Gustav Teichmüller and the Systematic Significance of Studying the History of Concepts

Studia Philosophica Estonica 8 (2):129-140 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The history of concepts is relevant in philosophy because conceptual distinctions fundamentally shape cognition. Because these conceptual distinctions are deeply entrenched in our way of thinking, we are not usually aware of this influence. How we view the world depends crucially on the concepts we have. These concepts, however, are the products of their history. Following Herbart, Gustav Teichmüller viewed philosophy as the systematic analysis and refinement of concepts. Refining concepts in such a way allows us to make new distinctions, or to transform or abandon old ones. In contrast to Herbart, Teichmüller emphasized that this process presupposes detailed historical studies. This does not mean, however, that Teichmüller embraced a kind of historicism---the view that philosophy and its history are one and the same thing. On the contrary, he derogatorily referred to such a view as "historical psychology". Rather, the history of concepts in Teichmüller's sense has to be understood as a history of problems which are reflected in conceptual distinctions. This means that the history of concepts, which brings to light explicit and implicit distinctions, can be applied as a kind of hermeneutics of world views---as the basis on which we can systematically reconstruct concepts in a new light. It is the aim of this presentation to unfold such an understanding of the history of concepts in view of Teichmüller's contribution to it.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,674

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Concepts.Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Making sense of conceptual change.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2008 - History and Theory 47 (3):351-372.
Gold, jade, and emeruby: The value of naturalness for theories of concepts and categories.Charles Kalish - 2002 - Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 22 (1):45-66.
Les rapports du Platonisme et de l'Aristotélisme.Teichmüller Teichmüller - 1876 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 2:429.
Sur l'origine de la conscience.Teichmüller Teichmüller - 1887 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 24:107.
Sur les dialogues de Platon.Teichmüller Teichmüller - 1880 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 9:591.
Sur l'essence de l'amour.Teichmüller Teichmüller - 1882 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 14:240.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-04-28

Downloads
32 (#511,228)

6 months
6 (#572,748)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.David Bohm - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):377-379.
Neue Grundlegung der Psychologie und Logik.Gustav Teichmüller & Jakob Ohse - 2014 - Basel: Schwabe Verlag. Edited by Heiner Schwenke.
Religionsphilosophie.Gustav Teichmüller - 2014 - Basel: Schwabe Verlag. Edited by Heiner Schwenke.

View all 10 references / Add more references