Spoof, Bluff, Go For It: A Defence of Spoofing

Journal of Business Ethics 189 (1):201-215 (2024)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Spoofing—placing orders on financial exchanges intending to withdraw them prior to execution—is widely legally prohibited. I argue instead on two main grounds that spoofing should be permitted and legalised. The first is that spoofing as a form of bluffing remains within the market practice of making legally binding offers—as opposed to lying or betraying trust—and primarily concerns the spoofer’s personal information. As a form of bluffing spoofing helps prevent financial speculators, in particular high-frequency algorithmic traders, from easily profiting by other market actors reliably revealing their underlying preferences through their market activity. The second is that at the systemic level permitting spoofing would benefit non-speculative actors who place orders to hedge economic risk and whose activities provide the raison d’être for financial exchanges, differentiating them from simple forums for gambling. I also address potential concerns that legalised spoofing would drive speculators out of financial markets entirely and, therefore, undermine market liquidity. This work contributes to the wider debate in business ethics regarding bluffing by illustrating the acceptability of bluffs which do not betray counterparty trust or reliance on testimony by remaining within the framework of market practices.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,100

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

You Can Bluff but You Should Not Spoof.Gil Hersch - 2020 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 39 (2):207-224.
Erratum: Applying the Principles of Gestalt Theory to Teaching Ethics.[author unknown] - 1991 - Journal of Business Ethics 10 (11):880-880.
Reviews. [REVIEW]Deborah C. Poff - 1983 - Journal of Business Ethics 2 (3):73-77.
Contents of Volume 40.[author unknown] - 2002 - Journal of Business Ethics 40 (4):405-407.
Contents of Volume 28.[author unknown] - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 28 (4):389-390.
Contents of Volume 59.[author unknown] - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 59 (4):415-416.
Contents of Volume 33.[author unknown] - 2001 - Journal of Business Ethics 33 (4):339-340.
Contents of Volume 43.[author unknown] - 2003 - Journal of Business Ethics 43 (4):397-398.
Contents of Volume 39.[author unknown] - 2002 - Journal of Business Ethics 39 (4):409-411.
Contents of Volume 62.[author unknown] - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 62 (4):419-421.
Call for Papers.[author unknown] - 2007 - Journal of Business Ethics 71 (2):107-107.
Contents of Volume 36.[author unknown] - 2002 - Journal of Business Ethics 36 (4):399-400.
Contents of Volume 51.[author unknown] - 2004 - Journal of Business Ethics 51 (4):397-399.
Contents of Volume 47.[author unknown] - 2003 - Journal of Business Ethics 47 (4):403-405.
Contents of Volume 27.[author unknown] - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 27 (4):393-394.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-12-01

Downloads
24 (#658,454)

6 months
17 (#149,054)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

After Virtue.A. MacIntyre - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46 (1):169-171.
Trust and antitrust.Annette Baier - 1986 - Ethics 96 (2):231-260.
Two concepts of rules.John Rawls - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):3-32.
Deciding to trust, coming to believe.Richard Holton - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (1):63 – 76.

View all 41 references / Add more references