马克思哲学与存在论问题

Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 17:303-344 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper begins with a discussion of the translations of the term “ontology” in Chinese language, and argues that its translation as “bentilun”(in Chinese PinYinorthography) can be supported by ample evidence from the history of doctrine and the tradition of Chinese culture. Therefore, It is necessary to keep this translation on condition that one distinguish strictly “ontology” as a branch of philosophy from “bentilun” as a special morphology of philosophical theory. Examining the history of metaphysics, this thesis draws a clear line of demarcation between “traditional ontology” and “modern ontology”, and reveals themain characteristics of traditional ontology. It holds that although the reformation of Marx’s Philosophy was realized through criticizing traditional ontology, his Philosophy did not abolish the concept of ontology as a branch of the discipline. The ontology of Marx’s philosophy is a theory that considers natural being, social being and human being as a unity. This theory emphasizes understanding the meaning of being from the perspective of a pattern. The main idea of ontology of Marx’s philosophy is that of a practical outlook and practical model of thinking. First, the concept of ontology and its translations would be reviewed. As regards itsderivation, we could find that Ontologie in German and in French both came from the word of Ontologia in Latin, which originated from the Greek. In the literal meaning of Greek,this word means the “logos” of “on”. In Greek, “on” corresponds to “being” in English. As to its signification, according to Heidegger, “on” has a twofold meaning that can signify both “being in general” and “the ground of being”. The former is close to essence while the latter to origin. From the angle ofhistory, Goclenius was the first one who used the term “Ontologia” in philosophy in 17th century. Since then this word was used and developed by subsequent philosophers. Although this term appeared in 17th century, yet its correlative questions had been studied from ancient Greece. The sticking point here is to pay attention to the demarcation between subject and theory. As a branch subject or as a universal noun, “Ontology” is counted in the historical tradition of western philosophy. Here all the problems discussed are public, but the concrete solutions and viewpoints are different. The former corresponds to the level of subject and the latter to the level of theory. These two levels must not be confused or substituted from one and other. That is, different ideas, schools and opinions could bebrought under the same problem. So it could be said that traditional ontology and modern ontology are two branches. Of course these two branches are very different in dealing with the problem of Ontology. This difference could be illustrated as following: (1) What to be→beings→substance —traditional ontology; (2) How to be→the mode of being→relation—modern ontology. Obviously both begin with the problem of being and end with Ontology, while their approaches are very different. The essential characteristic of traditional ontology is to seek the eternal substance, pursue the transcendent nature, establish the base of knowledge, and take the absolute truth as the ultimate telos. Traditional ontology ended with the critique of modern philosophy, Marxmade the crucial critique of traditional ontology in his remarks on Hegel’s philosophy. His critique of Hegel’s speculative method is actually the critique of traditional ontology although Marx himself never used the term of ontology explicitly in his new philosophy. Being in Marx’s philosophy is the real world of real beings. Concretely speaking, it is sensible world, objective world or human world that is integrated on the base of human praxis. The keystones here are natural being, social being and human being. There are some important similarities between Marx’s ontological approach and Heidegger’s ontology, that is, to understand the meaning of being through the mode and relation of being. In any case, the standpoint and thinking mode of praxis characterize the ontology of Marx’s philosophy.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,611

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Marx’s ontology of the praxis-relations of social production.Wujin Yu - 2009 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4 (3):400-416.
Marx's Ontology of the Praxis-Relations of Social Production.Yu Wujin & Kong Hui - 2009 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4 (3):400 - 416.
On Ontology.Roberta de Monticelli - 2003 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):171-186.
Language and ontology.Kanti Lal Das & Anirban Mukherjee (eds.) - 2008 - New Delhi: Northern Book Centre.
On Ontology Being a Philosophy Tendency.Cheng Long - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 17:275-296.
Ontological Frameworks for Scientific Theories.Jonas R. Becker Arenhart - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (4):339-356.
Logic and ontology.Thomas Hofweber - 2005 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
God as substance without substance ontology.von Wachter Daniel - 2007 - In Christian Kanzian & Muhammad Legenhausen (eds.), Substance and Attribute: Western and Islamic Traditions in Dialogue. Lancaster, LA: Ontos Verlag.
Critical Ontology: An Introductory Essay.Joseph Kaipayil - 2002 - Bangalore: Jeevalaya Institute of Philosophy.
Stuff versus individuals.Lucía Lewowicz & Olimpia Lombardi - 2012 - Foundations of Chemistry 15 (1):65-77.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-04-04

Downloads
45 (#356,447)

6 months
4 (#799,256)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Xuegong Yang
Peking University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references