The arts of action

Philosophers' Imprint 20 (14):1-27 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The theory and culture of the arts has largely focused on the arts of objects, and neglected the arts of action – the “process arts”. In the process arts, artists create artifacts to engender activity in their audience, for the sake of the audience’s aesthetic appreciation of their own activity. This includes appreciating their own deliberations, choices, reactions, and movements. The process arts include games, urban planning, improvised social dance, cooking, and social food rituals. In the traditional object arts, the central aesthetic properties occur in the artistic artifact itself. It is the painting that is beautiful; the novel that is dramatic. In the process arts, the aesthetic properties occur in the activity of the appreciator. It is the game player’s own decisions that are elegant, the rock climber’s own movement that is graceful, and the tango dancers’ rapport that is beautiful. The artifact’s role is to call forth and shape that activity, guiding it along aesthetic lines. I offer a theory of the process arts. Crucially, we must distinguish between the designed artifact and the prescribed focus of aesthetic appreciation. In the object arts, these are one and the same. The designed artifact is the painting, which is also the prescribed focus of appreciation. In the process arts, they are different. The designed artifact is the game, but the appreciator is prescribed to appreciate their own activity in playing the game. Next, I address the complex question of who the artist really is in a piece of process art — the designer or the active appreciator? Finally, I diagnose the lowly status of the process arts.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Dance Appreciation: The View from the Audience.Aili Bresnahan - 2017 - In David Goldblatt, Lee Brown & Stephanie Patridge (eds.), Aesthetics: A Reader in the Philosophy of the Arts, 4th edition. Routledge. pp. 347-350.
A Defense of Arts-Based Appreciation of Nature.Thomas Leddy - 2005 - Environmental Ethics 27 (3):299-315.
A Defense of Arts-Based Appreciation of Nature.Thomas Leddy - 2005 - Environmental Ethics 27 (3):299-315.
The Environment and the Arts.Arnold Berleant (ed.) - 2002 - Ashgate Press.
Improvisation in the Arts.Aili Bresnahan - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (9):573-582.
The Philosophy of the visual arts.Philip Alperson (ed.) - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
The Philosophy of the Visual Arts.Philip A. Alperson (ed.) - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press USA.
Games of Sport, Works of Art, and the Striking Beauty of Asian Martial Arts.Barry Allen - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 40 (2):241 - 254.
The aesthetic field.Arnold Berleant - 1970 - Springfield, Ill.,: Thomas.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-05-18

Downloads
5,341 (#981)

6 months
590 (#2,373)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

C. Thi Nguyen
University of Utah

Citations of this work

Value Capture.C. Thi Nguyen - forthcoming - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.
Autonomy and Aesthetic Valuing.Nick Riggle - forthcoming - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (I).
The opacity of play: a reply to commentators.C. Thi Nguyen - 2021 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 48 (3):448-475.
Phenomenal experience and the aesthetics of agency.Antonia Peacocke - 2021 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 48 (3):380-391.
The aesthetics of food.Alexandra Plakias - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 16 (11):e12781.

View all 8 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references