The moral significance of risking

Legal Theory 18 (3):339-356 (2012)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

What makes careless conduct careless is easily one of the deepest and most contested questions in negligence law, tort theory, and moral theory. Answering it involves determining the conditions that make the imposition of risk unjustifiable, wrong, or impermissible. Yet there is a still deeper as well as overlooked and undertheorized question: Why does subjecting others to risk of harm call for justification in the first place? That risk can be impermissibly imposed upon otherspresupposes that imposing risk is the kind of thing that can be impermissible. Unless imposing risk can be impermissible after all, unjustified risking is literally impossible. In this discussion, I explore what I call the moral significance of risking, arguing that the moral significance of risking resides in a certain kind of nonmaterial autonomy interest that is implicated whenever one imposes risk of harm on another

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Moral Significance of Birth.José Luis Bermúdez - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):378 - 403.
Imposing Risk: A Normative Framework.John Oberdiek - 2017 - Oxford University Press UK.
Towards a right against risking.John Oberdiek - 2009 - Law and Philosophy 28 (4):367 - 392.
Intending, foreseeing, and the state.David Enoch - 2007 - Legal Theory 13 (2):69-99.
Disgust and Moral Taboos.John Kekes - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (262):431 - 446.
The moral significance of collective entities.Keith Graham - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (1):21 – 41.
The moral significance of gestures.René ten Bos - 2011 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 20 (3):280-291.
Prolegomena to a future phenomenology of morals.Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons - 2008 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (1):115-131.
Moreel toeval en symbolisch herstel.Arnold Burms - 2003 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 65 (4):615 - 626.
Humanizing Personhood.Adam Kadlac - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (4):421 - 437.
The importance of what they care about.Matthew Noah Smith - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (2):297-314.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-10-31

Downloads
136 (#136,536)

6 months
17 (#151,142)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

John Oberdiek
Rutgers - New Brunswick

Citations of this work

Sparing Civilians.Seth Lazar - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
Can a risk of harm itself be a harm?Thomas Rowe - 2022 - Analysis 81 (4):694-701.
Intergenerational justice.Lukas Meyer - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
A Right against Risk-Imposition and the Problem of Paralysis.Sune Holm - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (4):917-930.
Risk imposition and freedom.Maria P. Ferretti - 2016 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 15 (3):261-279.

View all 22 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The Fragmentation of Value.Thomas Nagel - 1979 - In Mortal questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Who Can Be Wronged?Rahul Kumar - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (2):99-118.
Desire and the Human Good.Richard Kraut - 1994 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 68 (2):315.
Subjective and objective.Thomas Nagel - 1979 - In Mortal questions. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 207-222.

View all 10 references / Add more references