Switch to: References

Citations of:

The later philosophy of R.G. Collingwood

Chicago: University of Chicago Press (1962)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A reply to Mischel's "Collingwood on art as 'imaginative expression'".John A. Bailey - 1963 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41 (3):372 – 378.
  • Why Collingwood Matters: A Defence of Humanistic Understanding.Giuseppina D'Oro - 2023 - Bloomsbury.
    R.G. Collingwood (1889-1943) was an English philosopher, historian and practicing archaeologist. His work, particularly in the philosophy of action and history, has been profoundly influential in the 20th and 21st century. Although the importance of his work is indisputable, this is the first book to consider how and why it actually matters. Giussepina D'oro considers the importance of Collingwood as a thinker who thinks kaleidoscopically and, unlike lots of contemporary philosophers, refuses to focus on narrow, technical interests but instead, observes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ryle and Collingwood: Their correspondence and its philosophical context.Charlotte Vrijen - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (1):93 – 131.
    *I would like to thank Michel ter Hark, Lodi Nauta and James Connelly, for their critical reading of earlier versions of this paper and for their comments. Gilbert Ryle and R. G. Collingwood are no...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On understanding disaster.Herman Simissen - 1993 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (3):352-367.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Explanation of Action in History.Constantine Sandis - 2006 - Essays in Philosophy 7 (2):12.
    This paper focuses on two conflations which frequently appear within the philosophy of history and other fields concerned with action explanation. The first of these, which I call the Conflating View of Reasons, states that the reasons for which we perform actions are reasons why (those events which are) our actions occur. The second, more general conflation, which I call the Conflating View of Action Explanation, states that whatever explains why an agent performed a certain action explains why (that event (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A defense of Collingwood's theory of presuppositions.John Frederic Post - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):332 – 354.
    Collingwood's theory of presuppositions has never been taken very seriously. But critics have completely overlooked its significance as a theory or model of inquiry intimately tied to certain aspects of discourse in a context of investigation. Viewed this way, Collingwood's theory is on very strong ground, especially when it is reconstructed with the aid of a formal language. The reconstruction shows what is essential to the theory and what is not, allowing us to disregard those of Collingwood's extravagant claims which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making sense of History: Skagestad on popper and Collingwood.M. Hurup Nielsen & J. F. G. Shearmur - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):459-489.
  • Science, Worldviews and Education: An Introduction.Michael R. Matthews - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (6-7):641-666.
  • Idealism and the Ontological Argument.William J. Mander - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5):993-1014.
    The ontological proof became something of a signature argument for the British Idealist movement and this paper examines how and why that was so. Beginning with an account of Hegel's understanding of the argument, it looks at how the thesis was picked up, developed and criticized by the Cairds, Bradley, Pringle-Pattison and others. The importance of Bradley's reading in particular is stressed. Lastly, consideration is given to Collingwood's lifelong interest in the proof and it is argued that his attention is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Cook Wilson.Mathieu Marion - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    John Cook Wilson (1849–1915) was Wykeham Professor of Logic at New College, Oxford and the founder of ‘Oxford Realism’, a philosophical movement that flourished at Oxford during the first decades of the 20th century. Although trained as a classicist and a mathematician, his most important contribution was to the theory of knowledge, where he argued that knowledge is factive and not definable in terms of belief, and he criticized ‘hybrid’ and ‘externalist’ accounts. He also argued for direct realism in perception, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Robin George Collingwood.Giuseppina D'Oro & James Connelly - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Art as the Expression of Emotion in the Language of Imagination: Dickie's Misunderstandings of Collingwood's Aesthetics.José Juan González - 2011 - Art, Emotion and Value. Proceedings of the 5th Mediterranean Congress of Aesthetics. Cartagena (Spain), 4th-8th July 2011:175-184.
    It is a common statement in the most traditional views of the history of the philosophy of art to consider the nineteenth century as the moment of birth of the expressionist theory of art, a theory that ended pushing aside the already declining imitation theory of art. It is also usually understood that the expressionist theory defended that the essence of art was to express emotion, that the artist aim was to translate somehow emotions into artworks, and that these emotions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark