COVID-19 and the Authority of Science

HEC Forum 35 (2):111-138 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In an attempt to respond effectively to the COVID-19 pandemic, policy makers and scientific experts who advise them have aspired to present a unified front. Leveraging the authority of science, they have at times portrayed politically favored COVID interventions, such as lockdowns, as strongly grounded in scientific evidence—even to the point of claiming that enacting such interventions is simply a matter of “following the science.” Strictly speaking, all such claims are false, since facts alone never yield moral-political conclusions. More importantly, attempts to present a unified front have led to a number of other actions and statements by scientists and policy makers that erode the authority of science. These include actions and statements that: (1) mislead the public about epidemiological matters such as mortality rates, cause of death determinations, and computerized modeling, or fail to correct mainstream media sources that interpret such concepts in misleading ways; (2) incorporate moral-political opinions into ostensible statements of fact; and (3) misrepresent or misuse scientific expertise. The fundamental thesis of the paper is not primarily that such actions and statements have proliferated during the COVID-19 epidemic (though I think they have), but rather that they are unscientific and that presenting them as science undermines the authority of science. In the moral-political realm, the great power of science and the source of its authority derives from its agnosticism about fundamental moral-political claims. Science, for instance, has no built-in presumption that we should respect life, promote freedom, or practice toleration; nor does it tell us which of these values to prioritize when values conflict. Because of this agnosticism, science is recognized across a broad diversity perspectives as morally and politically impartial, and authoritative within its proper sphere. When it is infused with partisan bias, it loses that authority.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,923

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Experience or authority? A response to Widdershoven.Vilhjálmur Árnason - 2000 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (2):191-193.
Rosamond Rhodes: The trusted doctor: medical ethics and professionalism.Caitlin Maples - 2022 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 43 (5):421-424.
The language of medicine and bioethics.Henk Have & Bert Gordijn - 2010 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (3):191-192.
The language of medicine and bioethics.Henk ten Have & Bert Gordijn - 2010 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (3):191-192.
Transplant Medicine as Borderline Medicine.Volker H. Schmidt - 2003 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 6 (3):319-321.
Ethics and genetics.Bmj Publishing Group Ltd And Institute Of Medical Ethics - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (3):170-170.
Medical humanities and philosophy of medicine.Wim Dekkers & Bert Gordijn - 2007 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10 (4):357-358.
Ethics and genetics: Advanced European bioethics course.Bert Gordijn - 2000 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3 (106):236-237.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-05-13

Downloads
15 (#971,366)

6 months
3 (#1,037,581)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?