Results for 'Part-whole theory'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  11
    Part 4 Beyond Social Wholes?Beyond Social Wholes - 2010 - In Ton Otto & Nils Bubandt (eds.), Experiments in holism: theory and practice in contemporary anthropology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  16
    Part 2 Beyond Cultural Wholes?Beyond Cultural Wholes - 2010 - In Ton Otto & Nils Bubandt (eds.), Experiments in holism: theory and practice in contemporary anthropology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Free part-whole theory.Peter M. Simons - 1991 - In Karel Lambert (ed.), Philosophical applications of free logic. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 285--306.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4. Parts, Wholes, and Part-Whole Relations: The Prospects of Mereotopology.Achille C. Varzi - 1996 - Data and Knowledge Engineering 20:259–286.
    We can see mereology as a theory of parthood and topology as a theory of wholeness. How can these be combined to obtain a unified theory of parts and wholes? This paper examines various non-equivalent ways of pursuing this task, with specific reference to its relevance to spatio-temporal reasoning. In particular, three main strategies are compared: (i) mereology and topology as two independent (though mutually related) chapters; (ii) mereology as a general theory subsuming topology; (iii) topology (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  5.  87
    The Part-Whole Perception of Emotion.Trip Glazer - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 58:34-43.
    A clever argument purports to show that we can directly perceive the emotions of others: (1) some emotional expressions are parts of the emotions they express; (2) perceiving a part of something is sufficient for perceiving the whole; (3) therefore, perceiving some emotional expressions is sufficient for perceiving the emotions they express. My aim in this paper is to assess the extent to which contemporary psychological theories of emotion support the first premise of this argument.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6.  65
    A Taxonomy of PartWhole Relations.Morton E. Winston, Roger Chaffin & Douglas Herrmann - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):417-444.
    A taxonomy of partwhole or meronymic relations is developed to explain the ordinary English‐speaker's use of the term “part of” and its cognates. The resulting classification yields six types of meronymic relations: 1. component‐integral object (pedal‐bike), 2. member‐collection (ship‐fleet), 3. portion‐mass (slice‐pie), 4. stuff‐object (steel‐car), 5. feature‐activity (paying‐shopping), and 6. place‐area (Everglades‐Florida). Meronymic relations ore further distinguished from other inclusion relations, such as spatial inclusion, and class inclusion, and from several other semantic relations: attribution, attachment, and ownership. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  7.  64
    Parts, Wholes, and Presence by Power A Response to Gordon P. Barnes.Michael Hector Storck - 2008 - Review of Metaphysics 62 (1):45-59.
    Gordon P. Barnes has recently argued that presence by power is inadequate as an explanation of the way elements are present in complex bodies, and that it would be better to explain the elements’ presence by claiming that simpler substances—carbon atoms, for example—are actually and substantially present in living things. In order to address his arguments, this paper begins by briefly presenting St. Thomas’s understanding of presence by power, and then argues that Barnes’s proposal—that there is a multiplicity of substantial (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Set Size and the PartWhole Principle.Matthew W. Parker - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic (4):1-24.
    Recent work has defended “Euclidean” theories of set size, in which Cantor’s Principle (two sets have equally many elements if and only if there is a one-to-one correspondence between them) is abandoned in favor of the Part-Whole Principle (if A is a proper subset of B then A is smaller than B). It has also been suggested that Gödel’s argument for the unique correctness of Cantor’s Principle is inadequate. Here we see from simple examples, not that Euclidean theories (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  9.  36
    Parts, Wholes, and Phenomenological Necessity.Adam Konopka - 2019 - In Iulian Apostolescu (ed.), The Subject(s) of Phenomenology. Rereading Husserl. Springer. pp. 17-30.
