The epistemic costs of compromise in bioethics

Bioethics 32 (2):111-118 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Bioethicists sometimes defend compromise positions, particularly when they enter debates on applied topics that have traditionally been highly polarised, such as those regarding abortion, euthanasia and embryonic stem cell research. However, defending compromise positions is often regarded with a degree of disdain. Many are intuitively attracted to the view that it is almost always problematic to defend compromise positions, in the sense that we have a significant moral reason not to do so. In this paper, we consider whether this common sense view can be given a principled basis. We first show how existing explanations for the problematic nature of compromise fall short of vindicating the common sense view, before offering our own explanation, which, we claim, comes closer to vindicating that view. We argue that defending a compromise will typically have two epistemic costs: it will corrupt attempts to use the claims of ethicists as testimonial evidence, and it will undermine standards that are important to making epistemic progress in ethics. We end by suggesting that the epistemic costs of compromise could be reduced by introducing a stronger separation between ethical debate aimed at fulfilling the epistemic role of ethics, and ethical debate that aims to directly produce good policy or practice.

Similar books and articles

Scoring Rules and Epistemic Compromise.Sarah Moss - 2011 - Mind 120 (480):1053-1069.
Integrity and compromise in nursing ethics.Gerald R. Winslow - 1991 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (3):307-323.
Can a compromise be fair?Peter Jones & Ian O’Flynn - 2013 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (2):115-135.
Compromise: a political and philosophical history.Alin Fumurescu - 2013 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Moral Compromise.David Archard - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (3):403-420.
The Nature of Moral Compromise.Barry Hoffmaster & Cliff Hooker - 2017 - Social Theory and Practice 43 (1):55-78.
Compromise and Its Limits.P. A. Scott - 1997 - Nursing Ethics 4 (2):147-157.
Integrity and compromise.Robert M. MacIver (ed.) - 1972 - Freeport, N.Y.,: Books for Libraries Press.
Google, Human Rights, and Moral Compromise.George G. Brenkert - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 85 (4):453-478.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-12-27

Downloads
394 (#51,023)

6 months
86 (#54,816)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Katrien Devolder
Oxford University
Thomas Douglas
University of Oxford

References found in this work

Principles of biomedical ethics.Tom L. Beauchamp - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by James F. Childress.
The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement.Tom Kelly - 2005 - In Tamar Szabo Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology Volume 1. Oxford University Press UK.
Creating and sacrificing embryos for stem cells.K. Devolder - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (6):366-370.
Bioethics and health and human rights: a critical view.D. Benatar - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (1):17-20.

View all 7 references / Add more references