Ought-implies-can: Erasmus Luther and R.m. Hare

Sophia 29 (1):2-30 (1990)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

l. There is an antinomy in Hare's thought between Ought-Implies-Can and No-Indicatives-from-Imperatives. It cannot be resolved by drawing a distinction between implication and entailment. 2. Luther resolved this antinomy in the l6th century, but to understand his solution, we need to understand his problem. He thought the necessity of Divine foreknowledge removed contingency from human acts, thus making it impossible for sinners to do otherwise than sin. 3. Erasmus objected (on behalf of Free Will) that this violates Ought-Implies-Can which he supported with Hare-style ordinary language arguments. 4. Luther a) pointed out the antinomy and b) resolved it by undermining the prescriptivist arguments for Ought-Implies-Can. 5. We can reinforce Luther's argument with an example due to David Lewis. 6. Whatever its merits as a moral principle, Ought-Implies-Can is not a logical truth and should not be included in deontic logics. Most deontic logics, and maybe the discipline itself, should therefore be abandoned. 7. Could it be that Ought-Conversationally-Implies-Can? Yes - in some contexts. But a) even if these contexts are central to the evolution of Ought, the implication is not built into the semantics of the word; b) nor is the parallel implication built into the semantics of orders; and c) in some cases Ought conversationally implies Can, only because Ought-Implies-Can is a background moral belief. d) Points a) and b) suggest a criticism of prescriptivism - that Oughts do not entail imperatives but that the relation is one of conversational implicature. 8. If Ought-Implies-Can is treated as a moral principle, Erasmus' argument for Free Will can be revived (given his Christian assumptions). But it does not 'prove' Pelagianism as Luther supposed. A semi-Pelagian alternative is available.

Similar books and articles

The lutheran influence on Kant’s depraved will.Dennis Vanden Auweele - 2013 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 73 (2):117-134.
Martin Luther on the bondage of the will.Martin Luther - 1957 - [Westwood, N.J.]: Revell. Edited by J. I. Packer & O. R. Johnston.
Rhetoric and reform: Erasmus' civil dispute with Luther.Marjorie O'Rourke Boyle - 1983 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Ought but Cannot.Wayne Martin - 2009 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1pt2):103 - 128.
Bondage of the will.Martin Luther - 2008 - Peabody, Mass.: Hendrickson Publishers.
The education of a Christian prince.Desiderius Erasmus - 1965 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Lisa Jardine, Neil M. Cheshire, Michael J. Heath & Desiderius Erasmus.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
1,159 (#10,808)

6 months
157 (#20,866)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Charles R. Pigden
University of Otago

Citations of this work

I Ought, Therefore I Can.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 136 (2):167-216.
The Feasibility of Collectives' Actions.Holly Lawford-Smith - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (3):453-467.
Does 'ought' conversationally implicate 'can'?Bart Streumer - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):219–228.

View all 9 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

On referring.Peter F. Strawson - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):320-344.
The Fragility of Goodness.Martha Nussbaum - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (7):376-383.
Logic and the Basis of Ethics.Arthur Norman Prior - 1949 - London, England: Oxford University Press.
Logic and the Basis of Ethics.Arthur N. Prior - 1955 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 17 (1):174-175.

View all 9 references / Add more references