    This chapter reconstructs the account of the organization of unified definite manifolds that Husserl developed in his early logic of parts and wholes. I argue that Husserl’s conception of necessity gets fixed through the logic of fitness that is operative in his account of unified definite manifolds that are organized by symmetrical part/whole relations. Husserl’s logical account of necessity finds its ultimate justification in his theory of intentionality and is operative in his phenomenological methodology generally. Through this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Mereology as a theory of part-whole.Alexander Bochman - 1990 - Logique Et Analyse 129 (30):75-101.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Mereology as a Theory of Part-Whole.Alexander Bochman - 1990 - Logique Et Analyse 33 (29):75.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  6
    A Taxonomy of PartWhole Relations.Roger Chaffin - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):417-444.
    A taxonomy of partwhole or meronymic relations is developed to explain the ordinary English‐speaker's use of the term “part of” and its cognates. The resulting classification yields six types of meronymic relations: 1. component‐integral object (pedal‐bike), 2. member‐collection (ship‐fleet), 3. portion‐mass (slice‐pie), 4. stuff‐object (steel‐car), 5. feature‐activity (paying‐shopping), and 6. place‐area (Everglades‐Florida). Meronymic relations ore further distinguished from other inclusion relations, such as spatial inclusion, and class inclusion, and from several other semantic relations: attribution, attachment, and ownership. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13. Spatial Reasoning and Ontology: Parts, Wholes, and Locations.Achille C. Varzi - 2007 - In Marco Aiello, Ian E. Pratt-Hartmann & Johan van Benthem (eds.), Handbook of Spatial Logics. Springer Verlag. pp. 945-1038.
    A critical survey of the fundamental philosophical issues in the logic and formal ontology of space, with special emphasis on the interplay between mereology (the theory of parthood relations), topology (broadly understood as a theory of qualitative spatial relations such as continuity and contiguity), and the theory of spatial location proper.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  14. A visual representation of part-whole relationships in BFO-conformant ontologies.Jose M. Parente de Oliveira & Barry Smith - 2017 - In Á Rocha, A. M. Correia, H. Adeli, L. P. Reis & S. Costanzo (eds.), Recent Advances in Information Systems and Technologies (Advances in Intelligent Systems and Computing, 569). Springer. pp. 184-194.
    In the visual representation of ontologies, in particular of part-whole relationships, it is customary to use graph theory as the representational background. We claim here that the standard graph-based approach has a number of limitations, and we propose instead a new representation of part-whole structures for ontologies, and describe the results of experiments designed to show the effectiveness of this new proposal especially as concerns reduction of visual complexity. The proposal is developed to serve visualization (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  65
    Matrix representation of Husserl's part-whole-foundation theory.Richard Blecksmith & Gilbert Null - 1990 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32 (1):87-111.
  16.  37
    The Dispute Over the Part-Whole Puzzle in Aristotelian Hylomorphism and Ackrill’s Problem: The Argument in Metaphysics Z 17, 1041b11-33. [REVIEW]Christos Panayides - 2023 - Apeiron 56 (2):235-260.
    One of the unresolved issues in Aristotle’s hylomorphism is the part-whole puzzle. Some scholars suppose that in Metaphysics Z 17, 1041b11-33 he endorses non-mereological hylomorphism. This kind of interpretation, however, has been challenged by K. Koslicki who argues that if the evidence in Metaphysics Z 17 is combined with some related textual and conceptual considerations, then a convincing case can be made for a mereological construal of Aristotelian hylomorphism. This paper does four things. First, it scrutinizes these opposing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Developing the explanatory dimensions of partwhole realization.Ronald Endicott - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (12):3347-3368.
    I use Carl Gillett’s much heralded dimensioned theory of realization as a platform to develop a plausible partwhole theory. I begin with some basic desiderata for a theory of realization that its key terms should be defined and that it should be explanatory. I then argue that Gillett’s original theory violates these conditions because its explanatory force rests upon an unspecified “in virtue of” relation. I then examine Gillett’s later version that appeals instead to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  17
    Theory of the Whole and the Part – Ontological Perspective.Katarzyna Barska - 2015 - Studia Humana 4 (1):12-25.
