Deliberative Democratic Theory and “the Fact of Disagreement”

Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 5:73-86 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The development of the theory of deliberative democracy is connected to the completion of two tasks. The first is to combine broad political participation with the rationality of the political process. The second is to ensure the political unity of modern societies, which are characterized by a pluralism of often incompatible values, norms, and lifestyles. Within the framework of this theory, the key democratic procedure is rational deliberation open to all interested parties. The purpose of this procedure is to reach an agreement, as stated in the theory of Jurgen Habermas. However, experimental studies of deliberative practices show that they may result not in agreement but in the radicalization of positions. Unlike Habermas, John Rawls believes that a consensus on values and norms is unattainable. His theory of political liberalism attempts to answer the question of how political unity is possible in practically insoluble conflict, that is, in a situation of disagreement. He proposes the ideal of a well-ordered society with the assumption that a just society is one in which there is no agreement on comprehensive doctrines, but there is a consensus on the basic principles of justice. However, Rawls’s theory, in turn, faces a number of significant problems. For example, he was forced to admit that the democratic culture of society is a prerequisite for the formation of basic principles of justice in a well-ordered society. Rawls’s idea about the connections among disagreement, political freedom, and democracy influenced the further development of the theory of democracy, stimulating the search for different models of decision-making and the formation of political will without rational agreement. After all, the possibility of democracy lies in the conflict of ideas about justice and good.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,953

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On John Rawls and Public Reason.Jonah David Murdock - 1998 - Dissertation, Northwestern University
Political Liberalism.Charles Larmore - 1990 - Political Theory 18 (3):339-360.
Political Liberalism.John Rawls - 1993 - Columbia University Press.
Political Liberalism: Expanded Edition.John Rawls - 2005 - Columbia University Press.
Pluralism and consensus in deliberative democracy.José Luis Martí - 2017 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20 (5):556-579.
Emancipation or accommodation?Christian F. Rostbøll - 2008 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 34 (7):707-736.
The possibility of democratic socialism in Habermas.Pedro A. Teixeira - 2021 - European Journal of Social Theory 24 (4):601-618.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-01-10

Downloads
6 (#1,483,069)

6 months
3 (#1,045,430)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

The significance of deliberation for the legitimation of social institutions.Natalia Fialko - 2022 - Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 3:185-197.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
Kantian constructivism in moral theory.John Rawls - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (9):515-572.
The Law of Peoples.John Rawls - 1993 - Critical Inquiry 20 (1):36-68.
Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical.John Rawls - 1985 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (3):223-251.
Democracy and Disagreement.Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thompson - 1996 - Ethics 108 (3):607-610.

View all 15 references / Add more references