Results for 'Presumed consent laws'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  75
    Presumed consent: State organ confiscation or mandated charity? [REVIEW]Paul M. Hughes - 2009 - HEC Forum 21 (1):1-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  59
    What is presumed when we presume consent?Barbara K. Pierscionek - 2008 - BMC Medical Ethics 9 (1):8.
    The organ donor shortfall in the UK has prompted calls to introduce legislation to allow for presumed consent: if there is no explicit objection to donation of an organ, consent should be presumed. The current debate has not taken in account accepted meanings of presumption in law and science and the consequences for rights of ownership that would arise should presumed consent become law. In addition, arguments revolve around the rights of the competent autonomous (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3. Consent for organ retrieval cannot be presumed.Mike Collins - 2009 - HEC Forum 21 (1):71-106.
  4.  26
    Defining Consent: Autonomy and the Role of the Family.Alberto Molina Pérez, Janet Delgado & David Rodriguez-Arias - 2021 - In Solveig Lena Hansen & Silke Schicktanz (eds.), Ethical Challenges of Organ Transplantation. Transcript Verlag. pp. 43-64.
    The ethics of deceased organ procurement (OP) is supposedly based on individual consent to donate, either explicit (opt-in) or presumed (opt-out). However, in many cases, individuals fail to express any preference regarding donation after death. When this happens, the decision to remove or not to remove their organs depends on the policy’s default option or on family preferences. Several studies show that in most countries the family plays a significant and often decisive role in the process of decision-making (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  8
    Could It Be Pretty Obvious There's No God?Stephen Law - 2009-09-10 - In Russell Blackford & Udo Schüklenk (eds.), 50 Voices of Disbelief. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 129–138.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Logical Problem of Evil The Evidential Problem of Evil The Evil God Hypothesis and the Problem of Good Reverse Theodicies Notes.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. European and comparative law study regarding family’s legal role in deceased organ procurement.Marina Morla-González, Clara Moya-Guillem, Janet Delgado & Alberto Molina-Pérez - 2021 - Revista General de Derecho Público Comparado 29.
    Several European countries are approving legislative reforms moving to a presumed consent system in order to increase organ donation rates. Nevertheless, irrespective of the consent system in force, family's decisional capacity probably causes a greater impact on such rates. In this contribution we have developed a systematic methodology in order to analyse and compare European organ procurement laws, and we clarify the weight given by each European law to relatives' decisional capacity over individual's preferences (expressed or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  56
    Placebo and criminal law.Jan C. Joerden - 2004 - Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (1):65-72.
    This article considers issues concerning cases where the use of placebo is lawful or is not lawful under aspects of German criminal law. It will differentiate between cases of individual therapy and cases of supervised experiments within the scope of medical tests. Thereby, it reveals that a medication of placebo with regard to an individual patient seems to be lawful if there is no alternative possibility of a better treatment using a chemically effective medicine and if the limits of (...) consent are complied with. On the other hand, in the context of the supervised experiment, the assignment of a patient to a group treated with placebo is only lawful if the patient has been fully informed about the possibilities of a treatment and if the patient has given consent to it. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  40
    Respect for Autonomy: Its Demands and Limits in Biobanking. [REVIEW]Iain Law - 2011 - Health Care Analysis 19 (3):259-268.
    This paper argues that the demands of respect for autonomy in the context of biobanking are fewer and more limited than is often supposed. It discusses the difficulties of agreeing a concept of autonomy from which duties can easily be derived, and suggests an alternative way to determine what respect for autonomy in a biobanking context requires. These requirements, it argues, are limited to provision of adequate information and non-coercion. While neither of these is in itself negligible, this is a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  46
    How Informed Is Online Informed Consent?Connie K. Varnhagen, Matthew Gushta, Jason Daniels, Tara C. Peters, Neil Parmar, Danielle Law, Rachel Hirsch, Bonnie Sadler Takach & Tom Johnson - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (1):37-48.
    We examined participants' reading and recall of informed consent documents presented via paper or computer. Within each presentation medium, we presented the document as a continuous or paginated document to simulate common computer and paper presentation formats. Participants took slightly longer to read paginated and computer informed consent documents and recalled slightly more information from the paginated documents. We concluded that obtaining informed consent online is not substantially different than obtaining it via paper presentation. We also provide (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  10.  11
    Achieving Informed Consent for Cellular Therapies: A Preclinical Translational Research Perspective on Regulations versus a Dose of Reality.Aileen J. Anderson & Brian J. Cummings - 2016 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 44 (3):394-401.
    A central principle of bioethics is “subject autonomy,” the acknowledgement of the primacy of the informed consent of the subject of research. Autonomy requires informed consent — the assurance that the research participant is informed about the possible risks and benefits of the research. In fact, informed consent is difficult when a single drug is being tested, although subjects have a baseline understanding of the testing of a pharmacological agent and the understanding that they can stop taking (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  45
    Presumed Consent for Pelvic Exams Under Anesthesia Is Medical Sexual Assault.Stephanie Tillman - 2023 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1):1-20.
    Unconsented pelvic exams under anesthesia are assaults cloaked in defense of healthcare education. Preemptive linguistic qualifiers “presumed” or “implied” attempt to justify such violations with flippancy toward their oxymoronic implications: to suggest a priori that consent can be assumed undermines its otherwise standalone social, ethical, and medico-legal reverence. In this paper I conceptualize “medical sexual assault” and argue that presumed consent for intimate exams exemplifies its definition. By bluntly describing pelvic exams as “penetration,” this work aims (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  42
    The New Belgian Law on Biobanks: Some Comments from an Ethical Perspective.Sigrid Sterckx & Kristof Van Assche - 2011 - Health Care Analysis 19 (3):247-258.
    On 19 December 2008 the Official Journal of Belgium published the ‘Law regarding the procurement and use of human body material destined for human medical applications or for scientific research purposes’. This paper will comment on various aspects of the Law: its scope of application (what is understood by ‘body material’?); its concept of ‘residual human body material’ (with far-reaching implications for the type of consent required for research); the nature of actions with and uses of human body material (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  30
    Human dignity and consent in research biobanking.D. G. Kirchhoffer & K. Dierickx - 2012 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 5 (2):74--77.
    Biobanking policy needs to take into account the concept of human dignity, because this concept is enshrined in both international and South African law. The accepted understanding of informed consent, which is also required by law, is inadequate for biobanking because it is often not possible to inform people of possible uses of their stored tissue. If human dignity is understood as a multidimensional concept that corresponds to the multidimensionality of the human person, then human dignity can be said (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Presumed consent, autonomy, and organ donation.Michael B. Gill - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (1):37 – 59.
    I argue that a policy of presumed consent for cadaveric organ procurement, which assumes that people do want to donate their organs for transplantation after their death, would be a moral improvement over the current American system, which assumes that people do not want to donate their organs. I address what I take to be the most important objection to presumed consent. The objection is that if we implement presumed consent we will end up (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  15.  28
    An Ethical Defense of a Mandated Choice Consent Procedure for Deceased Organ Donation.Xavier Symons & Billy Poulden - 2022 - Asian Bioethics Review 14 (3):259-270.
    Organ transplant shortages are ubiquitous in healthcare systems around the world. In response, several commentators have argued for the adoption of an opt-out policy for organ transplantation, whereby individuals would by default be registered as organ donors unless they informed authorities of their desire to opt-out. This may potentially lead to an increase in donation rates. An opt-out system, however, presumes consent even when it is evident that a significant minority are resistant to organ donation. In this article, we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  39
    Presumed consent for transplantation: a dead issue after Alder Hey?V. English - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (3):147-152.
    In the wake of scandals about the unauthorised retention of organs following postmortem examination, the issue of valid consent has returned to the forefront. Emphasis is put on obtaining explicit authorisation from the patient or family prior to any medical intervention, including those involving the dead. Although the controversies in the UK arose from the retention of human material for education or research rather than therapy, concern has been expressed that public mistrust could also adversely affect organ donation for (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  17.  45
    Presumed Consent: An International Comparison and Possibilities for Change in the United States.Kenneth Gundle - 2005 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 14 (1):113-118.
    Every day in the United States 17 people die waiting for an organ transplant. The waiting list for organs, which now contains the names of 82,000 people, has more than tripled in the last 10 years. The U.S. policy on who can donate an organ is based both on previous consent of the potential donor and on the consent of the donor's family. This foundation greatly limits the number of potential donors. Spain is the world's leader in providing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  8
    A presumed consent model for regulating Informed Consent of Genetic Research involving DNA Banking.B. Elger & Alexandre Mauron - 2003 - In Bartha Maria Knoppers (ed.), Populations and genetics: legal and socio-ethical perspectives. Boston: Martinus Nijhoff. pp. 269--95.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  30
    Fewer Mistakes and Presumed Consent.Alexander Zambrano - 2021 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 46 (1):58-79.
    “Opt-out” organ procurement policies based on presumed consent are typically advertised as being superior to “opt-in” policies based on explicit consent at securing organs for transplantation. However, Michael Gill has argued that presumed consent policies are also better than opt-in policies at respecting patient autonomy. According to Gill’s Fewer Mistakes Argument, we ought to implement the procurement policy that results in the fewest frustrated wishes regarding organ donation. Given that the majority of Americans wish to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  51
    Presumed consent in emergency neonatal research.D. J. Manning - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (4):249-253.
    Current methods of obtaining consent for emergency neonatal research are flawed. They risk aggravating the distress of parents of preterm and other sick neonates. This distress, and the inevitable time constraints, compromise understanding and voluntariness, essential components of adequately informed consent. Current practice may be unjust in over-representing babies of more vulnerable and deprived parents. The research findings may thus not be generalisable. Informing parents antenatally about the possible need for emergency neonatal research, with presumed consent (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  17
    Presumed Consent for Organ Procurement.Nicanor Pier Giorgio Austriaco - 2009 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 9 (2):245-252.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  31
    Ancient rites and new laws: how should we regulate religious circumcision of minors?Dena S. Davis - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (7):456-458.
    The ancient practice of metzitzah b'peh, direct oral suction, is still practiced by ultra-Orthodox Jews as part of the religious rite of male newborn circumcision. Between 2000 and 2011, 11 children have died in New York and New Jersey, following infection by herpes simplex virus, presumably from infected practitioners. The City responded by requiring signed parental consent before oral suction, with parents being warned of the dangers of the practice. This essay argues that informed consent is not an (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  17
    Presumed consent: licenses and limits inferred from the case of geriatric hip fractures.Joseph Bernstein, Drake LeBrun, Duncan MacCourt & Jaimo Ahn - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):17.
    Hip fractures are common and serious injuries in the geriatric population. Obtaining informed consent for surgery in geriatric patients can be difficult due to the high prevalence of comorbid cognitive impairment. Given that virtually all patients with hip fractures eventually undergo surgery, and given that delays in surgery are associated with increased mortality, we argue that there are select instances in which it may be ethically permissible, and indeed clinically preferable, to initiate surgical treatment in cognitively impaired patients under (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  88
    Presumed consent and organ donation.Hugh Upton - 2012 - Clinical Ethics 7 (3):142-146.
    This article explores the meaning and moral significance of presumed consent with particular reference to an opt-out policy for postmortem organ donation. It does so under two general categories: circumstances where we believe consent to have been given and those where we have no reason to believe that it has either been given or been refused. In the context of an opt-out policy, the first category would relate to the idea of tacit consent. It is argued (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  21
    Presumed Consent to Organ Donation in Three European Countries.Barbara L. Neades - 2009 - Nursing Ethics 16 (3):267-282.
    United Kingdom Transplant reported that, during 2007—2008, a total of 7655 people were awaiting a transplant; however, only 3235 organs were available via the current `opt in' approach. To address this shortfall, new UK legislation sought to increase the number of organs available for donation. The Chief Medical Officer for England and Wales supports the adoption of `presumed consent' legislation, that is, an `opt out' approach, as used in much of Europe. Little research, however, has explored the impact (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Presumed consent for organ retrieval.Arthur J. Matas & Frank J. Veith - 1984 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 5 (2).
  27.  23
    Is Presumed Consent the Answer to the Organ Shortage?Susan S. Mattingly, Robert E. Anderson, David Wendell Moller & Robert E. Stevenson - 1984 - Hastings Center Report 14 (6):49-50.
  28.  47
    Presumed consent or contracting out.C. A. Erin & J. Harris - 1999 - Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (5):365-366.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29.  82
    Presumed consent for organ preservation in uncontrolled donation after cardiac death in the United States: a public policy with serious consequences. [REVIEW]Joseph L. Verheijde, Mohamed Y. Rady & Joan McGregor - 2009 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4:1-8.
    Organ donation after cessation of circulation and respiration, both controlled and uncontrolled, has been proposed by the Institute of Medicine as a way to increase opportunities for organ procurement. Despite claims to the contrary, both forms of controlled and uncontrolled donation after cardiac death raise significant ethical and legal issues. Identified causes for concern include absence of agreement on criteria for the declaration of death, nonexistence of universal guidelines for duration before stopping resuscitation efforts and techniques, and assumption of (...) intent to donate for the purpose of initiating temporary organ-preservation interventions when no expressed consent to donate is present. From a legal point of view, not having scientifically valid criteria of cessation of circulation and respiration for declaring death could lead to a conclusion that organ procurement itself is the proximate cause of death. Although the revised Uniform Anatomical Gift Act of 2006 provides broad immunity to those involved in organ-procurement activities, courts have yet to provide an opinion on whether persons can be held liable for injuries arising from the determination of death itself. Preserving organs in uncontrolled donation after cardiac death requires the administration of life-support systems such as extracorporeal membrane oxygenation. These life-support systems can lead to return of signs of life that, in turn, have to be deliberately suppressed by the administration of pharmacological agents. Finally, allowing temporary organ-preservation interventions without expressed consent is inherently a violation of the principle of respect for a person's autonomy. Proponents of organ donation from uncontrolled donation after cardiac death, on the other hand, claim that these nonconsensual interventions enhance respect for autonomy by allowing people, through surrogate decision making, to execute their right to donate organs. However, the lack of transparency and the absence of protection of individual autonomy, for the sake of maximizing procurement opportunities, have placed the current organ-donation system of opting-in in great jeopardy. Equally as important, current policies enabling and enhancing organ procurement practices, pose challenges to the constitutional rights of individuals in a pluralistic society as these policies are founded on flawed medical standards for declaring death. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  31
    Presumed Consent Models and Health Information Exchanges: Hard Nudges and Ambiguous Benefits.Ricky T. Munoz, Mark D. Fox & Michael R. Gomez - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6):14-15.
  31.  34
    AID and the law.D. J. Cusine - 1975 - Journal of Medical Ethics 1 (1):39-41.
    The present state of the law is unsatisfactory. The exact effect on the marriage of the parties has not been decided although in English law if artificial insemination by donor (AID) takes place without consent that would appear to be a ground for divorce since 1969. The law regards a child born as a result of AID as illegitimate and draws no distinction between the case where the husband consents and where he does not. Theoretically, an offence is committed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Is Presumed Consent a Morally Permissible Policy for Organ Donation?James Delaney - 2017 - In Jason T. Eberl (ed.), Contemporary Controversies in Catholic Bioethics. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Why is (Claiming) Ignorance of the Law no Excuse?Miroslav Imbrisevic - 2010 - Review Journal of Political Philosophy 8 (1):57-69.
    In this paper I will discuss two aspects of ignorance of the law: ignorance of illegality (including mistaking the law) and ignorance of the penalty; and I will look at the implications for natives, for tourists and for immigrants. I will argue that Carlos Nino's consensual theory of punishment need to rely on two premises in order to justify that (claiming) ignorance of the law is no excuse. The first premise explains why individuals are presumed to 'know' current (...). The second premise explains why individuals are presumed to 'know' new legislation. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Normative consent and presumed consent for organ donation: a critique.M. Potts, J. L. Verheijde, M. Y. Rady & D. W. Evans - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (8):498-499.
    Ben Saunders claims that actual consent is not necessary for organ donation due to ‘normative consent’, a concept he borrows from David Estlund. Combining normative consent with Peter Singer's ‘greater moral evil principle’, Saunders argues that it is immoral for an individual to refuse consent to donate his or her organs. If a presumed consent policy were thus adopted, it would be morally legitimate to remove organs from individuals whose wishes concerning donation are not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  20
    Presuming Consent, Presuming Refusal: Organ Donation and Communal Structure. [REVIEW]Erich H. Loewy - 2000 - Health Care Analysis 8 (3):297-308.
    Donating, distributing and ultimately transplantingorgans each has distinct ethical problems. In thispaper I suggest that the first ethical question is notwhat should be done but what is a fair way in whicheach of these problems can be addressed. Experts –whether these be transplant surgeons, policy analysts,political scientists or ethicists – can help guidebut cannot by themselves make such decisions. Inmaking these decisions the difference betweenidentified and non-identified lives is crucial. Isuggest that an approach in which reason is temperedby compassion (``compassionate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  35
    Taylor on presumed consent.Timothy M. Wilkinson - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):638-639.
    In his précis, James Stacey Taylor sets out his full-blooded Epicureanism, which concludes that “death is not a harm to the person who dies and that persons can neither be harmed nor wronged by events that occur after their deaths.”1 He then considers various topics in bioethics in the light of his Epicureanism, one of which I consider here: presumed consent in the procurement of organs for transplantation. Although I do not accept Taylor's Epicureanism and although his examination (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  57
    A principlist approach to presumed consent for organ donation.Hannah Welbourn - 2014 - Clinical Ethics 9 (1):10-16.
    The demand for donor organs for transplantation in the UK far exceeds the supply. A number of improvements in the infrastructure surrounding organ donation, as well as attempts to increase public awareness, have been made over recent years, but there remains a massive shortfall. It has been proposed that a system of presumed consent for organ donation, in which all individuals are considered to be potential organ donors after death unless they have previously opted out, may serve to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. ""Parental Consent Laws: Are They a" Reasonable Compromise"?Mike Males - 1994 - In Alison M. Jaggar (ed.), Living with contradictions: controversies in feminist social ethics. Boulder: Westview Press. pp. 287--290.
  39.  26
    What does “presumed consent” might presume? Preservation measures and uncontrolled donation after circulatory determination of death.Pablo de Lora - 2014 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 17 (3):403-411.
    One of the most controversial aspects in uncontrolled donation of organs after circulatory death is the initiation of preservation measures before death. I argue that in so-called opting-out systems only under very stringent conditions we might presume consent to the instauration of those measures. Given its current legal framework, I claim that this is not the case of Spain, a well-known country in which consent is presumed—albeit only formally—and where uDCD is currently practiced.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  15
    Communitarianism and Presumed Consent.Zohar Lederman - 2014 - Asian Bioethics Review 6 (3):302-314.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. From Altruistic Donation to Conditional Societal Organ Appropriation After Death.Caroline Guibet Lafaye & Henri Kreis - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (2):355-368.
    Since we have learned that human organs can be used to treat severe health problems, only donation has been considered for organ procurement. Among the other possibilities that can be used after a person’s death, purchase or systematic removal have been a priori rejected. However, we will show that the appeal to individual altruism have resulted in some of the aporias of the present situation. Subsequently, we will consider how systematic organ removal from deceased persons can be made acceptable in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  16
    Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to Moral Law by Christopher J. Insole. [REVIEW]Chris L. Firestone - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (1):164-166.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to Moral Law by Christopher J. InsoleChris L. FirestoneChristopher J. Insole. Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to Moral Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020. Pp. v + 409. Hardback, $110.00.The extent to which the philosophy of Immanuel Kant converges with or diverges from Christian thought has been a hotly debated topic in recent years. Central to that debate has been the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  24
    Contested Organ Harvesting from the Newly Deceased: First Person Assent, Presumed Consent, and Familial Authority.Mark J. Cherry - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (5):603-620.
    Organ procurement policy from the recently deceased recasts families into gatekeepers of a scarce medical resource. To the frustration of organ procurement teams, families do not always authorize organ donation. As a result, efforts to increase the number of organs available for transplantation often seek to limit the authority of families to refuse organ retrieval. For example, in some locales if a deceased family member has satisfied the legal conditions for first-person prior assent, a much looser and easier standard to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  21
    Remapping the organ donation ethical climate: a care ethics consideration.Hui Yun Chan - 2020 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 23 (2):295-308.
    Organ donation has gained much attention as the need for transplant exceeds the supply of organs. Various proposals have been put forward to address the organ shortage challenge, ranging from offering incentives to donors, addressing family refusals to donations and instituting presumed consent laws. Presumed consent as the favoured approach has not been universally effective in increasing actual transplants despite its appeal. Few considerations have been given to the broader ethical climate influencing the organ donation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  47
    The organs crisis and the Spanish model: theoretical versus pragmatic considerations.M. Quigley, M. Brazier, R. Chadwick, M. N. Michel & D. Paredes - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (4):223-224.
    In the United Kingdom, the debate about how best to meet the shortfall of organs for transplantation has persisted on and off for many years. It is often presumed that the answer is simply to alter the law to a system of presumed consent. Acting perhaps on that presumption in his annual report launched in July, the Chief Medical Officer, Sir Liam Donaldson, advocated a system of organ donation based on presumed consent, the so-called “opt-out” (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  48
    Informed consent law, ethics, and practice: From infancy to reflective adolescence. [REVIEW]Roberta M. Berry - 2005 - HEC Forum 17 (1):64-81.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Consenting options for posthumous organ donation: presumed consent and incentives are not favored. [REVIEW]Muhammad M. Hammami, Hunaida M. Abdulhameed, Kristine A. Concepcion, Abdullah Eissa, Sumaya Hammami, Hala Amer, Abdelraheem Ahmed & Eman Al-Gaai - 2012 - BMC Medical Ethics 13 (1):32-.
    Background Posthumous organ procurement is hindered by the consenting process. Several consenting systems have been proposed. There is limited information on public relative attitudes towards various consenting systems, especially in Middle Eastern/Islamic countries. Methods We surveyed 698 Saudi Adults attending outpatient clinics at a tertiary care hospital. Preference and perception of norm regarding consenting options for posthumous organ donation were explored. Participants ranked (1, most agreeable) the following, randomly-presented, options from 1 to 11: no-organ-donation, presumed consent, informed (...) by donor-only, informed consent by donor-or-surrogate, and mandatory choice; the last three options ± medical or financial incentive. Results Mean(SD) age was 32(9) year, 27% were males, 50% were patients’ companions, 60% had ≥ college education, and 20% and 32%, respectively, knew an organ donor or recipient. Mandated choice was among the top three choices for preference of 54% of respondents, with an overall median[25%,75%] ranking score of 3[2,6], and was preferred over donor-or-surrogate informed consent (4[2,7], p vs. 11[6,11], respectively, p = 0.002). Compared to females, males more perceived donor-or-surrogate informed consent as the norm (3[1,6] vs. 5[3,7], p vs. 8[4,9], p vs. 5[2,7], p Conclusions We conclude that: 1) most respondents were in favor of posthumous organ donation, 2) mandated choice system was the most preferred and presumed consent system was the least preferred, 3) there was no difference between preference and perception of norm in consenting systems ranking, and 4) financial (especially in females) and medical (especially in males) incentives reduced preference. (shrink)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  72
    Personal autonomy, posthumous harm, and presumed consent policies for organ procurement.James Stacey Taylor - 2006 - Public Affairs Quarterly 20 (4):381-404.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  85
    Treatment without consent. Law, Psychiatry and the Treatment of Mentally Disordered People since 1845.G. E. Berrios - 1997 - Journal of Medical Ethics 23 (2):121-122.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  15
    Consent in the law.Deryck Beyleveld - 2007 - Oxford: Hart. Edited by Roger Brownsword.
    In a community that takes rights seriously, consent features pervasively in both moral and legal discourse as a justifying reason: stated simply, where there is consent, there can be no complaint. However, without a clear appreciation of the nature of a consent-based justification, its integrity, both in principle and in practice, is liable to be compromised. This book examines the role of consent as a procedural justification, discussing the prerequisites for an adequate consent -- in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000