13 found

View year:

  1.  11
    Linguistic (and Ontological?) encounters between Plato and Karl Popper.Terezis Christos - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):01-28.
    In this study, I attempt to shed light on whether some passages from the Platonic dialogue Cratylus that deal with language correspond to Karl Popper’s theory on the third world. Specifically, I attempt to prove that Plato’s third world contains both divine and human properties, something that is provided through language, that is, through the human rational and developing in objective terms construction. In the four subchapters of my study, I basically investigate the relationship between the thinking subject and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  5
    O ponto de intersecção entre compostos naturais propriamente e não propriamente substanciais em Aristóteles.Rodrigo Romão de Carvalho - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):44-70.
    Ao longo da Metafísica e dos tratados de filosofia natural, Aristóteles toma os organismos vivos como os exemplos paradigmáticos de οὐσίαι (substâncias) naturais. No entanto, além dos organismos vivos, em certas passagens o filósofo menciona, também, as partes dos viventes e os elementos como exemplos de substâncias. Contudo, em outras passagens, Aristóteles parece considerar que as partes dos seres vivos e os corpos elementares não representariam, genuinamente ou propriamente, entidades substanciais. Por outro lado, em nenhum momento, o filósofo parece indicar (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  58
    On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle's Somatic Model of Socratean Akrasia.Brian Andrew Lightbody - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):134-161.
    The Protagoras is the touchstone of Socrates’ moral intellectualist stance. The position in a nutshell stipulates that the proper reevaluation of a desire is enough to neutralize it.[1] The implication of this position is that akrasia or weakness of will is not the result of desire (or fear for that matter) overpowering reason but is due to ignorance. -/- Socrates’ eliminativist position on weakness of will, however, flies in the face of the common-sense experience regarding akratic action and thus Aristotle (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  2
    O justo cívico em Ethica Nicomachea V.6.André Luiz Cruz Sousa - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):90-133.
    The present study aims at understanding how Ethica Nicomachea V.6 relates to its preceding chapters, V.1-5. On the one hand, the interpreter wonders for what purpose Aristotle introduces a topic named ‘the civic just’ (to politikon dikaion) in V.6, since V.1-5 treats extensively of matters of justice in the city. On the other hand, the same text posits that there is a certain ‘just without qualification’ (to haplōs dikaion), which may or may not be the civic just itself; compared to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  70
    Entre ética e ciência: necessidade e contingência na teoria da ação em Aristóteles.Jaqueline Stefani - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):71-89.
    Este artigo investiga a possibilidade de questões morais possuírem a mesma natureza de ocorrências no mais das vezes (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) discutidas na Física, Metafísica e nos Analíticos, em contraste com as categorias de necessário sem mais e de acaso/acidente. Tal categoria (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) ora é aproximada daquilo que é necessário (necessidade sem mais), quando Aristóteles realça a exclusão do acaso/acidente da ciência, ora é afastada do necessário sem mais, quando busca especificar as diferenças entre essas categorias (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Some remarks against non-epistemic accounts of immediate premises in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.Breno Zuppolini - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):29-43.
    Most interpretations of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics believe that the term ‘ameson’ is used to describe the principles or foundations of a given system of justification or explanation as epistemically prior to or more fundamental than the other propositions in the system. Epistemic readings (as I shall call them) arguably constitute a majority in the secondary literature. This predominant view has been challenged by Robin Smith (1986) and Michael Ferejohn (1994; 2013), who propose interpretations that should be classified as non-epistemic according (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  7
    The Problem of Modal Upgrading in Aristotle’s Apodictic Syllogistic.David Botting - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):96-120.
    This is another contribution to the unending controversy over the two Barbaras. My approach to the problem is hopefully quite new: I wish to view the issue through the prism of modal upgrading. Modal upgrading occurs when a subject term that has only been predicated of assertorically in the premises is predicated of apodictically either: i) in the conclusion of a given syllogism, or; ii) in some proposition that is derived from either the premises of the given syllogism alone or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  16
    How Does Aristotle Understand the Paradox of the Meno?Nathan Elvidge - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):80-95.
    I focus on the distinction between universal and particular knowledge or knowledge simpliciter in APr 2.21 and APo 1.1 as Aristotle’s explicit response to the paradox of the Meno. I attempt to derive a picture of Aristotle’s understanding of the philosophical problem underlying that paradox by asking what that problem would have to be in order for this distinction to make sense as a response to it. I consider two ways of taking the distinction, and argue that both point towards (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  12
    A Note on Aristotle’s De Anima Α 1, 403a10-16.Orestis Karasmanis - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):139-146.
    In this paper I discuss passage 403a10-16 from Aristotle’s De Anima. In this passage Aristotle deals with whether the soul could be separate from the body and presents an analogy with geometrical entities. This passage is highly obscure and it presents many textual difficulties. The interpretation I offer resolves the textual problems without requiring emendations to the text as many commentators suggest.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  6
    Callicles as a Potential Tyrant in Plato's Gorgias.Daniel R. N. Lopes - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):01-35.
    This essay argues that Callicles is depicted by Plato in the Gorgias as a potential tyrant from a psychological standpoint. To this end I will contend that the Calliclean moral psychology sketched at 491e-492c points towards the analysis of the tyrannical individual pursued by Plato in books VIII and IX of the Republic based upon the tripartite theory of the soul. I will thereby attempt to show that (i) in the Gorgias, Callicles does not actually personify the ideal of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Percepción Moral y Conocimiento Práctico en el Estoicismo.Christian Pineda - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):121-138.
    In a paper published in 1998, Ricardo Salles argues that the Stoic theory of action cannot account for practical knowledge, i.e., knowledge about what action is appropriate to be carried out in certain circumstances. The aim of this paper is to propose a solution to this problem. For this aim, I argue that the Stoics developed a perceptual theory of moral knowledge. According to this theory, the moral properties instantiated in objects, people, and actions are known through perception. After explaining (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  6
    Temporal Truth and Bivalence: an Anachronistic Formal Approach to Aristotle’s De Interpretatione 9.Luiz Henrique Lopes dos Santos - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):59-79.
    Regarding the famous Sea Battle Argument, which Aristotle presents in De Interpretatione 9, there has never been a general agreement not only about its correctness but also, and mainly, about what the argument really is. According to the most natural reading of the chapter, the argument appeals to a temporal concept of truth and concludes that not every statement is always either true or false. However, many of Aristotle’s followers and commentators have not adopted this reading. I believe that it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  22
    Learning through Love: A Lover’s Initiation in the Symposium.Paul Woodruff - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):36-58.
    In the Symposium of Plato, Socrates reports that Diotima once described to him a process of initiation by which a lover rises from desiring one beautiful body to catching sight of what seems to be the Platonic form of beauty. Scholars have debated whether the lover is to make this ascent by a rational process or a non-rational one, or by both working either in concert or independently. This paper argues that love leads and guides a process in this initiation (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues