Results for 'Concupiscence'

50 found
Order:
  1.  48
    Concupiscence and Moral Freedom in Augustine and before Augustine.Peter Burnell - 1995 - Augustinian Studies 26 (1):49-63.
  2. Karl rahner on concupiscence: Between aquinas and heidegger.Mario Ferrugia - 2005 - Gregorianum 86 (2):330-356.
    In recent years, Karl Rahner's theology of concupiscence as a «pre-ethical appetite» has been subjected to some negative criticism as «un-Thomistic» and as presupposing modern philosophy's dualistic understanding of being. The present essay tries to situate Rahner's interpretation within the theological context of the time when it was originally published; the major debate then was on the nature of the supernatural and the desiderium naturale videndi Deum. It then tries to reconstruct the usage Rahner himself made of Aquinas's theology (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  7
    On Love and Concupiscence: On the Virtue of Levinasian Love over Hegelian Love.Rylie Johnson - 2017 - PhaenEx 12 (1):18-33.
    The purpose of this paper is two-fold. First, I will argue that Levinas’ criticisms of Hegel are insufficient. Levinas’ accusation that Hegel’s system is totalitarian ignores the centrality of love in the latter’s work, which constitutes the ethical character of the State. Second, though, I will expand Levinas’ critique to encompass love. I argue that Hegelian love is an insufficient ground for ethics because it is, ultimately, a self-love. But, Levinasian love is sufficient, since it account for societal love, while (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. The Terrifying Concupiscence of Belonging: Noise and Evil in the Work of Michel Serres.Bryan Lueck - 2015 - Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 19 (1):249-267.
    In this paper I examine the conception of evil and the prescriptions for its mitigation that Michel Serres has articulated in his recent works. My explication of Serres’s argument centers on the claim, advanced in many different texts, that practices of exclusion, motivated by what he calls “the terrifying concupiscence of belonging,” are the primary sources of evil in the world. After explicating Serres’s argument, I examine three important objections, concluding that Serres overestimates somewhat the role of exclusion in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  1
    Sexuality and Concupiscence in Augustine.David F. Kelly - 1983 - The Annual of the Society of Christian Ethics 3:81-116.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  42
    Avicenna's concupiscence.Joep Lameer - 2013 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 23 (2):277-289.
    Philosophical and medical excellence notwithstanding, Avicenna was far from being an otherwordly person who buried himself in his books. He had an extraordinarily adventurous life and is reported to have been fond of good food, drink, and lovemaking. This article discusses the wellknown but quite unusual view that he died of having too much sex. A detailed analysis of the sources and a common-sense approach to some of their medical claims will show that this allegation is not supported by any (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  71
    Thomas Aquinas on the Basis of the Irascible-Concupiscible Division.Christopher A. Bobier - 2020 - Res Philosophica 97 (1):31-52.
    Thomas Aquinas divides the sensory appetite into two powers: the irascible and the concupiscible. The irascible power moves creatures toward arduous goods and away from arduous evils, while the concupiscible power moves creatures toward pleasant goods and away from non-arduous evils. Despite the importance of this distinction, it remains unclear what counts as an arduous good or evil, and why arduousness is the defining feature of the division. The aim of this paper is twofold. First, I argue that an arduous (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  14
    Aristotle’s Natural Wealth: The Role of Limitation in Thwarting Misordered Concupiscence.Skip Worden - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 84 (2):209-219.
    I argue that Aristotle's approach to the proper type of acquisition, use-value, want, and accumulation/storage of wealth is oriented less to excluding commercial activity, such as that of Aristotle's Athens, than to forestalling misordered concupiscence – the taking of an inherendy limited good for the unlimited, or highest, good. That is, his moral aversion to taking a means for an end lies behind his rendering of the sort of wealth that is natural. By stressing the limited nature of natural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  34
    A ordem da concupiscência e a grandeza do homem em Pascal Order of concupiscence and greatness of man in Pascal.Maria Isabel Limongi - 2006 - Trans/Form/Ação 29 (1):45-61.
    Pascal conceives the civil order as an order of conscupiscence, that is, an order produced and regulated by concupiscence. However, when exempting virtue from being the source of civil order, he does not advance the separation between politics and morals, but signals a new and problematic role to virtue in the interior of civil order - no more the role of producing it, but of judging it properly.Pascal concebe a ordem civil como uma ordem da concupiscência, isto é, uma (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  17
    Reconsidering Augustine on Marriage and Concupiscence.John C. Cavadini - 2017 - Augustinian Studies 48 (1-2):183-199.
    In the spirit of Augustine’s own “Reconsiderations,” and inspired by Peter Brown’s act of “reconsidering” in the Epilogue to Augustine of Hippo (new edition), this essay offers a reconsideration of Augustine’s work On Marriage and Concupiscence. Key to the reconsideration of this text is a reconsideration of the role of the “sacrament” of marriage in Augustine’s articulation and defense of the goods of marriage and of human sexuality. For Augustine, Julian’s advocacy of concupiscence as an innocent natural desire (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  39
    Reconsidering Augustine on Marriage and Concupiscence.John C. Cavadini - 2017 - Augustinian Studies 48 (1):183-199.
    In the spirit of Augustine’s own “Reconsiderations,” and inspired by Peter Brown’s act of “reconsidering” in the Epilogue to Augustine of Hippo, this essay offers a reconsideration of Augustine’s work On Marriage and Concupiscence. Key to the reconsideration of this text is a reconsideration of the role of the “sacrament” of marriage in Augustine’s articulation and defense of the goods of marriage and of human sexuality. For Augustine, Julian’s advocacy of concupiscence as an innocent natural desire amounts to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  43
    A ordem da concupiscência e a grandeza do homem em Pascal Order of concupiscence and greatness of man in Pascal.Maria Isabel Limongi - 2006 - Trans/Form/Ação 29 (1):45-61.
    Pascal concebe a ordem civil como uma ordem da concupiscência, isto é, uma ordem produzida e regulada pela concupiscência. Ao dispensar a virtude de ser o fundamento da ordem civil, ele não promove, contudo, a separação entre a política e a moral, mas assinala um novo e problemático papel para a virtude no interior da ordem civil - não mais o de produzi-la, mas o de julgá-la de modo apropriado. Pascal conceives the civil order as an order of conscupiscence, that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  64
    Aristotle’s Natural Wealth: The Role of Limitation in Thwarting Misordered Concupiscence[REVIEW]Skip Worden - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 84 (2):209 - 219.
    I argue that Aristotle's approach to the proper type of acquisition, use-value, want, and accumulation/storage of wealth is oriented less to excluding commercial activity, such as that of Aristotle's Athens, than to forestalling misordered concupiscence – the taking of an inherendy limited good for the unlimited, or highest, good. That is, his moral aversion to taking a means for an end lies behind his rendering of the sort of wealth that is natural. By stressing the limited nature of natural (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  26
    The conflict of freedom and concupiscence: A difficulty for Karl Rahner's theological anthropology.Dennis W. Jowers - 2012 - Heythrop Journal 53 (4):624-636.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  15
    Le marxisme, comme tentative de soustraire l'homme à la loi de la concupiscence déréglée — lex fomitis.Alphonse-Marie Parent - 1955 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 11 (2):149.
  16.  2
    Liberté, nécessité, contrainte chez Jansénius, Arnauld et Nicole.Michael Moriarty - 2015 - Archives de Philosophie 78 (1):111-130.
