Results for 'inductive strength'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Absence Makes the Thought Grow Stronger: Reducing Structural Overlap Can Increase Inductive Strength.Hee Seung Lee & Keith J. Holyoak - 2008 - In B. C. Love, K. McRae & V. M. Sloutsky (eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  37
    The strength of sharply bounded induction.Emil Jeřábek - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (6):613-624.
    We prove that the sharply bounded arithmetic T02 in a language containing the function symbol ⌊x /2y⌋ is equivalent to PV1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  82
    The strength of sharply bounded induction requires M S P.Sedki Boughattas & Leszek Aleksander Kołodziejczyk - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (4):504-510.
    We show that the arithmetical theory -INDx5, formalized in the language of Buss, i.e. with x/2 but without the MSP function x/2y, does not prove that every nontrivial divisor of a power of 2 is even. It follows that this theory proves neither NP=coNP nor.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4.  48
    Some theories with positive induction of ordinal strength ϕω.Gerhard Jäger & Thomas Strahm - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):818-842.
    This paper deals with: (i) the theory ID # 1 which results from $\widehat{\mathrm{ID}}_1$ by restricting induction on the natural numbers to formulas which are positive in the fixed point constants, (ii) the theory BON(μ) plus various forms of positive induction, and (iii) a subtheory of Peano arithmetic with ordinals in which induction on the natural numbers is restricted to formulas which are Σ in the ordinals. We show that these systems have proof-theoretic strength φω 0.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5.  36
    On the strength of Ramsey's theorem without Σ1 -induction.Keita Yokoyama - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (1-2):108-111.
    In this paper, we show that equation image is a equation image-conservative extension of BΣ1 + exp, thus it does not imply IΣ1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  11
    On the proof-theoretic strength of monotone induction in explicit mathematics.Thomas Glaß, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Schlüter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (1):1-46.
    We characterize the proof-theoretic strength of systems of explicit mathematics with a general principle asserting the existence of least fixed points for monotone inductive definitions, in terms of certain systems of analysis and set theory. In the case of analysis, these are systems which contain the Σ12-axiom of choice and Π12-comprehension for formulas without set parameters. In the case of set theory, these are systems containing the Kripke-Platek axioms for a recursively inaccessible universe together with the existence of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  15
    Some Theories with Positive Induction of Ordinal Strength $varphiomega 0$.Gerhard Jager & Thomas Strahm - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):818-842.
    This paper deals with: (i) the theory $\mathrm{ID}^{\tt\#}_1$ which results from $\widehat{\mathrm{ID}}_1$ by restricting induction on the natural numbers to formulas which are positive in the fixed point constants, (ii) the theory $\mathrm{BON}(\mu)$ plus various forms of positive induction, and (iii) a subtheory of Peano arithmetic with ordinals in which induction on the natural numbers is restricted to formulas which are $\Sigma$ in the ordinals. We show that these systems have proof-theoretic strength $\varphi\omega 0$.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  29
    On the intuitionistic strength of monotone inductive definitions.Sergei Tupailo - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):790-798.
    We prove here that the intuitionistic theory $T_{0}\upharpoonright + UMID_{N}$ , or even $EEJ\upharpoonright + UMID_{N}$ , of Explicit Mathematics has the strength of $\prod_{2}^{1} - CA_{0}$ . In Section I we give a double-negation translation for the classical second-order $\mu-calculus$ , which was shown in [ $M\ddot{o}02$ ] to have the strength of $\prod_{2}^{1}-CA_{0}$ . In Section 2 we interpret the intuitionistic $\mu-calculus$ in the theory $EETJ\upharpoonright + UMID_{N}$ . The question about the strength of monotone (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  25
    Comparing the Strength of Diagonally Nonrecursive Functions in the Absence of Induction.François G. Dorais, Jeffry L. Hirst & Paul Shafer - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (4):1211-1235.