    The purpose of the paper is demonstrate the thesis that Ingarden's ontological system allows a better understanding of the “part-whole” problem then previous theories. Especially, if we take into account the existential ontology of Ingarden, which refers to Husserl “part-wholetheory, we can see that development of terms made by Ingarden sheds new light on old problems. In this context, particularly important is to distinguish between two existential moments: contingancy/inseparatness, because thanks to them we can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The Whole-Part Dilemma: A Compositional Understanding of Plato’s Theory of Form.SeongSoo Park - forthcoming - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu.
    In this paper, I suggest a way of resolving the whole-part dilemma suggested in the Parmenides. Specifically, I argue that grabbing the second horn of the dilemma does not pose a significant challenge. To argue for this, I consider two theses about Forms, namely, the oneness and indivisibility theses. More specifically, I argue that the second horn does not violate the oneness thesis if we treat composition as identity and that the indivisibility thesis ought to be reinterpreted given (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Subjectivity as a Plurality: Parts and Wholes in Husserl's Theory of Intersubjectivity.Noam Cohen - 2023 - In Andrej Božič (ed.), Thinking Togetherness: Phenomenology and Sociality. Institute Nova Reijva for the Humanities. pp. 89-101.
    It is well-known that in the fifth of his Cartesian Meditations, Husserl puts forth a theory of intersubjectivity. Most commentators of Husserl have read his Cartesian Meditations as presenting a theory of intersubjectivity whose basis is empathy, in the form of a process of constituting the sense of “other” in one’s own experience, as the primary origin of the intersubjective layer of experience. In this paper, I claim that the structure of intersubjectivity as Husserl presents it in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  77
    The parts and the whole: Collapse theories and systems with identical constituents.GianCarlo Ghirardi - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (1):40-47.
    The very formal structure of quantum mechanics implies the loss of individuality of physical systems and it requires to look at the Universe as an unbroken whole. The main reason for which, within such a theory, one must renounce to a clear identification of the parts and the whole is the superposition principle which stays at the basis of the theory. It implies, as well known, the phenomenon of entanglement which, in the most extreme case, entails (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Parts and Wholes in Semantics.Friederike Moltmann - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book present a unified semantic theory of expressions involving the notions of part and whole. It develops a theory of part structures which differs from traditional (extensional) mereological theories in that the notion of an integrated whole plays a central role and in that the part structure of an entity is allowed to vary across different situations, perspectives, and dimensions. The book presents a great range of empirical generalizations involving plurals, mass nouns, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  23. Part Structures in Situations: The Semantics of 'Individual' and 'Whole'.Friederike Moltmann - 2005 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (5):599 - 641.
    This paper presents a theory of situated part structures involving the notion of an integrated and not just a part-of relation. The theory is applied in particular to the semantics of the modifiers 'whole' and 'individual', as in 'the whole collection' and 'the individual students'. The adnominal modifiers 'whole' and 'individual' have been entirely been ignored in the linguistic and philosophical literature, even though they pose significant challenges for standard views of reference, of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  28
    Agency, Goal-Directed Behavior, and Part-Whole Relationships in Biological Systems.Richard Watson - 2024 - Biological Theory 19 (1):22-36.
    In this essay we aim to present some considerations regarding a minimal but concrete notion of agency and goal-directed behavior that are useful for characterizing biological systems at different scales. These considerations are a particular perspective, bringing together concepts from dynamical systems, combinatorial problem-solving, and connectionist learning with an emphasis on the relationship between parts and wholes. This perspective affords some ways to think about agents that are concrete and quantifiable, and relevant to some important biological issues. Instead of advocating (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Shame and the Social Bond: Applying the Part/Whole Approach to a Case Study.Thomas J. Scheff - 2000 - Sociological Theory 18:86-99.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Spatial Continuity and the Theory of Part and Whole: A Brentano Study.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1992 - Brentano Studien 4:11-24.
