How chemistry shifts horizons: Element, substance, and the essential

Foundations of Chemistry 11 (2):65-77 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In 1931 eminent chemist Fritz Paneth maintained that the modern notion of “element” is closely related to (and as “metaphysical” as) the concept of element used by the ancients (e.g., Aristotle). On that basis, the element chlorine (properly so-called) is not the elementary substance dichlorine, but rather chlorine as it is in carbon tetrachloride. The fact that pure chemicals are called “substances” in English (and closely related words are so used in other European languages) derives from philosophical compromises made by grammarians in the late Roman Empire (particularly Priscian [fl. ~520 CE]). When the main features of the constitution of isotopes became clear in the first half of the twentieth century, the formal (IUPAC) definition of a “chemical element” was changed. The features that are “essential” to being an element had previously been “transcendental” (“beyond the sphere of consciousness”) but, by the mid-twentieth century the defining characteristics of elements, as such, had come to be understood in detail. This amounts to a shift in a “horizon of invisibility” brought about by progress in chemistry and related sciences. Similarly, chemical insight is relevant to currently-open philosophical problems, such as the status of “the bundle theory” of the coherence of properties in concrete individuals.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,592

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Response to Vollmer’s Review of Minds and Molecules.Eric Scerri - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (2):391-398.
Lavoisier and mendeleev on the elements.Robin Findlay Hendry - 2004 - Foundations of Chemistry 7 (1):31-48.
Chemical elements and the problem of universals.M. F. Sharlow - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 8 (3):225-242.
Elements, Compounds, and Other Chemical Kinds.Robin Findlay Hendry - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):864-875.
What is a chemical property?Nalini Bhushan - 2007 - Synthese 155 (3):293 - 305.
Conceptual Changes in Chemistry: The Notion of a Chemical Element, ca. 1900–1925.Helge Kragh - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 31 (4):435-450.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
91 (#186,766)

6 months
13 (#190,190)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Joseph E. Earley
Georgetown University

Citations of this work

Paneth, Kant, and the philosophy of chemistry.Klaus Ruthenberg - 2009 - Foundations of Chemistry 11 (2):79-91.
Editorial 37.Eric R. Scerri - 2011 - Foundations of Chemistry 13 (1):1-7.

View all 12 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Truth and truthmakers.D. M. Armstrong - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay About Substance Concepts.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 2000 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Qualitative Unity and the Bundle Theory.David Robb - 2005 - The Monist 88 (4):466-92.
Realism, Reduction and the “intermediate position”.Eric Scerri - 2000 - In Nalini Bhushan & Stuart Rosenfeld (eds.), Of Minds and Molecules: New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 51--72.
Relations and predicates.Herbert Hochberg & Kevin Mulligan (eds.) - 2013 - Lancaster, LA: Ontos Verlag.

View all 14 references / Add more references