Facticity and the Fate of Reason After Kant

Oxford University Press (forthcoming)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Kant’s science of the conditions of intelligibility leaves post-Kantians with a question: can a science of intelligibility tolerate brute facts? ‘Facticity’ is associated with phenomenology, for which the concept denotes underivable or brute conditions of intelligibility like temporality, sociality, and embodiment. While this suggests an affirmative answer to the post-Kantian question, scholars overlook that ‘facticity’ is a concept from German idealism, whose proponents answer the question in the negative. Fichte coins ‘facticity’ to denote the intolerable bruteness of conditions that are putatively presupposed by, and hence inexplicable limitations on, reason. A science of intelligibility must eliminate putative bruteness if it is to be systematic, as Fichte says, or presuppositionless, as Hegel says. Moreover, eliminating putative bruteness requires a new logic for deriving conditions of intelligibility from reason’s own contradictions, a dialectical logic that Fichte invents and Hegel develops. German idealism’s logical revolution subsequently provokes Heidegger’s phenomenological objection that dialectic presupposes brute conditions of the dialectician’s lived experience, conditions whose facticity dialectic inevitably reproduces and hence can only interpret hermeneutically. The heretofore untold history of the concept of facticity thus contains the deepest parting of the ways after Kant. On the one hand, Hegel eliminates vestigial facticity in Fichte’s system in his final step toward a presuppositionless science of intelligibility, although Schelling charges Hegel with presupposing both the value of science and the existence that science renders intelligible. On the other hand, Lask’s otherwise misleading reading of Fichte inspires Heidegger to reject the very idea of presuppositionlessness on behalf of a hermeneutics of facticity. The trajectory from German idealism via neo-Kantianism to phenomenology is accordingly one in which facticity begins as the obstacle to the science of intelligibility and ends as the character of the situation in which this science is possible in the first place. Within this trajectory and up to our own time, reason is fated to transform from the hand that unconditionally holds the world to the thrown activity of being in the world.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,998

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Concept of Fate in Hamlet.Feng Luo - 2010 - Modern Philosophy 4:101-107.
The Principle of Reason. [REVIEW]Richard Wolin - 1993 - Review of Metaphysics 47 (2):371-372.
Maurizio Ferraris’ Goodbye Kant[REVIEW]Tom Bailey - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2):pp. 328-330.
The concept of fate in mencius.Ning Chen - 1997 - Philosophy East and West 47 (4):495-520.
Fate and the fortune of the categories: Kant on the usurpation and schematization of concepts.Peter Thielke - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (5):438 – 468.
Le destin et la providence.Isabelle Koch - 2015 - Chôra 13 (9999):33-61.
Participative Reason as a Basis of a Decent Human World.Yuliya Shcherbina - 2017 - Dialogue and Universalism 27 (2):45-55.
Fate and humanity.Xunwu Chen - 2010 - Asian Philosophy 20 (1):67 – 77.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-08-01

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

G. Anthony Bruno
Royal Holloway University of London

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references