    Résumé Les théologiens jansénistes s’évertuent à réconcilier la thèse selon laquelle l’homme est assujetti à une nécessité générale de pécher avec le libre arbitre. Jansénius affirme que, malgré la nécessité générale, nous avons la liberté d’indifférence en ce qui concerne les actes particuliers ; mais il prétend aussi (en dépit d’Aristote) que la concupiscence, source des actes particuliers, se ramène à une forme de contrainte. Arnauld se contente d’affirmer la compatibilité de la nécessité générale de pécher avec l’indifférence, tandis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  31
    Does Augustine Contradict himself in Contra duas epistulas Pelagianorum?Ann A. Pang-White - 1999 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 73 (3):407-418.
    James Wetzel in his recent book argues that Augustine's statements in 'Contra duas epistulas Pelagianorum' (hereafter, 'C2EP'), especially that "(t)he apostles...were free from consent to evil desire," directly contradict his long-held anti-Pelagian thesis. For in 'C2EP' and his other anti-Pelagian works, Augustine apparently defends the thesis that in this earthly life every human being consents to concupiscence daily. Thus, all need God's forgiveness daily. This is, Augustine argues, the true meaning of the Lord's Prayer. But this seems to contradict (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  29
    Passions, virtue, and rational life.John Hacker-Wright - 2020 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 46 (2):131-140.
    Neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalists argue that moral norms are natural norms that apply to human beings. A central issue for neo-Aristotelians is to determine what belongs to the good human life; the question is complicated, since we take up a diversity of different lives, many of which seem good, and it seems unclear what the human species-characteristic life really is. The Aristotelian tradition gives some guidance on this question, however, because it describes us as rational animals with intellectual and appetitive powers; (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  37
    On Ultimate Ends: Aquinas’s Thesis that Loving God is Better than Knowing Him.Daniel Shields - 2014 - The Thomist 78 (4):581-607.
    I argue that, according to St. Thomas Aquinas, God--and not one's own happiness through union with God--is the ultimate end of the moral life strictly speaking. Although He is the source of happiness, God Himself, and not the happiness of knowing Him, is the center of the virtuous agent's life. Thus Aquinas, while incorporating all of the strengths of a virtue ethical framework, is not a eudaimonist in the normal sense, and is thus immune to any self-centeredness objections. I set (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  49
    The Paradox of Aquinas’s Altruism: From Self-Love to Love of Others.R. Mary Hayden - 1989 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 63:72-83.
    Aquinas argues that love of others depends on whether the other is seen as a person like oneself or as a tool of gratification. The former grounds love-of-friendship (altruistic love), the latter love-of-concupiscence. Seeing the other as a person like oneself enables one to love the other as another self, thereby, basing altruism ultimately on self-love.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  26
    Between Deleuze and Derrida (review).Mary Beth Mader - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (4):507-508.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Between Deleuze and DerridaMary Beth MaderPaul Patton and John Protevi, editors. Between Deleuze and Derrida. New York: Continuum, 2003. Pp. ix + 207. Cloth, $105.00. Paper, $29.95.One of the many provisions of Gilles Deleuze's prodigious philosophical invention, Difference and Repetition, is an ontological account of how invention is actual. That book itself is an instance of that of which it offers an account. An element of this account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  30
    'Learn virtue and toil'. Giovanni Pontano on passion, virtue and arduousness.Matthias Roick - 2011 - History of Political Thought 32 (5):732-750.
    In discussions of early-modern notions of passion and virtue, the humanist movement has played only a minor role. However, it has its own characteristics and approaches to the problem of passion and virtue. The moral philosophy of the Neapolitan humanist Giovanni Pontano is a case in point. Pontano pronounces himself against the Stoic doctrine of the eradication of the passions. Although his moral psychology follows traditional conceptions of the passions as subjected to the rule of reason, it rather illustrates the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  12
    "Concupiscience" and "Mimetic Desire": A Dialogue Between K. Rahner and R. Girard.Nikolaus Wandinger - 2004 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 11 (1):146-160.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:"CONCUPISCIENCE" AND "MIMETIC DESIRE": A DIALOGUE BETWEEN K. RAHNER AND R. GIRARD Nikolaus Wandinger Innsbruck University Since Augustine "concupiscence" has been the theological technical expression for the consequences that remain in all human persons subject to original sin. These consequences were often described as involuntary and uncontrollable desires or passions, especially in the realm ofsexuality. In the 1940s Karl Rahner revised that concept, freeing it from its narrow (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  20
    Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy (review).Richard A. Watson - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (1):168-169.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy by Susan JamesRichard A. WatsonSusan James. Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. Pp. vii + 318. Cloth, $35.00.Susan James shows how during the seventeenth century philosophers moved from the three souls of Aristotle and the tripartite soul of Thomas Aquinas in which passions and reasons compete for the attention of the will, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. The Augustinianism of Albert Camus' The Plague.Gene Fendt - 2020 - Heythrop Journal 61 (3):471-482.
