Heidegger, Lafont and the necessity of the transcendental

Philosophy and Social Criticism 34 (5):557-574 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Cristina Lafont's recent reading of Heidegger offers a powerful formulation of the widespread view that once one recognizes our `facticity' and the role of language in shaping it, there is no room left to talk about transcendental structures of meaning or experience. In this article I challenge this view. I argue that Lafont inaccurately conflates what Heidegger calls our `understanding of being' with that which language discloses. In order to show that the philosophical motivation for this conflation is unsound, I also argue that Lafont's own positive theory of meaning itself tacitly assumes a distinction between factical and transcendental, and so rests on exactly what she finds problematic in Heidegger. This still leaves a puzzle as to how factical individuals are actually able to grasp anything transcendental, so I conclude by sketching Heidegger's method of `formal indication', which is meant to show precisely how this can be done.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,440

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Heidegger and the synthetic a-priori.Cristina Lafont - 2007 - In Steven Galt Crowell & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. pp. 104--118.
Heidegger's transcendentalism.Daniel Dahlstrom - 2005 - Research in Phenomenology 35 (1):29-54.
What's Formal about Formal Indication? Heidegger's Method in Sein und Zeit.R. Matthew Shockey - 2010 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (6):525-539.
Heidegger's transcendental phenomenology in the light of Husserl's project of First Philosophy.Dermot Moran - 2007 - In Steven Galt Crowell & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. pp. 135--150.
Disentangling Heidegger’s transcendental questions.Chad Engelland - 2011 - Continental Philosophy Review 45 (1):77-100.
Is Heidegger a Kantian idealist?William D. Blattner - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):185 – 201.
Heidegger, language, and world-disclosure.Cristina Lafont - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger's phenomenology as transcendental philosophy.Paul Gorner - 2002 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (1):17 – 33.
Heidegger and the Supposition of a Single, Objective World.Denis McManus - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):195-220.
The Metaphysics of Kantian Epistemology.Avery Goldman - 2002 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 76:239-252.
Questioning and the materiality of crisis: Freud and Heidegger.Jeffrey M. Jackson - 2007 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 33 (2):251-269.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
57 (#283,343)

6 months
3 (#984,658)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

R. Matthew Shockey
Indiana University South Bend

Citations of this work

What's Formal about Formal Indication? Heidegger's Method in Sein und Zeit.R. Matthew Shockey - 2010 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (6):525-539.
Heidegger's Descartes and Heidegger's Cartesianism.R. Matthew Shockey - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):285-311.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Sein und Zeit.Martin Heidegger - 1928 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 7:161-161.
Heidegger, language, and world-disclosure.Cristina Lafont - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.

View all 15 references / Add more references