Three Aspects of the Nature of Linguistic Meaning

Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology (1996)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This dissertation is in three chapters, each treating a different aspect of the nature of linguistic meaning. Together, they support the thesis that linguistic meaning is a non-naturalistic property which we can have reason to ascribe only to the expressions of public languages. ;The first chapter argues that meaning facts cannot be shown to be naturalistic facts by being shown to be reducible to teleological facts, and these in turn to naturalistic facts. Insofar as meaning facts can be reduced to teleological facts, it is because telelological facts are normative; insofar as teleological facts can be reduced to naturalistic facts, it is because they are non-normative. Fred Dretske, Ruth Garrett Millikan and Jerry Fodor are each criticized for missing this point. ;The second chapter concerns rule-following and meaning scepticism. A sceptical argument based on epistemological considerations is set out and contrasted with Saul Kripke's argument for the conclusion that there is never a fact as to what one means by one's expressions. It is argued that the epistemological argument has broader implications than Kripke's. A solution to the sceptical problem raised, which relates one's epistemological access to the meanings of linguistic expressions to communal uses of the expressions, is presented in outline. ;The third chapter develops the solution to the epistemological problem raised in the second chapter. The thesis that one's only epistemological access to the meanings of expressions is via communal use, is defended against two objections. The first objection is that, insofar as it can be shown that one cannot have reason to believe that one knows the meanings of the expressions of a language independently of knowing a community's uses of the expressions, it can also be shown that one cannot have reason to believe that one knows the meanings of a community's language. The second objection is that insofar as one can have reason to believe that one knows the meanings of the expressions of a language by knowing its communal uses, one can also have reason to believe that one knows them independently of any community. Each objection is responded to in turn

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,440

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Use theories of meaning.Marc Staudacher - 2010 - Dissertation, University of Amsterdam
Rule-Following Scepticism and the Individuation of Speaker's Meaning.Isaac Nevo - 1988 - Dissertation, University of California, Santa Barbara
Kripke’s Normativity Argument.José L. Zalabardo - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):467-488.
A new skeptical solution.Christopher Gauker - 1999 - Acta Analytica 14:113-129.
Causes as events and facts.Max Kistler - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (1):25–46.
Abductive Reasoning and Linguistic Meaning.Pasi Pohjola - 2006 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 14 (2):321-332.
On the Relation between Situation and the Meaning of Language.Zuo-li Wang - 2004 - Nankai University (Philosophy and Social Sciences) 6:48-53.
Theories of Meaning and Truth Conditions.Kathrin Glüer - 2012 - In Manuel García-Carpintero & Max Kölbel (eds.), The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Continuum International.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-04

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references