate use of such examples in theorizing about norms, knowledge, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Knowledge and the epistemic function of argumentation – Comment on Gascón's "Where are dissent and reasons in epistemic justification?".Christoph Lumer - 2020 - In Catarina Dutilh Novaes, Henrike Jansen, Jan Albert Van Laar & Bart Verheij (eds.), Reason to Dissent. Proceedings of the 3rd European Conference on Argumentation. College Publications. pp. 219-224.
    José Ángel Gascón’s essay "Where are dissent and reasons in epistemic justification?" is an exposition of a version of a social functionalist epistemology. I agree with Gascón's emphasis on reasons and on taking into account dissent as important parts of epistemology. But I think that these concerns do not require a social functionalist epistemology, but that, on the contrary, Gascón's social functionalist epistemology throws the baby out with the bathwater. It does so by excluding also a traditional, at (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  27
    Common Knowledge and Hinge Epistemology.Michael Wilby - 2024 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 32 (1).
    Common knowledge is ubiquitous in our lives and yet there remains considerable uncertainty about how to model or understand it. Standard analyses of common knowledge end up being challenged by either regress or circularity which then give rise to well-known paradoxes of practical reasoning, such as the Two Generals’ Paradox. This paper argues that the nature and utility of common knowledge can be illuminated by appeal to Wittgenstein’s Hinge Epistemology. It is argued that those things that we (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  32
    Reality and reason: dialectic and the theory of knowledge.Sean Sayers - 1985 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Everything possible to be believed is an image of truth (The Marriage of Heaven and Hell, Blake) Introduction In this book I deal with some of the central ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33. Objective Knowledge and Self-Consciousness: The Role of Kant's Theory of Apperceptive Self-Identity in the "Critique of Pure Reason".Dennis J. Sweet - 1989 - Dissertation, The University of Iowa
    Kant's purpose in the Critique of Pure Reason was to describe the nature and set the boundaries of human knowledge. At the heart of this ambitious enterprise is his doctrine of apperceptive self-identity. He insists that in order for us to know anything, there must be a unitary self capable of being aware of its own identity over time. Unfortunately, Kant's descriptions of this unitary 'I think' are extremely obscure, and his accounts of how it functions in the first (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  61
    Sophisticated knowledge representation and reasoning requires philosophy.Selmer Bringsjord, Micah Clark & Joshua Taylor - forthcoming - In Ruth Hagengruber (ed.), Philosophy's Relevance in Information Science.
    Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR&R) is based on the idea that propositional content can be rigorously represented in formal languages long the province of logic, in such a way that these representations can be productively reasoned over by humans and machines; and that this reasoning can be used to produce knowledge-based systems (KBSs). As such, KR&R is a discipline conventionally regarded to range across parts of artificial intelligence (AI), computer science, and especially logic. This standard view of KR&R’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  21
    Lotteries, Knowledge, and Practical Reasoning.Rhys McKinnon - 2011 - Logos and Episteme 2 (2):225-231.
    This paper addresses an argument offered by John Hawthorne against the propriety of an agent’s using propositions she does not know as premises in practical reasoning. I will argue that there are a number of potential structural confounds in Hawthorne’s use of his main example, a case of practical reasoning about a lottery. By drawing these confounds out more explicitly, we can get a better sense of how to make appropriate use of such examples in theorizing about norms, knowledge, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  29
    Somatic knowledge and qualitative reasoning: From theory to practice.Richard Siegesmund - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (4):80-96.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Somatic Knowledge and Qualitative Reasoning:From Theory to PracticeRichard Siegesmund"Elliot Eisner is a writer to be reckoned with" is how my undergraduate student, Cheyenne, opened her final essay on The Arts and the Creation of Mind. After a semester of using his text in my art education methods class, reckoned seemed an apt word. The dictionary gives the definitions of reckoned as to settle accounts, make calculation, judge, and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  10
    Somatic Knowledge and Qualitative Reasoning: From Theory to Practice.Richard Siegesmund - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (4):80.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Somatic Knowledge and Qualitative Reasoning:From Theory to PracticeRichard Siegesmund"Elliot Eisner is a writer to be reckoned with" is how my undergraduate student, Cheyenne, opened her final essay on The Arts and the Creation of Mind. After a semester of using his text in my art education methods class, reckoned seemed an apt word. The dictionary gives the definitions of reckoned as to settle accounts, make calculation, judge, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  42
    Neuropragmatism, knowledge, and pragmatic naturalism.John Shook - 2013 - Human Affairs 23 (4):576-593.
    Neuropragmatism is a research program taking sciences about cognitive development and learning methods most seriously, in order to reevaluate and reformulate philosophical issues. Knowledge, consciousness, and reason are among the crucial philosophical issues directly affected. Pragmatism in general has allied with the science-affirming philosophy of naturalism. Naturalism is perennially tested by challenges questioning its ability to accommodate and account for knowledge, consciousness, and reason. Neuropragmatism is in a good position to evaluate those challenges. Some ways to defuse them (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  36
    Knowledge and transformation in Peirce's “reasoning and the logic of things”.Roger Ward - 2007 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 21 (2):142 - 150.
  40.  4
    Knowledge and Children's Reasoning about Possibility.David M. Sobel - 2011 - In Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack & Sarah R. Beck (eds.), Understanding Counterfactuals, Understanding Causation. Oxford University Press. pp. 123.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  9
    Knowledge and non-constructive reasoning.D. E. Over - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (142):29-36.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  4
    Reality and Reason, Dialectic and the Theory of Knowledge.Dudley Knowles - 1986 - Philosophical Books 27 (3):167-170.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  7
    Knowledge and the Space of Reasons: The Ideas of John McDowell and Paul Hirst.Geoffrey Hinchliffe - 2014 - Philosophy of Education 70:107-114.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Knowledge and lotteries.John Hawthorne - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Knowledge and Lotteries is organized around an epistemological puzzle: in many cases, we seem consistently inclined to deny that we know a certain class of propositions, while crediting ourselves with knowledge of propositions that imply them. In its starkest form, the puzzle is this: we do not think we know that a given lottery ticket will be a loser, yet we normally count ourselves as knowing all sorts of ordinary things that entail that its holder will not suddenly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   906 citations  
  45.  25
    Knowledge and the Function of Reason. By Richard I. Aaron. Oxford, Clarendon Press. 1971. Pp. x, 271. $12.00.David M. Johnson - 1972 - Dialogue 11 (4):643-644.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Self-knowledge, and the virtues of practical reasoning.Thomas Hibbs - 2009 - In Lawrence Cunningham (ed.), Intractable Disputes About the Natural Law: Alasdair Macintyre and Critics. University of Notre Dame Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  7
    Knowledge and political reason.Barry Hindess - 1998 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 1 (2):63-84.
  48.  8
    Scepticism, Knowledge, and Forms of Reasoning. [REVIEW]Anthony Brueckner - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3):733-736.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Science, reason, knowledge, and wisdom: A critique of specialism.Nicholas Maxwell - 1980 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 23 (1):19 – 81.
    In this paper I argue for a kind of intellectual inquiry which has, as its basic aim, to help all of us to resolve rationally the most important problems that we encounter in our lives, problems that arise as we seek to discover and achieve that which is of value in life. Rational problem-solving involves articulating our problems, proposing and criticizing possible solutions. It also involves breaking problems up into subordinate problems, creating a tradition of specialized problem-solving - specialized scientific, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  50.  54
    Rules for reasoning from knowledge and lack of knowledge.Douglas Walton - 2006 - Philosophia 34 (3):355-376.
    In this paper, the traditional view that argumentum ad ignorantiam is a logical fallacy is challenged, and lessons are drawn on how to model inferences drawn from knowledge in combination with ones drawn from lack of knowledge. Five defeasible rules for evaluating knowledge-based arguments that apply to inferences drawn under conditions of lack of knowledge are formulated. They are the veridicality rule, the consistency of knowledge rule, the closure of knowledge rule, the rule of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000