    Camus himself called The Plague his most anti-Christian text, and most theologically oriented readings of the text agree. This paper shows how the sermons of Fr. Paneloux—an Augustine scholar--as well as Dr. Rieux’s mother present an Augustinian picture of love. This love opposes the passionate concupiscence for possession of things with the divine love which wishes for the constant conscious presence of the beloved in the light of the good. Such is possible for us, as Augustine exhibits and helps (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  41
    A ‘Chief Error’ of Protestant Soteriology: Sin in the Justified and Early Modern Catholic Theology.Matthew T. Gaetano - 2020 - Perichoresis 18 (6):41-72.
    Catholic theologians after Trent saw the Protestant teaching about the remnants of original sin in the justified as one of the ‘chief ’ errors of Protestant soteriology. Martin Luther, John Calvin, Martin Chemnitz, and many Protestant theologians believed that a view of concupiscence as sinful, strictly speaking, did away with any reliance on good works. This conviction also clarified the Christian’s dependence on the imputed righteousness of Christ. Catholic theologians condemned this position as detracting from the work of Christ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  5
    Après Les aveux de la chair: généalogie du sujet chez Michel Foucault.Sandra Boehringer & Laurie Laufer (eds.) - 2020 - Paris 14e: EPEL.
    Attraper erôs dans le filet du logos, l'Occident n'a pas attendu la psychanalyse pour s'y employer. Entre [es aphrodisia grecs et le dispositif de sexualité moderne, il ne restait plus à Foucault qu'à déposer une dernière pièce au puzzle de son Histoire de la sexualité : que s'est-il passé au temps de la concupiscence chrétienne et du péché de chair? Comment le sexe en est-il venu à polariser le rapport de soi à soi? 'Il m'a semblé, écrit Foucault, que (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  9
    Creating links without self-hood: Montaigne.Sylvia Giocanti - 2020 - Astérion 22.
    Si l’on conçoit le lien à la fois comme préexistant et nécessairement emprunté, il n’y a aucune nécessité à le valoriser socialement et politiquement selon le modèle de la fusion communautaire, où les individus ne feraient qu’un. Nous voudrions montrer à partir de cette considération, d’une part que Montaigne promeut une communauté de la différence, dans un bon usage de la conflictualité inhérente à l’ambivalence des désirs, d’autre part qu’il ne valorise pas pour autant l’organisation de la servitude dans le (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  5
    “Pecunia non olet”: The She-Wolf and Ambivalent Motherhood.Sibusiso Hyacinth Madondo - 2015 - Iris 36:57-60.
    La louve n’est pas seulement associée à la violence et à la terreur mais elle évoque également l’image de la mère nourricière et protectrice comme dans les légendes de Rémus et Romulus et de saint Ailbhe. Dans les deux légendes, des héros allaités par une louve grandissent pour devenir fondateurs : Rome pour Rémus et Romulus et le diocèse d’Emly pour saint Ailbhe. La louve est aussi liée à la débauche et à la luxure, et le bordel est nommé lupanar (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  24
    "Pride and Prejudice": Thought, Character, Argument, and Plot.Richard McKeon - 1979 - Critical Inquiry 5 (3):511-527.