    The concepts of a spatially continuous substance, of spatial dimension and of spatial boundary are here "analyzed out" of the concepts of individual thing, of constituent and of coincidence. The analysis is based upon the theory of spatial coincidence that was developed by Brentano. Its presuppositions are essentially these: (1) if there are spatial objects of any kind, then there are continuous spatial substances. (2) such substances are possibly such that they are not constituents of any individual thing; and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  27. Whole and part in mathematics.John L. Bell - 2004 - Axiomathes 14 (4):285-294.
    The centrality of the whole/part relation in mathematics is demonstrated through the presentation and analysis of examples from algebra, geometry, functional analysis,logic, topology and category theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28. On Husserl's Theory of Wholes and Parts.Ettore Casari - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (1):1-43.
    The strongly innovative theory of whole-parts relations outlined by Husserl in his Third logical Investigation—to which he attributed a basic value for his entire phenomenology—has recently attracted a renewed interest. Although many important issues have been clarified (especially by Kit Fine) the subject seems still worth being revisited. To this aim Husserlian universes are introduced. These are lower bounded distributive lattices endowed with a unary operation of defect and a binary relation of isogeneity. Husserl's contents are identified with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  29. Wholes and parts in general systems methodology.Martin Zwick - 2001 - In G. P. Wagner (ed.), The Character Concept in Evolutionary Biology. Academic Press. pp. 237--56.
    Reconstructability analysis (RA) decomposes wholes, namely data in the form either of set theoretic relations or multivariate probability distributions, into parts, namely relations or distributions involving subsets of variables. Data is modeled and compressed by variable-based decomposition, by more general state-based decomposition, or by the use of latent variables. Models, which specify the interdependencies among the variables, are selected to minimize error and complexity.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Indivisibles, Parts, and Wholes in Rubio’s Treatise on the Composition of Continuum (1605).Simone Guidi - 2022 - Bruniana and Campanelliana 1.
    In this paper I reconstruct and discuss Antonio Rubio (1546-1615)’s theory of the composition of the continuum, as set out in his Tractatus de compositione continui, a part of his influential commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, published in 1605 but rewritten in 1606. Here I attempt especially to show that Rubio’s is a significant case of Scholastic overlapping between Aristotle’s theory of infinitely divisible parts and indivisibilism or ‘Zenonism’, i.e. the theory that allows for indivisibles, extensionless points, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  50
    Husserl's theory of wholes and parts and the methodology of nursing research.Gary S. Schultz & Richard Cobb-Stevens - 2004 - Nursing Philosophy 5 (3):216-223.
    Whenever the name Edmund Husserl appears in the context of nursing research, what correctly comes to mind is the phenomenological approach to qualitative methodology. Husserl is not only considered the founder of phenomenology, but his broad concept development also contributed to the demise of positivism and inspired fruitful approaches to the social sciences. In this spirit of inspiration, it must be expressed that Husserl's theory of wholes and parts, and particularly his differentiation of parts into ‘pieces’ and ‘moments’, is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Parts and wholes. An inquiry into quantum and classical correlations.M. P. Seevinck - unknown
    ** The primary topic of this dissertation is the study of the relationships between parts and wholes as described by particular physical theories, namely generalized probability theories in a quasi-classical physics framework and non-relativistic quantum theory. ** A large part of this dissertation is devoted to understanding different aspects of four different kinds of correlations: local, partially-local, no-signaling and quantum mechanical correlations. Novel characteristics of these correlations have been used to study how they are related and how they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  33.  50
    Husserl's theory of wholes and parts and the methodology of nursing research.R. N. PhD & Richard Cobb-Stevens PhD - 2004 - Nursing Philosophy 5 (3):216–223.
  34.  13
    Towards a Platonic theory of wholes and parts.Ariel Meirav - 1997 - Dissertation, University of Edinburgh
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  55
    Whole-for-Part Metonymy as Classification Exploiting Functional Integrity.Alexandra Arapinis - 2013 - Linguistics and Philosophy.
    Since the early 80s, metonymy has progressively gained central stage in linguistic investigations. The advent of cognitive linguistics marked a new turn in the study of this trope conceived, not as a deviation from semantic conventions (contra classical rhetorical theories), but as a phenomenon rooted in non-language-specific mechanisms of conceptualization and structuring of the world. Focusing on the particular case of whole-for-part (WP) metonymy, the general stand of this presentation will be to argue for the need to re-inject (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  30
    "The whole is greater than the part." Mereology in Euclid's Elements.Klaus Robering - 2016 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 25 (3):371-409.
    The present article provides a mereological analysis of Euclid’s planar geometry as presented in the first two books of his Elements. As a standard of comparison, a brief survey of the basic concepts of planar geometry formulated in a set-theoretic framework is given in Section 2. Section 3.2, then, develops the theories of incidence and order using a blend of mereology and convex geometry. Section 3.3 explains Euclid’s “megethology”, i.e., his theory of magnitudes. In Euclid’s system of geometry, megethology (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37. Husserl's theory of parts and wholes: The dynamic of individuating and contextualizing interpretation —übergehen, abheben, ergänzungsbedürftigkeit.Jay Lampert - 1989 - Research in Phenomenology 19 (1):195-212.
  38.  47
    Parts and wholes: Liberal-communitarian tensions in democratic states.Eric Bredo - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (3):445–457.
    One source of tension within and between modern nation states derives from conflict between individual and cultural rights. Modern democracies have been built on ideas of individual liberty whose extensions to the rights of culturally distinctive groups to survival and acceptance can create normative and political conflict. Such tensions raise questions about the role of the state, the underlying theory legitimising liberal states, and the social aims of education. Philosophical aspects of such conflicts are explored in Kevin McDonough and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  4
    Parts and Wholes: Liberal-Communitarian Tensions in Democratic States.Eric Bredo - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (3):445-457.
    One source of tension within and between modern nation states derives from conflict between individual and cultural rights. Modern democracies have been built on ideas of individual liberty whose extensions to the rights of culturally distinctive groups to survival and acceptance can create normative and political conflict. Such tensions raise questions about the role of the state, the underlying theory legitimising liberal states, and the social aims of education. Philosophical aspects of such conflicts are explored in Kevin McDonough and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. When do parts form wholes? Integrated information as the restriction on mereological composition.Kelvin J. McQueen & Naotsugu Tsuchiya - forthcoming - Neuroscience of Consciousness.
    Under what conditions are material objects, such as particles, parts of a whole object? This is the composition question and is a longstanding open question in philosophy. Existing attempts to specify a non-trivial restriction on composition tend to be vague and face serious counterexamples. Consequently, two extreme answers have become mainstream: composition (the forming of a whole by its parts) happens under no or all conditions. In this paper, we provide a self-contained introduction to the integrated information (...) of consciousness (IIT). We show that IIT specifies a non-trivial restriction on composition: composition happens when integrated information is maximized. We compare the IIT-restriction to existing proposals and argue that the IIT-restriction has significant advantages, especially in response to the problems of vagueness and counterexamples. An appendix provides an introduction to calculating parts and wholes with a simple system. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  4
    Part 3 Beyond Structural Wholes?Collectives Encompassment - 2010 - In Ton Otto & Nils Bubandt (eds.), Experiments in holism: theory and practice in contemporary anthropology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 175.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  90
    Applications and limits of mereology. From the theory of parts to the theory of wholes.Massimo Libardi - 1994 - Axiomathes 5 (1):13-54.
    The discovery of the importance of mereology follows and does not precede the formalisation of the theory. In particular, it was only after the construction of an axiomatic theory of the part-whole relation by the Polish logician Stanisław Leśniewski that any attempt was made to reinterpret some periods in the history of philosophy in the light of the theory of parts and wholes. Secondly, the push for formalisation - and the individuation of mereology as a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  26
    Wholes, Parts, and Infinite Collections.P. O. Johnson - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (261):367 - 379.
    In his book, The Principles of Mathematics , the young Bertrand Russell abandoned the common-sense notion that the whole must be greater than its part, and argued that wholes and their parts can be similar, e.g. where both are infinite series, the one being a sub-series of the other. He also rejected the popular view that the idea of an infinite number is self-contradictory, and that an infinite set or collection is an impossibility. In this paper, I intend (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Introduction - Understanding Parts and Wholes: Medieval Mereology and Early Modern Matters.Simone Guidi - 2022 - Bruniana and Campanelliana 1 (2022).
    In this paper I reconstruct and discuss Antonio Rubio (1546-1615)’s theory of the composition of the continuum, as set out in his Tractatus de compositione continui, a part of his influential commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, published in 1605 but rewritten in 1606. Here I attempt especially to show that Rubio’s is a significant case of Scholastic overlapping between Aristotle’s theory of infinitely divisible parts and indivisibilism or ‘Zenonism’, i.e. the theory that allows for indivisibles, extensionless points, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  29
    Of Parts and Wholes.Barbara Fultner - 1998 - ProtoSociology 11:41-65.
    Pace Dummett, the issue between molecularism and holism does not turn on whether a meaning theory is compositional, but on how successful communication is conceived. Given a notion of partial understanding, molecularism escapes the two most prevalent objections against holism (learnability and communication). Holism, too, can escape these objections, provided we also grant the holist a notion of partial understanding and suitably amend our conception of successful communication.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Formalisation of Husserl’s Theory of Wholes and Parts.Peter Simons - 1982 - In Barry Smith (ed.), Parts and Moments. Studies in Logic and Formal Ontology. Philosophia Verlag. pp. 111-159.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  47.  37
    Mereology and the Sciences: Parts and Wholes in the Contemporary Scientific Context.Claudio Calosi & Pierluigi Graziani (eds.) - 2014 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This volume is the first systematic and thorough attempt to investigate the relation and the possible applications of mereology to contemporary science. It gathers contributions from leading scholars in the field and covers a wide range of scientific theories and practices such as physics, mathematics, chemistry, biology, computer science and engineering. Throughout the volume, a variety of foundational issues are investigated both from the formal and the empirical point of view. The first section looks at the topic as it applies (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48. The Role of Theory and Culture in Bioethics.Part Five - 2009 - In Sandra Shapshay (ed.), Bioethics at the movies. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 295.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  13
    The whole versus the sum of some of the parts: toward resolving the apparent controversy of clitoral versus vaginal orgasms.James G. Pfaus, Gonzalo R. Quintana, Conall Mac Cionnaith & Mayte Parada - 2016 - Socioaffective Neuroscience and Psychology 6.
    BackgroundThe nature of a woman’s orgasm has been a source of scientific, political, and cultural debate for over a century. Since the Victorian era, the pendulum has swung from the vagina to the clitoris, and to some extent back again, with the current debate stuck over whether internal sensory structures exist in the vagina that could account for orgasms based largely on their stimulation, or whether stimulation of the external glans clitoris is always necessary for orgasm.MethodWe review the history of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Co-Emergence of Parts and Wholes in Psychological Individuation.B. Scott - 2007 - Constructivist Foundations 2 (2-3):65-71.
    Purpose: The purpose of the paper is to provide a constructivist account of the "self as subject" that avoids the need for any metaphysical assumptions. Findings: The thesis developed in this paper is that the human "psychological individual," "self" or "subject" is an emergent within the nexus of human social interaction. With respect to psychological and social wholes (composites) there is no distinction between the form of the elements and the form of the composites they constitute i.e., all elements have (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000