    We prove that the statement “there is aksuch that for everyfthere is ak-bounded diagonally nonrecursive function relative tof” does not imply weak König’s lemma over${\rm{RC}}{{\rm{A}}_0} + {\rm{B\Sigma }}_2^0$. This answers a question posed by Simpson. A recursion-theoretic consequence is that the classic fact that everyk-bounded diagonally nonrecursive function computes a 2-bounded diagonally nonrecursive function may fail in the absence of${\rm{I\Sigma }}_2^0$.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  6
    On the proof-theoretic strength of monotone induction in explicit mathematics.Thomas Glass, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Schlüter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (1):1-46.
  11.  7
    On the proof-theoretic strength of monotone induction in explicit mathematics.Thomas Glaß, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Schlüter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (1):1-46.
  12.  19
    Proof-theoretic strengths of weak theories for positive inductive definitions.Toshiyasu Arai - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (3):1091-1111.
  13.  46
    A note on Bar Induction in Constructive Set Theory.Michael Rathjen - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (3):253-258.
    Bar Induction occupies a central place in Brouwerian mathematics. This note is concerned with the strength of Bar Induction on the basis of Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory, CZF. It is shown that CZF augmented by decidable Bar Induction proves the 1-consistency of CZF. This answers a question of P. Aczel who used Bar Induction to give a proof of the Lusin Separation Theorem in the constructive set theory CZF.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  10
    Assessing the strength of angular induction using waveforms.Ernest Greene & Sabah Al-Quaddoomi - 1989 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 27 (3):245-248.
  15.  58
    Induction–recursion and initial algebras.Peter Dybjer & Anton Setzer - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (1-3):1-47.
    Induction–recursion is a powerful definition method in intuitionistic type theory. It extends inductive definitions and allows us to define all standard sets of Martin-Löf type theory as well as a large collection of commonly occurring inductive data structures. It also includes a variety of universes which are constructive analogues of inaccessibles and other large cardinals below the first Mahlo cardinal. In this article we give a new compact formalization of inductive–recursive definitions by modeling them as initial algebras (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  97
    Deductively Definable Logies of Induction.John D. Norton - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (6):617 - 654.
    A broad class of inductive logics that includes the probability calculus is defined by the conditions that the inductive strengths [A|B] are defined fully in terms of deductive relations in preferred partitions and that they are asymptotically stable. Inductive independence is shown to be generic for propositions in such logics; a notion of a scale-free inductive logic is identified; and a limit theorem is derived. If the presence of preferred partitions is not presumed, no inductive (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  18
    Deductively Definable Logics of Induction.John D. Norton - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (6):617-654.
    A broad class of inductive logics that includes the probability calculus is defined by the conditions that the inductive strengths [A|B] are defined fully in terms of deductive relations in preferred partitions and that they are asymptotically stable. Inductive independence is shown to be generic for propositions in such logics; a notion of a scale-free inductive logic is identified; and a limit theorem is derived. If the presence of preferred partitions is not presumed, no inductive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  59
    The strength of some Martin-Löf type theories.Edward Griffor & Michael Rathjen - 1994 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 33 (5):347-385.
    One objective of this paper is the determination of the proof-theoretic strength of Martin-Löf's type theory with a universe and the type of well-founded trees. It is shown that this type system comprehends the consistency of a rather strong classical subsystem of second order arithmetic, namely the one with Δ 2 1 comprehension and bar induction. As Martin-Löf intended to formulate a system of constructive (intuitionistic) mathematics that has a sound philosophical basis, this yields a constructive consistency proof of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  19.  18
    Transfinite induction within Peano arithmetic.Richard Sommer - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76 (3):231-289.
    The relative strengths of first-order theories axiomatized by transfinite induction, for ordinals less-than 0, and formulas restricted in quantifier complexity, is determined. This is done, in part, by describing the provably recursive functions of such theories. Upper bounds for the provably recursive functions are obtained using model-theoretic techniques. A variety of additional results that come as an application of such techniques are mentioned.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  20.  54
    The strength of Mac Lane set theory.A. R. D. Mathias - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 110 (1-3):107-234.
    Saunders Mac Lane has drawn attention many times, particularly in his book Mathematics: Form and Function, to the system of set theory of which the axioms are Extensionality, Null Set, Pairing, Union, Infinity, Power Set, Restricted Separation, Foundation, and Choice, to which system, afforced by the principle, , of Transitive Containment, we shall refer as . His system is naturally related to systems derived from topos-theoretic notions concerning the category of sets, and is, as Mac Lane emphasises, one that is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  21.  19
    On a Theory for AC0 and the Strength of the Induction Scheme.Satoru Kuroda - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (3):417-426.
    We define a fragment of Primitive Recursive Arithmetic by replacing the defining axioms for primitive recursive functions by those for functions in some specific complexity class. In this note we consider such theory for AC0. We present a model-theoretical property of this theory, by means of which we are able to characterize its provably total functions. Next we consider the problem of how strong the induction scheme can be in this theory.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Optimism about the pessimistic induction.Sherrilyn Roush - 2010 - In P. D. Magnus & Jacob Busch (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Science. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 29-58.
    How confident does the history of science allow us to be about our current well-tested scientific theories, and why? The scientific realist thinks we are well within our rights to believe our best-tested theories, or some aspects of them, are approximately true.2 Ambitious arguments have been made to this effect, such as that over historical time our scientific theories are converging to the truth, that the retention of concepts and claims is evidence for this, and that there can be no (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  23.  18
    Monotone inductive definitions in a constructive theory of functions and classes.Shuzo Takahashi - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 42 (3):255-297.
    In this thesis, we study the least fixed point principle in a constructive setting. A constructive theory of functions and sets has been developed by Feferman. This theory deals both with sets and with functions over sets as independent notions. In the language of Feferman's theory, we are able to formulate the least fixed point principle for monotone inductive definitions as: every operation on classes to classes which satisfies the monotonicity condition has a least fixed point. This is called (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  24.  57
    Argument Strength, the Toulmin Model, and Ampliative Probability.James B. Freeman - 2006 - Informal Logic 26 (1):25-40.
    We argue that Cohen’s concept of inductive or ampliative probability facilitates proper explication of sufficient strength for non-demonstrative arguments conforming to the Toulmin model. The data and claims of such arguments are singular statements. We may epistemically classify the warrants of such arguments as empirical (either physical or personal), institutional, or evaluative. Backing evidence and rebutting considerations vary with the epistemic type of warrant, but in each case the notion of ampliative probability for arguments with warrants of that (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  35
    Elementary inductive dichotomy: Separation of open and clopen determinacies with infinite alternatives.Kentaro Sato - 2020 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 171 (3):102754.
    We introduce a new axiom called inductive dichotomy, a weak variant of the axiom of inductive definition, and analyze the relationships with other variants of inductive definition and with related axioms, in the general second order framework, including second order arithmetic, second order set theory and higher order arithmetic. By applying these results to the investigations on the determinacy axioms, we show the following. (i) Clopen determinacy is consistency-wise strictly weaker than open determinacy in these frameworks, except (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  55
    A Hybrid Theory of Induction.Adrià Segarra - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    There are two important traditions in the philosophy of induction. According to one tradition, which has dominated for the last couple of centuries, inductive arguments are warranted by rules. Bayesianism is the most popular view within this tradition. Rules of induction provide functional accounts of inductive support, but no rule is universal; hence, no rule is by itself an accurate model of inductive support. According to another tradition, inductive arguments are not warranted by rules but by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  30
    Deductive, Probabilistic, and Inductive Dependence: An Axiomatic Study in Probability Semantics.Georg Dorn - 1997 - Verlag Peter Lang.