    Justification for reading Pride and Prejudice as a philosophical novel may be found in its much cited and variously interpreted opening sentence: "It is a truth universally acknowledged, that a single man in possession of a good fortune, must be in want of a wife." This universal law is the first principle of a philosophical novel, although I shall also interpret it as the statement of a scientific law of human nature, a characterization of the civility of English society, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  7
    Œuvres morales.Pierre Nicole - 2015 - Paris: Éditions Manucius. Edited by Thibault Barrier & Denis Kambouchner.
    Publiés dans le dernier quart du XVIIe siècle, les Essais de morale de Pierre Nicole (1625-1695), l'un des auteurs les plus importants de Port-Royal, constituèrent pendant plus d'un siècle une référence incontournable de la pensée morale. Fort de leur succès immédiat, les Essais furent très vite republiés et enrichis par les éditeurs de textes posthumes et de lettres jusqu'à former un ensemble de vingt-cinq tomes en 1771. Pour introduire à la lecture d'un tel massif, le présent volume offre un choix (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  18
    Socrates and Diotima: sexuality, religion, and the nature of divinity.Andrea Nye - 2015 - New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Daemonic eros -- The work of love -- Beauty itself -- The spirit at the center of the world -- The highest one -- Demonizing the daemonic -- Saint Augustine and concupiscence of the flesh -- The eclipse of beauty -- Religion without God -- Social virtue -- The problem of evil -- Surviving death.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  11
    Children and Moral Agency.Cristina L. H. Traina - 2009 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 29 (2):19-37.
    CHILDREN ARE INCONSISTENTLY LABELED MORAL AGENTS IN SOME HIGHLY charged situations and denied that status in others. This essay draws on the writings of Nomy Arpaly, Lisa Tessman, and legal theorists to argue that both children and adults should nearly always be considered moral agents. But agency does not imply autonomy, ability to articulate rational reasons, or legal liability for either adults or children. Rather, all agents are dependent and conditioned. This quality divides them from a strict Augustinian vision in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    What Is a Desiring Man?Agustín Colombo - 2021 - Foucault Studies 29:71-90.
    This article investigates Foucault’s account of desiring man by drawing upon History of Sexuality vol. 4, Confessions of the Flesh. In order to do so, the article focuses on Foucault’s diagnosis of the Christian elaboration of “the analytic of the subject of concupiscence” that closes Confessions of the Flesh. As the article shows, “the analytic of the subject of concupiscence” inspires Foucault’s account of desiring man. However, Foucault’s diagnosis of the Christian elaboration of “the analytic of concupiscence (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  20
    Reflection on the Financial Crisis: Aquinas on the Proper Role of Finance.Mary L. Hirschfeld - 2015 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 35 (1):63-82.
    Aquinas's teachings on usury are difficult to apply directly to the modern economy given the tremendous transformations in economic institutions and sensibilities since his day. However, his treatment of the relationship between the abstraction of money and the problem of disordered concupiscent desire proves to be helpful in understanding modern financial instability. Money invites a disordered understanding of the infinite good that is the object of human desire, channeling that desire into the fruitless quest for indefinite accumulation, which is both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  56
    Augustine, Akrasia, and Manichaeism.Ann A. Pang-White - 2003 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 77 (2):151-169.
    This paper examines Augustine’s analysis of the possible causes of akrasia and suggests that an implicit two-phased consent process takes place in an akratic decision. This two-phased consent theory revolves around Augustine’s theory of the two wills, one carnal and the other spiritual. Without the help of grace, the fallen will dominated by the carnal will can only choose to sin. After exploration of this two-phased consent theory, the paper turns to examine the accusation made by Julian of Eclanum, a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  87
    On Reason’s Control of the Passions in Aquinas’s Theory of Temperance.Giuseppe Butera - 2006 - Mediaeval Studies 68 (1):133-160.
