“Surveyability” in Hilbert, Wittgenstein and Turing

Philosophies 8 (1):6 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

An investigation of the concept of “surveyability” as traced through the thought of Hilbert, Wittgenstein, and Turing. The communicability and reproducibility of proof, with certainty, are seen as earmarked by the “surveyability” of symbols, sequences, and structures of proof in all these thinkers. Hilbert initiated the idea within his metamathematics, Wittgenstein took up a kind of game formalism in the 1920s and early 1930s in response. Turing carried Hilbert’s conception of the “surveyability” of proof in metamathematics through into his analysis of what a formal system (what a step in a computation) is in “On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem” (1936). Wittgenstein’s 1939 investigations of the significance of surveyability to the concept of “proof “in Principia Mathematica were influenced, both by Turing’s remarkable everyday analysis of the Hilbertian idea, and by conversations with Turing. Although Turing does not use the word “surveyability” explicitly, it is clear that the Hilbertian idea plays a recurrent role in his work, refracted through his engagement with Wittgenstein’s idea of a “language-game”. This is evinced in some of his later writings, where the “reform” of mathematical notation for the sake of human surveyability (1944/45) may be seen to draw out the Hilbertian idea. For Turing, as for Wittgenstein, the need for “surveyability” earmarks the evolving culture of humans located in an evolving social and scientific world, just as it had for Hilbert.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,931

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Deviant encodings and Turing’s analysis of computability.B. Jack Copeland & Diane Proudfoot - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3):247-252.
Turing's golden: How well Turing's work stands today.Justin Leiber - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (1):13-46.
Turing, Wittgenstein, and the science of the mind.Jack Copeland - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (4):497-519.
Robots and Rule-following.Diane Proudfoot - 2004 - In Christof Teuscher (ed.), Alan Turing: Life and Legacy of a Great Thinker. Springer-Verlag. pp. 359-379.
Infinite time Turing machines.Joel David Hamkins - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (4):567-604.
The Turing test.B. Jack Copeland - 2000 - Minds and Machines 10 (4):519-539.
omnibus Review. [REVIEW]John Crossley - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1089-1090.
[Omnibus Review].John N. Crossley - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1089-1090.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-01-12

Downloads
31 (#531,821)

6 months
12 (#243,608)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Juliet Floyd
Boston University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Computing machinery and intelligence.Alan M. Turing - 1950 - Mind 59 (October):433-60.
The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (4):11-12.
Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik.D. Hilbert & W. Ackermann - 1928 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 7:157-157.
Philosophical Grammar.Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rush Rhees & Anthony Kenny - 1975 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 8 (4):260-262.

View all 27 references / Add more references