Results for 'B-Deduction'

998 found
Order:
  1.  40
    Is the transcendental deduction a patchwork?B. Lund Yates - 1930 - Mind 39 (155):318-331.
  2. Systems of Deduction Chapter 2:.B. G. Sundholm - unknown
  3. An operant analysis of problem solving.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):583-591.
    Behavior that solves a problem is distinguished by the fact that it changes another part of the solver's behavior and is strengthened when it does so. Problem solving typically involves the construction of discriminative stimuli. Verbal responses produce especially useful stimuli, because they affect other people. As a culture formulates maxims, laws, grammar, and science, its members behave more effectively without direct or prolonged contact with the contingencies thus formulated. The culture solves problems for its members, and does so by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  4.  79
    Bias in Human Reasoning: Causes and Consequences.Jonathan St B. T. Evans (ed.) - 1990 - Psychology Press.
    This book represents the first major attempt by any author to provide an integrated account of the evidence for bias in human reasoning across a wide range of disparate psychological literatures. The topics discussed involve both deductive and inductive reasoning as well as statistical judgement and inference. In addition, the author proposes a general theoretical approach to the explanations of bias and considers the practical implications for real world decision making. The theoretical stance of the book is based on a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   201 citations  
  5. Methods and theories in the experimental analysis of behavior.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):511-523.
    We owe most scientific knowledge to methods of inquiry that are never formally analyzed. The analysis of behavior does not call for hypothetico-deductive methods. Statistics, taught in lieu of scientific method, is incompatible with major features of much laboratory research. Squeezing significance out of ambiguous data discourages the more promising step of scrapping the experiment and starting again. As a consequence, psychologists have taken flight from the laboratory. They have fled to Real People and the human interest of “real life,” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  6.  37
    Natural Deduction Rules for Obligation.Frederic B. Fitch - 1966 - American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1):27 - 38.
  7.  57
    Uncertain deduction and conditional reasoning.Jonathan St B. T. Evans, Valerie A. Thompson & David E. Over - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
  8.  66
    Natural deduction rules for English.Frederic B. Fitch - 1973 - Philosophical Studies 24 (2):89 - 104.
    A system of natural deduction rules is proposed for an idealized form of English. The rules presuppose a sharp distinction between proper names and such expressions as the c, a (an) c, some c, any c, and every c, where c represents a common noun. These latter expressions are called quantifiers, and other expressions of the form that c or that c itself, are called quantified terms. Introduction and elimination rules are presented for any, every, some, a (an), and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. Kant's Conceptualism: a New Reading of the Transcendental Deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2018 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (3):464-488.
    I defend a novel interpretation of Kant's conceptualism regarding the contents of our perceptual experiences. Conceptualist interpreters agree that Kant's Deduction aims to prove that intuitions require the categories for their spatiality and temporality. But conceptualists disagree as to which features of space and time make intuitions require the categories. Interpreters have cited the singularity, unity, infinity, and homogeneity of space and time. But this is incompatible with Kant's Aesthetic, which aims to prove that these same features qualify space (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  11
    Search For Facts, Truth Or Enlightenment You Get Them All In the Big Tent of Tucson-2002-And Quantum Too.B. Faw - 2002 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (7):44-49.
    I have long concluded that psychologists seek 'facts' but don't care about 'truth'; while philosophers seek 'truth' but don't care about 'facts'. After attending Tucson-2002, I would create a third reckless stereotype: eastern philosophy seek 'enlightenment' but don't care about 'facts' or 'truth'. To avoid this seeming to be the equal-opportunity put-down that it really is, let me amend that to: scientists seek inductive 'facts' about consciousness, western philosophers seek deductive 'truth' about consciousness, and eastern philosophers seek transcendent 'enlightenment' - (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Kant’s Neglected Alternative and the Unavoidable Need for the Transcendental Deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2019 - Kantian Review 24 (1):127-152.
    The problem of Kant’s Neglected Alternative is that while his Aesthetic provides an argument that space and time are empirically real – in applying to all appearances – its argument seems to fall short of the conclusion that space and time are transcendentally ideal, in not applying to any things in themselves. By considering an overlooked passage in which Kant explains why his Transcendental Deduction is ‘unavoidably necessary’, I argue that it is not solely in his Aesthetic but more (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  15
    Cartesian Deduction.David B. Wong - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:1-19.
    The objective of the article is twofold: to advance an interpretation of Descartes’ position on the problem of explaining how deduction from universal propositions to their particular instances can be both legitimate and useful for discovery of truth; and to argue that his position is a valuable contribution to the philosophy of logic. In Descartes’ view. the problem in question is that syllogistic deductions from universal propositions to their particular instances is circular and hence useless as a means for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  31
    Cartesian Deduction.David B. Wong - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:1-19.
    The objective of the article is twofold: to advance an interpretation of Descartes’ position on the problem of explaining how deduction from universal propositions to their particular instances can be both legitimate and useful for discovery of truth; and to argue that his position is a valuable contribution to the philosophy of logic. In Descartes’ view. the problem in question is that syllogistic deductions from universal propositions to their particular instances is circular and hence useless as a means for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and his Transcendental Deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2015 - Kantian Review 20 (2):265-288.
    I argue for a novel, non-subjectivist interpretation of Kant’s transcendental idealism. Kant’s idealism is often interpreted as specifying how we must experience objects or how objects must appear to us. I argue to the contrary by appealing to Kant’s Transcendental Deduction. Kant’s Deduction is the proof that the categories are not merely subjectively necessary conditions we need for our cognition, but objectively valid conditions necessary for objects to be appearances. My interpretation centres on two claims. First, Kant’s method (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  84
    Kant on Representation and Objectivity.A. B. Dickerson - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a study of the second-edition version of the 'Transcendental Deduction', which is one of the most important and obscure sections of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. By way of a close analysis of the B-Deduction, Adam Dickerson makes the distinctive claim that the Deduction is crucially concerned with the problem of making intelligible the unity possessed by complex representations - a problem that is the representationalist parallel of the semantic problem of the unity of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  16.  70
    Reasoning to and from belief: Deduction and induction are still distinct.Jonathan St B. T. Evans & David E. Over - 2013 - Thinking and Reasoning 19 (3-4):267-283.
  17.  37
    J. B. Rosser and A. R. Turquette. Axiom schemes for m-valued functional calculi of first order. Part II. Deductive completeness. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 16 , pp. 22–34. See Errata, ibid., p. iv.Burton Spencer Dreben, J. B. Rosser & A. R. Turquette - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (4):269.
  18.  26
    Hintikka, deductive chains, and the consequences of knowing.Christopher B. Kulp - 1994 - Philosophia 23 (1-4):45-58.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  92
    Axioms and tests for the presence of minimal consciousness in agents I: Preamble.Igor L. Aleksander & B. Dunmall - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (4-5):7-18.
    This paper relates to a formal statement of the mechanisms that are thought minimally necessary to underpin consciousness. This is expressed in the form of axioms. We deem this to be useful if there is ever to be clarity in answering questions about whether this or the other organism is or is not conscious. As usual, axioms are ways of making formal statements of intuitive beliefs and looking, again formally, at the consequences of such beliefs. The use of this style (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  30
    Impossibility in the Prior Analytics and Plato's dialectic.B. Castelnérac - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (4):303-320.
    I argue that, in the Prior Analytics, higher and above the well-known ‘reduction through impossibility’ of figures, Aristotle is resorting to a general procedure of demonstrating through impossibility in various contexts. This is shown from the analysis of the role of adunaton in conversions of premises and other demonstrations where modal or truth-value consistency is indirectly shown to be valid through impossibility. Following the meaning of impossible as ‘non-existent’, the system is also completed by rejecting any invalid combinations of terms (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  11
    Quantifier Rules and Natural Deduction.Frederic B. Fitch - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):127-127.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  23
    Semantic Information Processing. [REVIEW]B. M. M. - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (2):353-353.
    Since the introduction of the computer in the early 1950's, the investigation of artificial intelligence has followed three chief avenues: the discovery of self-organizing systems; the building of working models of human behavior, incorporating specific psychological theories; and the building of "heuristic" machines, without bias in favor of humanoid characteristics. While this work has used philosophical logic and its results may illustrate philosophical problems, the artificial intelligence program is by now an intricate, organized specialty. This book, therefore, has a quite (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. A note on the deductive completeness of m-valued propositional calculi.J. B. Rosser & A. R. Turquette - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (4):219-225.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Kant and the Most Difficult Thing That Could Ever Be Undertaken on Behalf of Metaphysics.Justin B. Shaddock - 2014 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 31 (1).
    Kant calls his Transcendental Deduction "the most difficult thing that could ever be undertaken on behalf of metaphysics" (4:260). Readers have found it not just difficult but downright impossible. I will address two long-standing problems. First, Kant seems to contradict his conclusion at the outset of his proof. He does so in both the 1781 and 1787 editions of his Critique of Pure Reason. Second, Kant seems to argue for his single conclusion twice over in his Critique's 1787 edition. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25.  20
    A Theorem Concerning Syntactical Treatments Of Nonidealized Belief.Charles B. Cross - 2001 - Synthese 129 (3):335-341.
    In ‘Syntactical Treatments of Modality, with Corollaries on Reflexion Principles and Finite Axiomatizability’, Acta Philosophica Fennica16 (1963), 153–167, Richard Montague shows that the use of a single syntactic predicate (with a context-independent semantic value) to represent modalities of alethic necessity and idealized knowledge leads to inconsistency. In ‘A Note on Syntactical Treatments of Modality’, Synthese44 (1980), 391–395, Richmond Thomason obtains a similar impossibility result for idealized belief: under a syntactical treatment of belief, the assumption that idealized belief is deductively closed, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26.  27
    Another Defense of the Deductive Model.David B. Hausman - 1976 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):111-117.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  43
    Logical Form, Probability Interpretations, and the Inductive/Deductive Distinction.James B. Freeman - 1983 - Informal Logic 5 (2).
    Logical Form, Probability Interpretations, and the Inductive/Deductive Distinction.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28.  20
    E. J. Lemmon. Quantifier rules and natural deduction. Mind, n.s. vol. 70 , pp. 235–238.Frederic B. Fitch - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):127-127.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Logic, Inductive and Deductive. [REVIEW]B. H. Bode - 1909 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 6 (23):635-638.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Questions and challenges for the new psychology of reasoning.Jonathan St B. T. Evans - 2012 - Thinking and Reasoning 18 (1):5 - 31.
    In common with a number of other authors I believe that there has been a paradigm shift in the psychology of reasoning, specifically the area traditionally labelled as the study of deduction. The deduction paradigm was founded in a philosophical tradition that assumed logicality as the basis for rational thought, and provided binary propositional logic as the agreed normative framework. By contrast, many contemporary authors assume that people have degrees of uncertainty in both premises and conclusions, and reject (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  31.  96
    Justification, Objectivity, and Subjectivity in Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Justin B. Shaddock - 2012 - Southwest Philosophy Review 28 (1):177-185.
  32.  14
    Natural deduction.G. B. Keene - 1966 - Philosophical Books 7 (3):1-2.
  33. Here is the evidence, now what is the hypothesis? The complementary roles of inductive and hypothesis‐driven science in the post‐genomic era.Douglas B. Kell & Stephen G. Oliver - 2004 - Bioessays 26 (1):99-105.
    It is considered in some quarters that hypothesis‐driven methods are the only valuable, reliable or significant means of scientific advance. Data‐driven or ‘inductive’ advances in scientific knowledge are then seen as marginal, irrelevant, insecure or wrong‐headed, while the development of technology—which is not of itself ‘hypothesis‐led’ (beyond the recognition that such tools might be of value)—must be seen as equally irrelevant to the hypothetico‐deductive scientific agenda. We argue here that data‐ and technology‐driven programmes are not alternatives to hypothesis‐led studies in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  34.  28
    Peirce’s graphs amended.B. H. Slater - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (2):101-106.
    One of the claims made for C. S. Peirce's existential graphs has been that they are a deductively complete formulation of first-order logic with identity. As Peirce presented them, this is true only for certain versions of first-order logic :those which do not include terms for individuals. I amend Peirce's rules here, showing, in particular, how they are capable of demonstrating that, for instance, ?Jack is in the kitchen? contradicts ?Jack is not in the kitchen?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  11
    A Note on the Deductive Completeness of m-Valued Propositional Calculi.J. B. Rosser & A. R. Turquette - 1950 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):137-138.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  16
    The ethical concept of medicine as a profession discovery or invention?Laurence B. McCullough - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (12):786-787.
    Rosamond Rhodes makes a persuasive case for the view that medical ethics does not derive from common morality.1 Rhodes identifies the challenge that immediately arises and its corollary: Whence the origin of medical ethics? And, should we understand medical ethics as autonomous? From the perspective of professional ethics in medicine, the first question can now be restated: Whence the origin of the ethical concept of medicine as a profession, the basis of the ethical obligations of physicians in patient care, research, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. McDowell's germans: Response to 'on Pippin's postscript'.Robert B. Pippin - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):411–434.
    As McDowell makes clear in ‘On Pippin’s Postscript’ and in many other works, the interpretive question at issue in this exchange—how to understand the relation between Kant and Hegel, especially as that concerns Kant’s central ‘Deduction’ argument in the Critique of Pure Reason1—brings into the foreground an even larger problem on which all the others depend: the right way to understand at the highest level of generality the relation between active or spontaneous thought and our receptive and corporeal sensibility (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  5
    Techniques of Deductive Inference.G. B. Keene - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (67):179-180.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  4
    The deduction theorem in the combinatory theory of restricted generality.H. B. Curry - 1960 - Logique Et Analyse 3 (3):15-39.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  12
    The Deduction Theorem in the Combinatory Theory of Restricted Generality.Haskell B. Curry - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):468-469.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  25
    The Logic of Plurality. [REVIEW]B. W. A. - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (3):549-549.
    Among the quantificational notions neglected by classical logic are "many," "few," and "nearly all." Despite the apparent vagueness associated with these terms in ordinary discourse, in specific contexts we can and do draw strict inferences from statements in which they occur. In this pioneering work, Altham has attempted to uncover something of the formal logic that justifies such inferences. He begins by showing the mutual interdefinability of the three terms. If negation and any one of them are taken as primitive, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  58
    A consistent theory of attributes in a logic without contraction.Richard B. White - 1993 - Studia Logica 52 (1):113 - 142.
    This essay demonstrates proof-theoretically the consistency of a type-free theoryC with an unrestricted principle of comprehension and based on a predicate logic in which contraction (A (A B)) (A B), although it cannot holds in general, is provable for a wide range ofA's.C is presented as an axiomatic theoryCH (with a natural-deduction equivalentCS) as a finitary system, without formulas of infinite length. ThenCH is proved simply consistent by passing to a Gentzen-style natural-deduction systemCG that allows countably infinite conjunctions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  43.  31
    Variants of Gödel’s Ontological Proof in a Natural Deduction Calculus.B. Woltzenlogel Paleo & Annika Kanckos - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (3):553-586.
    This paper presents detailed formalizations of ontological arguments in a simple modal natural deduction calculus. The first formal proof closely follows the hints in Scott’s manuscript about Gödel’s argument and fills in the gaps, thus verifying its correctness. The second formal proof improves the first one, by relying on the weaker modal logic KB instead of S5 and by avoiding the equality relation. The second proof is also technically shorter than the first one, because it eliminates unnecessary detours and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  36
    A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason. [REVIEW]J. B. - 1960 - Review of Metaphysics 13 (4):698-698.
    This book, besides meeting a definite need in the field of Kantian ethical studies, is excellent. Professor Beck treats the Practical Reason as an exemplification of a general Kantian method applied to problems organic to the Kantian system as a whole. His interpretation of the 'Transcendental deduction' of the Principle of Pure Practical Reason is particularly brilliant; the Principle is shown to be established in precisely the form required for a complete resolution of the third antinomy of the Critique (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  77
    Why is Kant’s Transcendental Deduction So Difficult?Justin B. Shaddock - 2013 - Southwest Philosophy Review 29 (1):155-162.
  46.  30
    Kant’s Transcendental Deduction: An Analytical-Historical Commentary by Henry E. Allison.A. B. Dickerson - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (3):507-508.
    This is a monumental study of the transcendental deduction—that argument of legendary obscurity lying at the heart of Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Allison begins from the methodological precept that “Kant’s argument can best be understood in light of the internal development of his thought”, and his book thus provides a systematic historical account of the deduction and its emergence from earlier texts. It begins with two chapters on the major pre-critical writings, which trace the emergence of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  47
    Axiom schemes for m-valued functional calculi of first order: Part II. deductive completeness.J. B. Rosser & A. R. Turquette - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (1):22-34.
  48.  73
    Recent work on Kant's transcendental deduction.Justin B. Shaddock - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (2):401-410.
  49. The significance of taste: Kant, aesthetic and reflective judgment.Robert B. Pippin - 1996 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (4):549-569.
    The Significance of Taste: Kant, Aesthetic and Reflective Judgment ROBERT B. PIPPIN 1? THE FUNDAMENTAL QUESTION of the "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment" is easy enough to identify. On what basis, if any, could one claim some sort of universal a priori validity for judgments of the form, "This is beautiful"? In Kant's well-known analysis of this question, the issue is reformulated as: By what right could one claim that another person ought to feel pleasure (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50.  46
    The assessment of individual moral goodness.Raymond B. Chiu & Rick D. Hackett - 2016 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (1):31-46.
    In a field dominated by research on moral prescription and moral prediction, there is poor understanding of the place of moral perceptions in organizations alongside philosophical ethics and causal models of ethical outcomes. As leadership failures continue to plague organizational health and firms recognize the wide-ranging impact of subjective bias, scholars and practitioners need a renewed frame of reference from which to reconceptualize their current understanding of ethics as perceived in individuals. Based on an assessment and selection perspective from the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 998