The very idea of rational irrationality

Politics, Philosophy and Economics 23 (1):3-21 (2024)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

I am interested in the “rational irrationality hypothesis” about voter behavior. According to this hypothesis, voters regularly vote for policies that are contrary to their interests because the act of voting for them isn’t. Gathering political information is time-consuming and inconvenient. Doing so is unlikely to lead to positive results since one's vote is unlikely to be decisive. However, we have preferences over our political beliefs. We like to see ourselves as members of certain groups (e.g. “rugged individualists”) and being part of those groups depends on having certain beliefs (e.g. about welfare spending). Even if a decrease in welfare spending would be bad for me, I might still benefit by believing in and, consequently, voting for a decrease since my vote is unlikely to make a difference but getting to see myself as a rugged individualist will make a noticeable difference to my wellbeing. It is sometimes argued that this hypothesis fails for empirical reasons. I will argue that things are worse: it is conceptually incoherent. I will do so by first showing that it is a rationalizing explanation and then argue that rationalizing explanations must be reflectively stable from the agent's perspective. The rational irrationality hypothesis is not.

Similar books and articles

Rational Choice and Political Irrationality in the New Millennium.Tom Hoffman - 2015 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 27 (3-4):299-315.
Exploitation and Rational Choice.Loren King - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Political Science 44 (3):35–661.
Is Epistocracy Irrational?Adam F. Gibbons - 2022 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 21 (2).
Rational choice theory.William J. Goode - 1997 - American Sociologist 28 (2):22.
Reasoning as a Tool at the Service of our Goals.Amelia Gangemi - 2023 - In Alessandro Capone & Assunta Penna (eds.), Exploring Contextualism and Performativity: The Environment Matters. Springer Verlag. pp. 163-177.
The Normativity of Rationality.Benjamin Kiesewetter - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dissonance and Doxastic Resistance.Cristina Borgoni - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (5):957-974.
What rational choice explains.Robert E. Lane - 1995 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 9 (1-2):107-126.
The Ongoing Debate Over Political Ignorance: Reply to My Critics.Ilya Somin - 2015 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 27 (3-4):380-414.
Ruhelosigkeit, Phantasie und der Begriff des Geistes.Jonathan Lear - 2009 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 57 (1):49-71.
Reasons to Be Rational.Jens Gillessen - 2021 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 98 (3):359-394.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-05-27

Downloads
486 (#38,041)

6 months
428 (#4,068)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Spencer Paulson
Northwestern University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Wrong Kind of Reason.Pamela Hieronymi - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy 102 (9):437 - 457.
Doxastic deliberation.Nishi Shah & J. David Velleman - 2005 - Philosophical Review 114 (4):497-534.
A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism.James M. Joyce - 1998 - Philosophy of Science 65 (4):575-603.
Epistemic Teleology and the Separateness of Propositions.Selim Berker - 2013 - Philosophical Review 122 (3):337-393.
The aim of belief.Ralph Wedgwood - 2002 - Philosophical Perspectives 16:267-97.

View all 33 references / Add more references