    Contrary to the fairly standard view of Aquinas on temperance according to which this virtue habituates the concupiscible appetite to move in ways that accord with reason spontaneously, that is, independently of any immediate command from reason, the author of this paper argues that temperance is a virtue which "(1) disposes the concupiscible appetite to remain more or less still in the absence of any command from reason to move, thus preventing vehement, spontaneous passions of any sort, ordinate or inordinate, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  15
    The Quarrel between Poetry and Philosophy in the Early Dialogues of St. Augustine.Michael P. Foley - 2015 - Philosophy and Literature 39 (1):15-31.
    After he was delivered from the necessity of making provision for the flesh in its concupiscence and after tendering his resignation as a professor of rhetoric, St. Augustine was, in the autumn of 386 a.d., eager to explore his newfound Christian faith and prepare for his reception into the Catholic Church. His conversion, momentous though it was, did not so much entail a repudiation of all that he had learned and studied as it did a transformation of what had (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  10
    Between the monster and the saint: reflections on the human condition.Richard Holloway - 2008 - Edinburgh: Canongate.
    1 MONSTER . . . evil is, not, as we thought, deeds that must be punished, but our lack of faith, our dishonest mood of denial, the concupiscence of the ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  5
    Confiteor. Le retour à soi dans les Confessions de saint Augustin.Emmanuel Housset - 2015 - Cahiers de Philosophie de L’Université de Caen 52:39-68.
    Par rapport à la conception réflexive du retour à soi propre à la philosophie du sujet telle qu’elle se développe de Hegel à Ricœur et qui cherche à surmonter la dispersion de la vie temporelle par une formation de soi dans l’unité d’une histoire, saint Augustin nous donne à penser une autre figure de l’ipséité qui permet d’échapper aux apories de la centration égologique comme à l’antihumanisme de ses contestations. L’histoire personnelle dans sa finitude et sa facticité ne peut trouver (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    The 2007 Meeting of the Society for Buddhist-Christian Studies: San Diego, California, November 16–17, 2007.Peter A. Huff - 2008 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 28:137-139.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The 2007 Meeting of the Society for Buddhist-Christian StudiesSan Diego, California, November 16–17, 2007Peter A. HuffThe Society for Buddhist-Christian Studies sponsored two sessions in conjunction with the 2007 annual meeting of the American Academy of Religion (AAR). Each session highlighted themes related to the work of a major figure in Buddhist-Christian dialogue. The first session, addressing the topic “Homosexuality, the Church, and the Sangha,” was organized in honor of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  92
    The Fall of Humanity: Weakness of the Will and Moral Responsibility in the Later Augustine.Ann A. Pang-White - 2000 - Medieval Philosophy and Theology 9 (1):51-67.
    Augustine of Hippo is often regarded as the champion of the doctrine of weakness of the will. John M. Rist in his 1994 'Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized' draws an interesting analogy between Aristotle's 'akrasia' and Augustine's 'concupiscentia'. However, such an analogy without further qualification is defective and misleading because it implies that Augustine commits himself to the notion that since everyone is perpetually akratic and, thus, always morally blameworthy. I argue that, for Augustine, weakness of the will has equivocal meanings (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  67
    Delectatio, gaudium, fruitio. Three Kinds of Pleasure for Three Kinds of Knowledge in Thomas Aquinas.Daniel De Haan - 2015 - Quaestio 15:543-552.
    This paper investigates Thomas Aquinas’s threefold division of pleasure into delectatio, gaudium, and fruitio, and its taxonomical basis in his threefold division of knowledge into tactility, the cogitative power, and the intellect. -/- Thomas Aquinas distinguishes three ways in which the sensory and intellectual appetites rest in the good. When the will rests in the intellectually apprehended good, this act is called fruitio; when the concupiscible appetite rests in a good apprehended by the internal senses this passion is called gaudium; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  54
    Paul Tillich's Realistic Stance Toward the Vital Trends of Nature.Eduardo R. Cruz - 2001 - Zygon 36 (2):327-334.