    This work is in two parts. The main aim of part 1 is a systematic examination of deductive, probabilistic, inductive and purely inductive dependence relations within the framework of Kolmogorov probability semantics. The main aim of part 2 is a systematic comparison of (in all) 20 different relations of probabilistic (in)dependence within the framework of Popper probability semantics (for Kolmogorov probability semantics does not allow such a comparison). Added to this comparison is an examination of (in all) 15 (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  37
    Strength or Nausea? Children’s Reasoning About the Health Consequences of Food Consumption.Damien Foinant, Jérémie Lafraire & Jean-Pierre Thibaut - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Children’s reasoning on food properties and health relationships can contribute to healthier food choices. Food properties can either be positive (“gives strength”) or negative (“gives nausea”). One of the main challenges in public health is to foster children’s dietary variety, which contributes to a normal and healthy development. To face this challenge, it is essential to investigate how children generalize these positive and negative properties to other foods, including familiar and unfamiliar ones. In the present experiment, we hypothesized that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. On the strength of Ramsey's theorem for pairs.Peter A. Cholak, Carl G. Jockusch & Theodore A. Slaman - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):1-55.
    We study the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of Ramsey's theorem for pairs. Let RT n k denote Ramsey's theorem for k-colorings of n-element sets, and let RT $^n_{ denote (∀ k)RT n k . Our main result on computability is: For any n ≥ 2 and any computable (recursive) k-coloring of the n-element sets of natural numbers, there is an infinite homogeneous set X with X'' ≤ T 0 (n) . Let IΣ n and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  30.  94
    A Survey of Inductive Generalization.John D. Norton - unknown
    Inductive generalization asserts that what obtains in known instances can be generalized to all. Its original form is enumerative induction, the earliest form of inductive inference, and it has been elaborated in various ways, largely with the goal of extending its reach. Its principal problem is that it supplies no intrinsic notion of strength of support so that one cannot tell if the generalization has weak or strong support.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  52
    Induction and Inductive Definitions in Fragments of Second Order Arithmetic.Klaus Aehlig - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (4):1087 - 1107.
    A fragment with the same provably recursive functions as n iterated inductive definitions is obtained by restricting second order arithmetic in the following way. The underlying language allows only up to n + 1 nested second order quantifications and those are in such a way, that no second order variable occurs free in the scope of another second order quantifier. The amount of induction on arithmetical formulae only affects the arithmetical consequences of these theories, whereas adding induction for arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32. Induction, more or less.Peter Smith - unknown
    The first main topic of this paper is a weak second-order theory that sits between firstorder Peano Arithmetic PA1 and axiomatized second-order Peano Arithmetic PA2 – namely, that much-investigated theory known in the trade as ACA0. What I’m going to argue is that ACA0, in its standard form, lacks a cogent conceptual motivation. Now, that claim – when the wraps are off – will turn out to be rather less exciting than it sounds. It isn’t that all the work that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  14
    The Strength of an Axiom of Finite Choice for Branches in Trees.G. O. H. Jun Le - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1367-1386.
    In their logical analysis of theorems about disjoint rays in graphs, Barnes, Shore, and the author (hereafter BGS) introduced a weak choice scheme in second-order arithmetic, called the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of finite choice (hereafter finite choice). This is a special case of the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of choice ( $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ ) introduced by Kreisel. BGS showed that $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ suffices for proving many of the aforementioned theorems in graph theory. While it is not known (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  31
    Sufficiency and Necessity Assumptions in Causal Structure Induction.Ralf Mayrhofer & Michael R. Waldmann - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (8):2137-2150.
    Research on human causal induction has shown that people have general prior assumptions about causal strength and about how causes interact with the background. We propose that these prior assumptions about the parameters of causal systems do not only manifest themselves in estimations of causal strength or the selection of causes but also when deciding between alternative causal structures. In three experiments, we requested subjects to choose which of two observable variables was the cause and which the effect. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  18
    Necessary use of [image] induction in a reversal.Itay Neeman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):561 - 574.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem (INDEC) states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis, and then, in the base system RCA₀ plus ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}$ induction, it was shown by Neeman to have strength strictly between weak ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ choice and ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{1}^{1}$ comprehension. We prove in this paper that ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ induction is needed (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  9
    Inductive Inferences on Galactic Redshift, Understood Materially.John D. Norton - 2023 - In Cristián Soto (ed.), Current Debates in Philosophy of Science: In Honor of Roberto Torretti. Springer Verlag. pp. 227-246.
    A two-fold challenge faces any account of inductive inference. It must provide means to discern which are the good inductive inferences or which relations capture correctly the strength of inductive support. It must show us that those means are the right ones. Formal theories of inductive inference provide the means through universally applicable formal schema. They have failed, I argue, to meet either part of the challenge. In their place, I urge that background facts in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. A Puzzle about Inferential Strength and Probability.Alexander Hughes - manuscript
    Inductive logic would be the logic of arguments that are not valid, but nevertheless justify belief in something like the way in which valid arguments would. Maybe we could describe it as the logic of “almost valid” arguments. There is a sort of transitivity to valid arguments. Valid arguments can be chained together to form arguments and such arguments are themselves valid. One wants to distinguish the “almost valid” arguments by noting that chains of “almost valid” arguments are weaker (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  36
    Assessing the Strengths and Weaknesses of Large Language Models.Shalom Lappin - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 33 (1):9-20.
    The transformers that drive chatbots and other AI systems constitute large language models (LLMs). These are currently the focus of a lively discussion in both the scientific literature and the popular media. This discussion ranges from hyperbolic claims that attribute general intelligence and sentience to LLMs, to the skeptical view that these devices are no more than “stochastic parrots”. I present an overview of some of the weak arguments that have been presented against LLMs, and I consider several of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  17
    The strength of choiceless patterns of singular and weakly compact cardinals.Daniel Busche & Ralf Schindler - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 159 (1-2):198-248.
    We extend the core model induction technique to a choiceless context, and we exploit it to show that each one of the following two hypotheses individually implies that , the Axiom of Determinacy, holds in the of a generic extension of : every uncountable cardinal is singular, and every infinite successor cardinal is weakly compact and every uncountable limit cardinal is singular.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. Inductive Logic.Franz Huber - 2008 - In J. Lachs R. Talisse (ed.), Encyclopedia of American Philosophy. Routledge.
    Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises and a conclusion. The quality of an argument depends on at least two factors: the truth of the premises, and the strength with which the premises confirm the conclusion. The truth of the premises is a contingent factor that depends on the state of the world. The strength with which the premises confirm the conclusion is supposed to be independent of the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. The largest countable inductive set is a mouse set.Mitch Rudominer - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):443-459.
    Let κ R be the least ordinal κ such that L κ (R) is admissible. Let $A = \{x \in \mathbb{R} \mid (\exists\alpha such that x is ordinal definable in L α (R)}. It is well known that (assuming determinacy) A is the largest countable inductive set of reals. Let T be the theory: ZFC - Replacement + "There exists ω Woodin cardinals which are cofinal in the ordinals." T has consistency strength weaker than that of the theory (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  18
    Richard Swinburne's Inductive Argument for the Existence of God – A Critical Analysis.Emma Beckman - unknown
    This essay discusses and criticizes Richard Swinburne's inductive argument for the existence of God. In his The Existence of God, Swinburne aims at showing that the existence of God is more probable than not. This is an argument taking into consideration the premises of all traditional arguments for the existence of God. Swinburne uses the phenomena and events that constitute the premises of these arguments as evidence in an attempt to show that his hypothesis is more probably true than (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  20
    Antonio Montalbán, Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 6 (2006), no. 1, pp. 89–120. - Itay Neeman, _The strength of Jullien’s indecomposability theorem_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 8 (2008), no. 1, pp. 93–119. - Itay Neeman, _Necessary use of_ _induction in a reversal. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76 (2011), no. 2, pp. 561–574. [REVIEW]Henry Towsner - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):366-368.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  47
    Explanatory coherence and the induction of properties.Steven A. Sloman - 1997 - Thinking and Reasoning 3 (2):81 – 110.
    Statements that share an explanation tend to lend inductive support to one another. For example, being told that Many furniture movers have a hard time financing a house increases the judged probability that Secretaries have a hard time financing a house. In contrast, statements with different explanations reduce one another s judged probability. Being told that Many furniture movers have bad backs decreases the judged probability that Secretaries have bad backs. I pose two questions concerning such discounting effects. First, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  38
    A note on the theory of positive induction, $${{\rm ID}^*_1}$$.Bahareh Afshari & Michael Rathjen - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (2):275-281.
    The article shows a simple way of calibrating the strength of the theory of positive induction, ${{\rm ID}^{*}_{1}}$ . Crucially the proof exploits the equivalence of ${\Sigma^{1}_{1}}$ dependent choice and ω-model reflection for ${\Pi^{1}_{2}}$ formulae over ACA 0. Unbeknown to the authors, D. Probst had already determined the proof-theoretic strength of ${{\rm ID}^{*}_{1}}$ in Probst, J Symb Log, 71, 721–746, 2006.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  29
    Shuttling Between Depictive Models and Abstract Rules: Induction and Fallback.Daniel L. Schwartz & John B. Black - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (4):457-497.
    A productive way to think about imagistic mental models of physical systems is as though they were sources of quasi‐empirical evidence. People depict or imagine events at those points in time when they would experiment with the world if possible. Moreover, just as they would do when observing the world, people induce patterns of behavior from the results depicted in their imaginations. These resulting patterns of behavior can then be cast into symbolic rules to simplify thinking about future problems and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  47.  38
    Statistical models for the induction and use of selectional preferences.Marc Light & Warren Greiff - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):269-281.
    Selectional preferences have a long history in both generative and computational linguistics. However, since the publication of Resnik's dissertation in 1993, a new approach has surfaced in the computational linguistics community. This new line of research combines knowledge represented in a pre‐defined semantic class hierarchy with statistical tools including information theory, statistical modeling, and Bayesian inference. These tools are used to learn selectional preferences from examples in a corpus. Instead of simple sets of semantic classes, selectional preferences are viewed as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Peirce on Inference: Validity, Strength, and the Community of Inquirers.Richard Kenneth Atkins - 2023 - New York City: Oxford University Press.
    Above all other titles, Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914) prized that of logician. He thought of logic broadly, such that it includes not merely formal logic but an examination of the entire process of inquiry. His works are replete with detailed investigations into logical questions. Peirce is especially concerned to show that valid inferential processes, diligently followed, will eventually root out error and alight on the truth. Peirce on Inference draws together diverse strands from Peirce's lifelong reflections on logic in order (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  46
    Weak systems of determinacy and arithmetical quasi-inductive definitions.P. D. Welch - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):418 - 436.
    We locate winning strategies for various ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}$ -games in the L-hierarchy in order to prove the following: Theorem 1. KP+Σ₂-Comprehension $\vdash \exists \alpha L_{\alpha}\ models"\Sigma _{2}-{\bf KP}+\Sigma _{3}^{0}-\text{Determinacy}."$ Alternatively: ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}\phantom{\rule{0ex}{0ex}}$ "there is a β-model of ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{3}^{1}-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}+\text{\hspace{0.17 em}}{\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}$ -Determinacy." The implication is not reversible. (The antecedent here may be replaced with ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\left({\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\right)-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}:\text{\hspace{0.17em}}{\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}$ instances of Comprehension with only ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}$ -lightface definable parameters—or even weaker theories.) Theorem 2. KP +Δ₂-Comprehension +Σ₂-Replacement + ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}\phantom{\rule{0ex}{0ex}}$ -Determinacy. (Here AQI (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  50. The formal equivalence of grue and green and how it undoes the new Riddle of induction.John D. Norton - unknown
    The hidden strength of Goodman's ingenious "new riddle of induction" lies in the perfect symmetry of grue/bleen and green/blue. The very same sentence forms used to define grue/bleen in terms of green/blue can be used to define green/blue in terms of grue/bleen by permutation of terms. Therein lies its undoing. In the artificially restricted case in which there are no additional facts that can break the symmetry, grue/bleen and green/blue are merely notational variants of the same facts; or, if (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000