Results for 'weak randomness'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Subclasses of the Weakly Random Reals.Johanna N. Y. Franklin - 2010 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (4):417-426.
    The weakly random reals contain not only the Schnorr random reals as a subclass but also the weakly 1-generic reals and therefore the n -generic reals for every n . While the class of Schnorr random reals does not overlap with any of these classes of generic reals, their degrees may. In this paper, we describe the extent to which this is possible for the Turing, weak truth-table, and truth-table degrees and then extend our analysis to the Schnorr random (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  11
    Weakly 2-randoms and 1-generics in Scott sets.Linda Brown Westrick - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (1):392-394.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  10
    Ω-change randomness and weak Demuth randomness.Johanna N. Y. Franklin & Keng Meng Ng - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (3):776-791.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  3
    Motion of dislocations through a random array of weak obstacles.J. Schlipf & R. Schindlmayr - 1975 - Philosophical Magazine 31 (1):25-37.
  5.  3
    Motion of dislocations through a random array of weak obstacles.R. Schindlmayr & J. Schlipf - 1975 - Philosophical Magazine 31 (1):13-24.
  6.  25
    Randomness and Semimeasures.Laurent Bienvenu, Rupert Hölzl, Christopher P. Porter & Paul Shafer - 2017 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (3):301-328.
    A semimeasure is a generalization of a probability measure obtained by relaxing the additivity requirement to superadditivity. We introduce and study several randomness notions for left-c.e. semimeasures, a natural class of effectively approximable semimeasures induced by Turing functionals. Among the randomness notions we consider, the generalization of weak 2-randomness to left-c.e. semimeasures is the most compelling, as it best reflects Martin-Löf randomness with respect to a computable measure. Additionally, we analyze a question of Shen, a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  41
    Demuth randomness and computational complexity.Antonín Kučera & André Nies - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (7):504-513.
    Demuth tests generalize Martin-Löf tests in that one can exchange the m-th component a computably bounded number of times. A set fails a Demuth test if Z is in infinitely many final versions of the Gm. If we only allow Demuth tests such that GmGm+1 for each m, we have weak Demuth randomness.We show that a weakly Demuth random set can be high and , yet not superhigh. Next, any c.e. set Turing below a Demuth random set is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8.  37
    Algorithmic randomness, reverse mathematics, and the dominated convergence theorem.Jeremy Avigad, Edward T. Dean & Jason Rute - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1854-1864.
    We analyze the pointwise convergence of a sequence of computable elements of L1 in terms of algorithmic randomness. We consider two ways of expressing the dominated convergence theorem and show that, over the base theory RCA0, each is equivalent to the assertion that every Gδ subset of Cantor space with positive measure has an element. This last statement is, in turn, equivalent to weak weak Königʼs lemma relativized to the Turing jump of any set. It is also (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  20
    Randomness notions and reverse mathematics.André Nies & Paul Shafer - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (1):271-299.
    We investigate the strength of a randomness notion ${\cal R}$ as a set-existence principle in second-order arithmetic: for each Z there is an X that is ${\cal R}$-random relative to Z. We show that the equivalence between 2-randomness and being infinitely often C-incompressible is provable in $RC{A_0}$. We verify that $RC{A_0}$ proves the basic implications among randomness notions: 2-random $\Rightarrow$ weakly 2-random $\Rightarrow$ Martin-Löf random $\Rightarrow$ computably random $\Rightarrow$ Schnorr random. Also, over $RC{A_0}$ the existence of computable (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  49
    Algorithmic randomness and measures of complexity.George Barmpalias - forthcoming - Association for Symbolic Logic: The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
    We survey recent advances on the interface between computability theory and algorithmic randomness, with special attention on measures of relative complexity. We focus on (weak) reducibilities that measure (a) the initial segment complexity of reals and (b) the power of reals to compress strings, when they are used as oracles. The results are put into context and several connections are made with various central issues in modern algorithmic randomness and computability.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Mass problems and randomness.Stephen G. Simpson - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (1):1-27.
    A mass problem is a set of Turing oracles. If P and Q are mass problems, we say that P is weakly reducible to Q if every member of Q Turing computes a member of P. We say that P is strongly reducible to Q if every member of Q Turing computes a member of P via a fixed Turing functional. The weak degrees and strong degrees are the equivalence classes of mass problems under weak and strong reducibility, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  12.  30
    Kolmogorov–Loveland randomness and stochasticity.Wolfgang Merkle, Joseph S. Miller, André Nies, Jan Reimann & Frank Stephan - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 138 (1):183-210.
    An infinite binary sequence X is Kolmogorov–Loveland random if there is no computable non-monotonic betting strategy that succeeds on X in the sense of having an unbounded gain in the limit while betting successively on bits of X. A sequence X is KL-stochastic if there is no computable non-monotonic selection rule that selects from X an infinite, biased sequence.One of the major open problems in the field of effective randomness is whether Martin-Löf randomness is the same as KL- (...). Our first main result states that KL-random sequences are close to Martin-Löf random sequences in so far as every KL-random sequence has arbitrarily dense subsequences that are Martin-Löf random. A key lemma in the proof of this result is that for every effective split of a KL-random sequence at least one of the halves is Martin-Löf random. However, this splitting property does not characterize KL-randomness; we construct a sequence that is not even computably random such that every effective split yields two subsequences that are 2-random. Furthermore, we show for any KL-random sequence A that is computable in the halting problem that, first, for any effective split of A both halves are Martin-Löf random and, second, for any computable, nondecreasing, and unbounded function g and almost all n, the prefix of A of length n has prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity at least n−g. Again, the latter property does not characterize KL-randomness, even when restricted to left-r.e. sequences; we construct a left-r.e. sequence that has this property but is not KL-stochastic and, in fact, is not even Mises–Wald–Church stochastic.Turning our attention to KL-stochasticity, we construct a non-empty class of KL-stochastic sequences that are not weakly 1-random; by the usual basis theorems we obtain such sequences that in addition are left-r.e., are low, or are of hyperimmune-free degree.Our second main result asserts that every KL-stochastic sequence has effective dimension 1, or equivalently, a sequence cannot be KL-stochastic if it has infinitely many prefixes that can be compressed by a factor of α<1. This improves on a result by Muchnik, who has shown that were they to exist, such compressible prefixes could not be found effectively. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  13.  13
    Computing from projections of random points.Noam Greenberg, Joseph S. Miller & André Nies - 2019 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 20 (1):1950014.
    We study the sets that are computable from both halves of some (Martin–Löf) random sequence, which we call 1/2-bases. We show that the collection of such sets forms an ideal in the Turing degrees that is generated by its c.e. elements. It is a proper subideal of the K-trivial sets. We characterize 1/2-bases as the sets computable from both halves of Chaitin’s Ω, and as the sets that obey the cost function c(x,s)=Ωs−Ωx−−−−−−−√. Generalizing these results yields a dense hierarchy of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  50
    Lowness for Kurtz randomness.Noam Greenberg & Joseph S. Miller - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):665-678.
    We prove that degrees that are low for Kurtz randomness cannot be diagonally non-recursive. Together with the work of Stephan and Yu [16], this proves that they coincide with the hyperimmune-free non-DNR degrees, which are also exactly the degrees that are low for weak 1-genericity. We also consider Low(M, Kurtz), the class of degrees a such that every element of M is a-Kurtz random. These are characterised when M is the class of Martin-Löf random, computably random, or Schnorr (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  19
    Continuous higher randomness.Laurent Bienvenu, Noam Greenberg & Benoit Monin - 2017 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 17 (1):1750004.
    We investigate the role of continuous reductions and continuous relativization in the context of higher randomness. We define a higher analogue of Turing reducibility and show that it interacts well with higher randomness, for example with respect to van Lambalgen’s theorem and the Miller–Yu/Levin theorem. We study lowness for continuous relativization of randomness, and show the equivalence of the higher analogues of the different characterizations of lowness for Martin-Löf randomness. We also characterize computing higher [Formula: see (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  15
    Characterizing lowness for Demuth randomness.Laurent Bienvenu, Rod Downey, Noam Greenberg, André Nies & Dan Turetsky - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (2):526-560.
    We show the existence of noncomputable oracles which are low for Demuth randomness, answering a question in [15]. We fully characterize lowness for Demuth randomness using an appropriate notion of traceability. Central to this characterization is a partial relativization of Demuth randomness, which may be more natural than the fully relativized version. We also show that an oracle is low for weak Demuth randomness if and only if it is computable.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  13
    Luzin’s (n) and randomness reflection.Arno Pauly, Linda Westrick & Liang Yu - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-27.
    We show that a computable function $f:\mathbb R\rightarrow \mathbb R$ has Luzin’s property if and only if it reflects $\Pi ^1_1$ -randomness, if and only if it reflects $\Delta ^1_1$ -randomness, and if and only if it reflects ${\mathcal {O}}$ -Kurtz randomness, but reflecting Martin–Löf randomness or weak-2-randomness does not suffice. Here a function f is said to reflect a randomness notion R if whenever $f$ is R-random, then x is R-random as well. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  8
    Luzin’s (n) and randomness reflection.Arno Pauly, Linda Westrick & Liang Yu - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (2):802-828.
    We show that a computable function $f:\mathbb R\rightarrow \mathbb R$ has Luzin’s property if and only if it reflects $\Pi ^1_1$ -randomness, if and only if it reflects $\Delta ^1_1$ -randomness, and if and only if it reflects ${\mathcal {O}}$ -Kurtz randomness, but reflecting Martin–Löf randomness or weak-2-randomness does not suffice. Here a function f is said to reflect a randomness notion R if whenever $f$ is R-random, then x is R-random as well. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  22
    Program extraction for 2-random reals.Alexander P. Kreuzer - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (5-6):659-666.
    Let ${2-\textsf{RAN}}$ be the statement that for each real X a real 2-random relative to X exists. We apply program extraction techniques we developed in Kreuzer and Kohlenbach (J. Symb. Log. 77(3):853–895, 2012. doi:10.2178/jsl/1344862165), Kreuzer (Notre Dame J. Formal Log. 53(2):245–265, 2012. doi:10.1215/00294527-1715716) to this principle. Let ${{\textsf{WKL}_0^\omega}}$ be the finite type extension of ${\textsf{WKL}_0}$ . We obtain that one can extract primitive recursive realizers from proofs in ${{\textsf{WKL}_0^\omega} + \Pi^0_1-{\textsf{CP}} + 2-\textsf{RAN}}$ , i.e., if ${{\textsf{WKL}_0^\omega} + \Pi^0_1-{\textsf{CP}} + 2-\textsf{RAN} (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  12
    Contextuality and Dichotomizations of Random Variables.Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov & Janne V. Kujala - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 52 (1):1-25.
    The Contextuality-by-Default approach to determining and measuring the (non)contextuality of a system of random variables requires that every random variable in the system be represented by an equivalent set of dichotomous random variables. In this paper we present general principles that justify the use of dichotomizations and determine their choice. The main idea in choosing dichotomizations is that if the set of possible values of a random variable is endowed with a pre-topology (V-space), then the allowable dichotomizations split the space (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  4
    Introenumerability, Autoreducibility, and Randomness.L. I. Ang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic.
    We define $\Psi $ -autoreducible sets given an autoreduction procedure $\Psi $. Then, we show that for any $\Psi $, a measurable class of $\Psi $ -autoreducible sets has measure zero. Using this, we show that classes of cototal, uniformly introenumerable, introenumerable, and hyper-cototal enumeration degrees all have measure zero. By analyzing the arithmetical complexity of the classes of cototal sets and cototal enumeration degrees, we show that weakly 2-random sets cannot be cototal and weakly 3-random sets cannot be of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  29
    A note on the learning-theoretic characterizations of randomness and convergence.Tomasz Steifer - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-15.
    Recently, a connection has been established between two branches of computability theory, namely between algorithmic randomness and algorithmic learning theory. Learning-theoretical characterizations of several notions of randomness were discovered. We study such characterizations based on the asymptotic density of positive answers. In particular, this note provides a new learning-theoretic definition of weak 2-randomness, solving the problem posed by (Zaffora Blando, Rev. Symb. Log. 2019). The note also highlights the close connection between these characterizations and the problem (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  40
    The K -Degrees, Low for K Degrees,and Weakly Low for K Sets.Joseph S. Miller - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (4):381-391.
    We call A weakly low for K if there is a c such that $K^A(\sigma)\geq K(\sigma)-c$ for infinitely many σ; in other words, there are infinitely many strings that A does not help compress. We prove that A is weakly low for K if and only if Chaitin's Ω is A-random. This has consequences in the K-degrees and the low for K (i.e., low for random) degrees. Furthermore, we prove that the initial segment prefix-free complexity of 2-random reals is infinitely (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24.  45
    A learning-theoretic characterisation of Martin-Löf randomness and Schnorr randomness.Francesca Zaffora Blando - 2021 - Review of Symbolic Logic 14 (2):531-549.
    Numerous learning tasks can be described as the process of extrapolating patterns from observed data. One of the driving intuitions behind the theory of algorithmic randomness is that randomness amounts to the absence of any effectively detectable patterns: it is thus natural to regard randomness as antithetical to inductive learning. Osherson and Weinstein [11] draw upon the identification of randomness with unlearnability to introduce a learning-theoretic framework (in the spirit of formal learning theory) for modelling algorithmic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  15
    On the interplay between effective notions of randomness and genericity.Laurent Bienvenu & Christopher P. Porter - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):393-407.
    In this paper, we study the power and limitations of computing effectively generic sequences using effectively random oracles. Previously, it was known that every 2-random sequence computes a 1-generic sequence and every 2-random sequence forms a minimal pair in the Turing degrees with every 2-generic sequence. We strengthen these results by showing that every Demuth random sequence computes a 1-generic sequence and that every Demuth random sequence forms a minimal pair with every pb-generic sequence. Moreover, we prove that for every (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. You better play 7: mutual versus common knowledge of advice in a weak-link experiment.Giovanna Devetag, Hykel Hosni & Giacomo Sillari - 2013 - Synthese 190 (8):1351-1381.
    This paper presents the results of an experiment on mutual versus common knowledge of advice in a two-player weak-link game with random matching. Our experimental subjects play in pairs for thirteen rounds. After a brief learning phase common to all treatments, we vary the knowledge levels associated with external advice given in the form of a suggestion to pick the strategy supporting the payoff-dominant equilibrium. Our results are somewhat surprising and can be summarized as follows: in all our treatments (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. On the construction of effectively random sets.Wolfgang Merkle & Nenad Mihailović - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):862-878.
    We present a comparatively simple way to construct Martin-Löf random and rec-random sets with certain additional properties, which works by diagonalizing against appropriate martingales. Reviewing the result of Gács and Kučera, for any given set X we construct a Martin-Löf random set from which X can be decoded effectively. By a variant of the basic construction we obtain a rec-random set that is weak truth-table autoreducible and we observe that there are Martin-Löf random sets that are computably enumerable self-reducible. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  4
    Which subsets of an infinite random graph look random?Will Brian - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (6):478-486.
    Given a countable graph, we say a set A of its vertices is universal if it contains every countable graph as an induced subgraph, and A is weakly universal if it contains every finite graph as an induced subgraph. We show that, for almost every graph on, (1) every set of positive upper density is universal, and (2) every set with divergent reciprocal sums is weakly universal. We show that the second result is sharp (i.e., a random graph on will (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  28
    On bifurcations and chaos in random neural networks.B. Doyon, B. Cessac, M. Quoy & M. Samuelides - 1994 - Acta Biotheoretica 42 (2-3):215-225.
    Chaos in nervous system is a fascinating but controversial field of investigation. To approach the role of chaos in the real brain, we theoretically and numerically investigate the occurrence of chaos inartificial neural networks. Most of the time, recurrent networks (with feedbacks) are fully connected. This architecture being not biologically plausible, the occurrence of chaos is studied here for a randomly diluted architecture. By normalizing the variance of synaptic weights, we produce a bifurcation parameter, dependent on this variance and on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  9
    Very Short-Term Blackout Prediction for Grid-Tied PV Systems Operating in Low Reliability Weak Electric Grids of Developing Countries.Benson H. Mbuya, Aleksandar Dimovski, Marco Merlo & Thomas Kivevele - 2022 - Complexity 2022:1-13.
    Sub-Saharan emerging countries experience electrical shortages resulting in power rationing, which ends up hampering economic activities. This paper proposes an approach for very short-term blackout forecast in grid-tied PV systems operating in low reliability weak electric grids of emerging countries. A pilot project was implemented in Arusha-Tanzania; it mainly comprised of a PV-inverter and a lead-acid battery bank connected to the local electricity utility company, Tanzania Electric Supply Company Limited. A very short-term power outage prediction model framework based on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  32
    Jump inversions inside effectively closed sets and applications to randomness.George Barmpalias, Rod Downey & Keng Meng Ng - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):491 - 518.
    We study inversions of the jump operator on ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{1}^{0}$ classes, combined with certain basis theorems. These jump inversions have implications for the study of the jump operator on the random degrees—for various notions of randomness. For example, we characterize the jumps of the weakly 2-random sets which are not 2-random, and the jumps of the weakly 1-random relative to 0′ sets which are not 2-random. Both of the classes coincide with the degrees above 0′ which are not 0′-dominated. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Tying one's hands.Weakness of Will as A. Justification - 2001 - Public Affairs Quarterly 15:355.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  6
    other camp doesn't really understand Darwin or evolution; both routinely pay homage to George Williams's (1966) modest use of adaptationism.Strong Versus Weak - 2005 - In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents. New York, US: Oxford University Press USA. pp. 141.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  44
    A strong law of computationally weak subsets.Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen - 2011 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 11 (1):1-10.
    We show that in the setting of fair-coin measure on the power set of the natural numbers, each sufficiently random set has an infinite subset that computes no random set. That is, there is an almost sure event [Formula: see text] such that if [Formula: see text] then X has an infinite subset Y such that no element of [Formula: see text] is Turing computable from Y.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Peter Kirschenmann.Concepts Of Randomness - 1973 - In Mario Augusto Bunge (ed.), Exact Philosophy; Problems, Tools, and Goals. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 129.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  11
    Reference Explained Away: Anaphoric Reference and Indirect.Robert Bb Random - 2005 - In J. C. Beall & B. Armour-Garb (eds.), Deflationary Truth. Open Court. pp. 258.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  11
    Fandom as Methodology: A Sourcebook for Artists and Writers.Catherine Grant & Kate Random Love (eds.) - 2019 - London: MIT Press.
    An illustrated exploration of fandom that combines academic essays with artist pages and experimental texts. Fandom as Methodology examines fandom as a set of practices for approaching and writing about art. The collection includes experimental texts, autobiography, fiction, and new academic perspectives on fandom in and as art. Key to the idea of “fandom as methodology” is a focus on the potential for fandom in art to create oppositional spaces, communities, and practices, particularly from queer perspectives, but also through transnational, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Introduction: Fandom as methodology.Catherine Grant & Kate Random Love - 2019 - In Catherine Grant & Kate Random Love (eds.), Fandom as Methodology: A Sourcebook for Artists and Writers. London: MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  18
    Commentary on Risto Naatanen (1990). The role of attention in auditory information processing as revealed by event-related potentials and other brain measures of cognitive fenctiono BBS 13s201-2888. [REVIEW]A. Ryan, R. D. Ryder, L. Schiebinger, P. Singer & Random House - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14:4.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  80
    A C.E. Real That Cannot Be SW-Computed by Any Ω Number.George Barmpalias & Andrew E. M. Lewis - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (2):197-209.
    The strong weak truth table (sw) reducibility was suggested by Downey, Hirschfeldt, and LaForte as a measure of relative randomness, alternative to the Solovay reducibility. It also occurs naturally in proofs in classical computability theory as well as in the recent work of Soare, Nabutovsky, and Weinberger on applications of computability to differential geometry. We study the sw-degrees of c.e. reals and construct a c.e. real which has no random c.e. real (i.e., Ω number) sw-above it.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41.  23
    Arithmetical Measure.Sebastiaan A. Terwijn & Leen Torenvliet - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (2):277-286.
    We develop arithmetical measure theory along the lines of Lutz [10]. This yields the same notion of measure 0 set as considered before by Martin-Löf, Schnorr, and others. We prove that the class of sets constructible by r.e.-constructors, a direct analogue of the classes Lutz devised his resource bounded measures for in [10], is not equal to RE, the class of r.e. sets, and we locate this class exactly in terms of the common recursion-theoretic reducibilities below K. We note that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  47
    Low upper bounds of ideals.Antonín Kučera & Theodore A. Slaman - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):517-534.
    We show that there is a low T-upper bound for the class of K-trivial sets, namely those which are weak from the point of view of algorithmic randomness. This result is a special case of a more general characterization of ideals in $\Delta _2^0 $ T-degrees for which there is a low T-upper bound.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Synchronic and diachronic emergence.Paul Humphreys - 2008 - Minds and Machines 18 (4):431-442.
    I discuss here a number of different kinds of diachronic emergence, noting that they differ in important ways from synchronic conceptions. I argue that Bedau’s weak emergence has an essentially historical aspect, in that there can be two indistinguishable states, one of which is weakly emergent, the other of which is not. As a consequence, weak emergence is about tokens, not types, of states. I conclude by examining the question of whether the concept of weak emergence is (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  44.  8
    On Sequences of Homomorphisms Into Measure Algebras and the Efimov Problem.Piotr Borodulin–Nadzieja & Damian Sobota - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (1):191-218.
    For given Boolean algebras$\mathbb {A}$and$\mathbb {B}$we endow the space$\mathcal {H}(\mathbb {A},\mathbb {B})$of all Boolean homomorphisms from$\mathbb {A}$to$\mathbb {B}$with various topologies and study convergence properties of sequences in$\mathcal {H}(\mathbb {A},\mathbb {B})$. We are in particular interested in the situation when$\mathbb {B}$is a measure algebra as in this case we obtain a natural tool for studying topological convergence properties of sequences of ultrafilters on$\mathbb {A}$in random extensions of the set-theoretical universe. This appears to have strong connections with Dow and Fremlin’s result stating (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  40
    Superhighness.Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen & Andrée Nies - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (4):445-452.
    We prove that superhigh sets can be jump traceable, answering a question of Cole and Simpson. On the other hand, we show that such sets cannot be weakly 2-random. We also study the class $superhigh^\diamond$ and show that it contains some, but not all, of the noncomputable K-trivial sets.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  8
    Approximate counting and NP search problems.Leszek Aleksander Kołodziejczyk & Neil Thapen - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 22 (3).
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Volume 22, Issue 03, December 2022. We study a new class of NP search problems, those which can be proved total using standard combinatorial reasoning based on approximate counting. Our model for this kind of reasoning is the bounded arithmetic theory [math] of [E. Jeřábek, Approximate counting by hashing in bounded arithmetic, J. Symb. Log. 74(3) (2009) 829–860]. In particular, the Ramsey and weak pigeonhole search problems lie in the new class. We give a purely (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Instrumental Divergence.J. Dmitri Gallow - forthcoming - Philosophical Studies:1-27.
    The thesis of instrumental convergence holds that a wide range of ends have common means: for instance, self preservation, desire preservation, self improvement, and resource acquisition. Bostrom contends that instrumental convergence gives us reason to think that "the default outcome of the creation of machine superintelligence is existential catastrophe". I use the tools of decision theory to investigate whether this thesis is true. I find that, even if intrinsic desires are randomly selected, instrumental rationality induces biases towards certain kinds of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  5
    The ergodic hierarchy.Edward N. Zalta - 2014 - In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    The so-called ergodic hierarchy (EH) is a central part of ergodic theory. It is a hierarchy of properties that dynamical systems can possess. Its five levels are egrodicity, weak mixing, strong mixing, Kolomogorov, and Bernoulli. Although EH is a mathematical theory, its concepts have been widely used in the foundations of statistical physics, accounts of randomness, and discussions about the nature of chaos. We introduce EH and discuss its applications in these fields.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  3
    Proof by Verbosity.Phil Smolenski - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 289–292.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called ' proof by verbosity (PVB)'. PVB is a favorite device among conspiracy theorists who utilize it to obfuscate the weakness of their case. By supporting their theories with so much random information (and misinformation), it gives the impression that their position is superficially well researched and supported by an avalanche of evidence. Sometimes PVB takes the form of a proof by intimidation, especially when an argument is made (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  4
    Law of demand and stochastic choice.S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci & A. Rustichini - 2021 - Theory and Decision 92 (3-4):513-529.
    We consider random choice rules that, by satisfying a weak form of Luce’s choice axiom, embody a form probabilistic rationality. We show that for this important class of stochastic choices, the law of demand for normal goods—arguably the main result of traditional consumer theory—continues to hold on average when strictly dominated alternatives are dismissed.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000