    Many scientists have argued forcefully for the pointlessness of nature, something that challenges any doctrine of Creation. However, apparent design and comprehensibility are also to be found in nature; it is ambivalent. This trait is nowhere more evident than in the natural inclinations that lead to concupiscence and the “seven deadly sins” in human beings. These inclinations are dealt with as pertaining to the “pre-fallen” condition of nature and human beings. As a framework to make sense of the goodness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  5
    Eating God.Patricia Grosse - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 21:17-21.
    In his biography on Augustine, Possidius writes: “His table was frugal and sparing, though indeed with the herbs and lentils he also had meats at times for the sake of his guests or for some of the weaker brethren”.1 Given the importance of friendship in Augustine’s life, it is not surprising that he ate meat for the sake of others and not for his own pleasures. However, Augustine spends much time in Book X of his Confessions obsessing over his delight (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  15
    L'ame et l'amour selon Malebranche.Jean-Louis Vieillard-Baron - forthcoming - Les Etudes Philosophiques.
    Malebranche ne dissocie jamais la théorie et la pratique. Son Traité de morale est une œuvre métaphysique. Ceci a sa raison dans les rapports entre la foi et la raison qui sont complémentaires. Le rapport de l'âme et de l'amour, conformément à une tradition platonicienne, est un lieu où l'on peut vérifier cette connexion. L'analyse de l'âme met en évidence la modernité de Malebranche dans sa conception de la conscience ou sentiment intérieur, où se révèle l'irréductibilité du sensible. L'amour est (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  51
    Search, rest, and grace in Pascal.Jennifer L. Soerensen - 2014 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 76 (1):19-40.
    For Pascal, how are human beings related, or how do they relate themselves, to the summum bonum in this life? In what sense do they share in it, and how do they come to share in it? These are questions that emerge in many ways in Pascal’s writing, significantly in his concept of repos. To answer these questions, especially by elucidating what repos is for human beings in this life, I would like to begin with Graeme Hunter’s “Motion and Rest (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    Mulla Sadrā and His Defense of the Ancients on the Soul.Sümeyye Parildar - 2022 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 26 (3):1235-1251.
    Mulla Sadrā refers to ancient Greek philosophers in his writings quite often, especially when the subject matter is the soul. In this article, I will address how Mulla Sadra reiterates Avicenna’s summary and analyses of ancient theories of the soul as discussed in Safar 4, Bab 5, and Fasl 5 of, al-Hikmat al-Mutaʿāliya fi asfār al-ʿaqliyyat al-arbaʿa. The source of these discussions, when the structure and basic contents are considered, is Aristotle’s De Anima Book I. Before defining the soul, Aristotle (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  3
    Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas’s Ethics. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 2001 - Review of Metaphysics 54 (4):905-905.
    In the introduction to this important study Bowlin draws attention to the fact that contemporary students of ethics often resort to Aristotle, but overlook Aquinas, one of the more able interpreters of the Aristotelian moral tradition. He intends to correct this situation by concentrating on a particular point of Thomas’s moral theory: the contingencies of various kinds which we must confront. Bowlin argues that Thomas’s treatment of the moral virtues is largely functional: they help to cope with contingencies, although he (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  19
    Robert Grosseteste on the Cross and Redemptive Love - With the Text of his Sermon on Galatians 5:24 and Notes its Reception. [REVIEW]J. Mcevoy - 1999 - Recherches de Theologie Et Philosophie Medievales 66 (2):289-315.
    In a sermon on the words of St Paul, «And they that are Christ's, have crucified their flesh, with the vices and concupiscences», Robert Grosseteste expressed that interior spirituality of the cross which he shared, notably, with the Franciscans. The sermon is located in his sermon-collection but it has not been edited or studied hitherto. Brief though it is, it merits publication and translation, for it instantiates its author's biblical and practical approach both to theology and to the interior life (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark