Results for 'third party consent'

991 found
Order:
  1.  5
    Larry Alexander.Third-Party Defense - 2012 - In Marmor Andrei (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law. Routledge. pp. 222.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Should third party consent to research be mandated? Should there be a right for third parties to have data about them withdrawn from a research project? Two perspectives.[Series of two articles]: Part 2.[Ethics Committee reflection.]. [REVIEW]Colin Jh Thomson - 2004 - Monash Bioethics Review 23 (1):83.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  5
    Should third party consent to research be mandated? Should there be a right for third parties to have data about them withdrawn from a research project? Two perspectives. [REVIEW]Martin Delatycki - 2004 - Monash Bioethics Review 23 (1):S75-S86.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  38
    Consent and Third-Party Coercion.Mollie Gerver - 2021 - Ethics 131 (2):246-269.
    It is commonly claimed that when X coerces Y into consenting to Z φ-ing, Y’s consent is invalid, and Z is only permitted to φ if this reduces harm or increases optionality for Y. This article demonstrates that Y’s consent in such cases is valid if Y is choosing between options that include all those Z has a duty to offer Y and no autonomy-reducing options Z has a duty to not offer Y. When these conditions are met, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  30
    Consenting Under Third-Party Coercion.Maximilian Kiener - 2021 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 19 (4):361-389.
    This paper focuses on consent and third-party coercion, viz. cases in which a person consents to another person performing a certain act because a third party coerced her into doing so. I argue that, in these cases, the validity of consent depends on the behavior of the recipient of consent rather than the third party’s coercion taken separately, and I will specify the conditions under which consent is invalid. My view, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Consent Under Pressure: The Puzzle of Third Party Coercion.Joseph Millum - 2014 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (1):113-127.
    Coercion by the recipient of consent renders that consent invalid. But what about when the coercive force comes from a third party, not from the person to whom consent would be proffered? In this paper I analyze how threats from a third party affect consent. I argue that, as with other cases of coercion, we should distinguish threats that render consent invalid from threats whose force is too weak to invalidate (...) and threats that are legitimate. Illegitimate controlling third party threats render consent invalid just as they do in two party cases. However, knowing that the consent is invalid is not sufficient to tell the recipient of consent what she may or should do. I argue that when presented with a token of consent from someone whom she thinks is experiencing an illegitimate controlling threat, the recipient may act on that token if and only if doing so represents a reasonable joint decision for her and the victim of coercion. The appropriate action for someone faced with third party coercion therefore depends on the other options open to her and those open to the victim of coercion. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  17
    Genetic Knowledge and Third-Party Interests.Elisabeth Boetzkes - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):386-392.
    Recent discussions of genetic information have highlighted the need for ethical disclosure guidelines. For instance, the (Canadian) Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies points out the range of third-party interests in genetic information and the lack of clear ethical and professional guidelines governing its dissemination. Among the more worrying interests are those of insurance companies and prospective employers. However, also worrisome is the problem of negotiating the first-party interest in privacy (from which the professional obligation of confidentiality (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  41
    Justice and third party risk: The ethics of xenotransplantation.Jonathan Hughes - 2007 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 24 (2):151–168.
    The question of when it is permissible to inflict risks on others without their consent is one that we all face in our everyday lives, but which is often brought to our attention in contexts of technological innovation and scientific uncertainty. Xenotransplantation, the transplantation of organs or tissues from animals to humans, has the potential to save or improve the lives of many patients but gives rise to the possibility of infectious agents being transferred from donor animals into the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  35
    Informed consent and collaborative research: Perspectives from the developing world.Adnan A. Hyder & Salman A. Wali - 2006 - Developing World Bioethics 6 (1):33–40.
    203 surveys were considered complete and were included in the analysis. Written consent was not used by nearly 40% of the researchers.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  10.  68
    Consent to Sex in an Unjust World.Victor Tadros - 2021 - Ethics 131 (2):293-318.
    This article explores the moral significance of consent in an unjust world by developing the view that the validity of consent depends on its causes. It defends the view that the causes of consent make it valid or invalid. It then shows how this idea helps us to distinguish different ways in which consent might matter morally where it has problematic causes. Finally, it uses this analysis to explore the moral significance of a range of problematic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  57
    Trusted consent and research biobanks: Towards a 'new alliance' between researchers and donors.Giovanni Boniolo, Pier Paolo di Fiore & Salvatore Pece - 2010 - Bioethics 26 (2):93-100.
    We argue that, in the case of research biobanks, there is a need to replace the currently used informed consent with trusted consent. Accordingly, we introduce a proposal for the structure of the latter. Further, we discuss some of the issues that can be addressed effectively through our proposal. In particular, we illustrate: i) which research should be authorized by donors; ii) how to regulate access to information; iii) the fundamental role played by a Third Party (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12.  16
    Consent and living organ donation.Maximilian Kiener - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (12):e50-e50.
    This paper focuses on voluntary consent in the context of living organ donation. Arguing against three dominant views, I claim that voluntariness must not be equated with willingness, that voluntariness does not require the exercise of relational moral agency, and that, in cases of third-party pressure, voluntariness critically depends on the role of the surgeon and the medical team, and not just on the pressure from other people. I therefore argue that an adequate account of voluntary (...) cannot understand voluntariness as a purely psychological concept, that it has to be consistent with people pursuing various different conceptions of the good and that it needs to make the interaction between the person giving consent and the person receiving consent central to its approach. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  46
    Consenting Under Coercion: The Partial Validity Account.Sameer Bajaj & Patrick Tomlin - forthcoming - Philosophical Quarterly.
    How is the validity of our consent, and others’ moral permission to act on our consent affected by coercion? Everyone agrees that in cases of two-party coercion—when X coerces Y to do something with or for X—the consent of the coerced is invalid, and the coercer is not permitted to act upon the consent they receive. But coercers and the recipients of consent are not always identical. Sometimes a victim, Y, agrees to do something (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  40
    The informed consent process in a rural African setting: a case study of the Kassena-Nankana district of Northern Ghana.N. Kass & P. Akweongo - 2005 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 28 (3):1-6.
  15.  42
    The consent problem within DNA biobanks.Darren Shickle - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (3):503-519.
    Large prospective biobanks are being established containing DNA, lifestyle and health information in order to study the relationship between diseases, genes and environment. Informed consent is a central component of research ethics protection. Disclosure of information about the research is an essential element of seeking informed consent. Within biobanks, it is not possible at recruitment to describe in detail the information that will subsequently be collected because people will not know which disease they will develop. It will also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  16. Why does duress undermine consent?1.Tom Dougherty - 2019 - Noûs 55 (2):317-333.
    In this essay, I discuss why consent is invalidated by duress that involves attaching penalties to someone's refusal to give consent. At the heart of my explanation is the Complaint Principle. This principle specifies that consent is defeasibly invalid when the consent results from someone conditionally imposing a penalty on the consent‐giver's refusal to give the consent, such that the consent‐giver has a legitimate complaint against this imposition focused on how it is affects (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  61
    Consent for targeted advertising: the case of Facebook.Sourya Joyee De & Abdessamad Imine - 2020 - AI and Society 35 (4):1055-1064.
    The EU General Data Protection Regulation recognizes the data subject’s consent as one of the legal grounds for data processing. Targeted advertising, based on personal data processing, is a central source of revenue for data controllers such as Google and Facebook. At present, the implementation of consent mechanisms for such advertisements are often not well developed in practice and their compliance with the GDPR requirements can be questioned. The absence of consent may mean an unlawful data processing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Exploited consent.David Archard - 1994 - Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (3):92--101.
    The article considers whether a professional's sexual relations with a client are wrong, even if the client's consent is not coerced, incapacitated or manipulated, the impartial conduct of professional affairs is not interfered with, and there are no damaged third parties. It argues that consent may be ``exploited'' if it is forthcoming only due to the occupancy of respective positions within an unequal relationship whose scope excludes such intimacy. The article explains the use of the term, exploited', (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  48
    Why does duress undermine consent? 1.Tom Dougherty - 2021 - Noûs 55 (2):317-333.
    In this essay, I discuss why consent is invalidated by duress that involves attaching penalties to someone's refusal to give consent. At the heart of my explanation is the Complaint Principle. This principle specifies that consent is defeasibly invalid when the consent results from someone conditionally imposing a penalty on the consent‐giver's refusal to give the consent, such that the consent‐giver has a legitimate complaint against this imposition focused on how it is affects (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Autonomy and the folk concept of valid consent.Joanna Demaree-Cotton & Roseanna Sommers - 2022 - Cognition 224 (C):105065.
    Consent governs innumerable everyday social interactions, including sex, medical exams, the use of property, and economic transactions. Yet little is known about how ordinary people reason about the validity of consent. Across the domains of sex, medicine, and police entry, Study 1 showed that when agents lack autonomous decision-making capacities, participants are less likely to view their consent as valid; however, failing to exercise this capacity and deciding in a nonautonomous way did not reduce consent judgments. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  8
    Informed consent.S. Stevens - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (1):65-65.
    SIRI was concerned to read the following statement by Anne Zachary published by Marilyn Lawrence, Editor, and Co-editors, in Psychoanalytic Psychotherapy, The Journal of the Association of For Psychoanalytic Psychotherapists in the NHS.1 “Whilst we do not want to raise too starkly ourselves the moral, ethical, legal problem of sharing what the unsophisticated patient believes to be confidential with a third party, thereby destroying our ….
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  14
    Medical necessity and consent for intimate procedures.Brian D. Earp & Lori Bruce - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (9):591-593.
    This issue considers the ethics of a healthcare provider intervening into a patient’s genitalia, whether by means of cutting or surgery or by ‘mere’ touching/examination. Authors argue that the permissibility of such actions in the absence of a relevant medical emergency does not primarily turn on third-party judgments of expected levels of physical harm versus benefit, or on related notions such as extensiveness or invasiveness; rather, it turns on the patient’s own consent. To bolster this argument, attention (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  14
    The Reporting of Informed Consent and Related Issues in Critical-Care Research.Jeffrey T. Berger, Edward Khalil, Samar Khan & Tony Varghese - 2008 - Research Ethics 4 (1):10-14.
    Background: Previous studies have found lapses in ethical safeguards for subjects of critical-care research. Objective: To assess recently published empiric critical-care research conducted in the United States for the reporting of research protections as they relate to informed consent and surrogate decision-making. Methods: Systematic review of a sample of empiric critical-care research studies published between 2000 and 2004. Results: Of 51 studies reviewed, consent was reported as having been obtained in 44. Assessment of subjects' decision-making capacity was noted (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  39
    Gamete Donor Consent and Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research.Andrew W. Siegel - 2015 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 25 (2):149-168.
    There is a lack of consensus on whether the derivation and use of human embryonic stem cells (hESCs) from embryos remaining after infertility treatment morally require the informed consent of third-party gamete donors who contributed to the creation of the embryos. The principal guidelines for oversight and funding of hESC research in the United States make minimal or no demands for consent from gamete donors. In this article, I consider the arguments supporting and opposing gamete donor (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Risk communication and informed consent in the medical tourism industry: A thematic content analysis of canadian broker websites. [REVIEW]Kali Penney, Jeremy Snyder, Valorie A. Crooks & Rory Johnston - 2011 - BMC Medical Ethics 12 (1):17-.
    Background: Medical tourism, thought of as patients seeking non-emergency medical care outside of their home countries, is a growing industry worldwide. Canadians are amongst those engaging in medical tourism, and many are helped in the process of accessing care abroad by medical tourism brokers - agents who specialize in making international medical care arrangements for patients. As a key source of information for these patients, brokers are likely to play an important role in communicating the risks and benefits of undergoing (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  54
    Legal and ethical considerations in processing patient-identifiable data without patient consent: lessons learnt from developing a disease register.C. L. Haynes, G. A. Cook & M. A. Jones - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (5):302-307.
    The legal requirements and justifications for collecting patient-identifiable data without patient consent were examined. The impetus for this arose from legal and ethical issues raised during the development of a population-based disease register. Numerous commentaries and case studies have been discussing the impact of the Data Protection Act 1998 and Caldicott principles of good practice on the uses of personal data. But uncertainty still remains about the legal requirements for processing patient-identifiable data without patient consent for research purposes. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27.  47
    Routine antenatal HIV testing: the responses and perceptions of pregnant women and the viability of informed consent. A qualitative study.P. de Zulueta & M. Boulton - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (6):329-336.
    This qualitative cross-sectional survey, undertaken in the antenatal booking clinics of a hospital in central London, explores pregnant women’s responses to routine HIV testing, examines their reasons for declining or accepting the test, and assesses how far their responses fulfil standard criteria for informed consent. Of the 32 women interviewed, only 10 participants were prepared for HIV testing at their booking interview. None of the women viewed themselves as being particularly at risk for HIV infection. The minority of the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  53
    On the prospects of collective informed consent.Jukka Varelius - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (1):35–44.
    It has been suggested that collective informed consent procedures could be used in solving moral problems arising in connection with such collective arrangements as land use planning, business administration, and developing new technology. Critics have however argued that informed consent is not an appropriate method for collective moral decision-making for three reasons. Firstly, informed consent procedures only allow the affected parties to choose between rejecting and accepting certain predetermined options, while those parties should be allowed to take (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  42
    Hide-and-seek or show-and-tell? Emerging issues of informed consent.Leonard J. Haas - 1991 - Ethics and Behavior 1 (3):175 – 189.
    This article reviews key philosophical and legal underpinnings of mental health professionals' obligation to obtain informed consent from consumers of their services. The basic components of informed consent are described, and strategies for clinically and ethically appropriate methods of obtaining informed consent are discussed. Emerging issues in informed consent involving duty to assess and protect against client dangerousness, obligations to third parties, and issues of deception are considered as well. The article proposes that part of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  23
    Managed care, medical privacy, and the paradigm of consent.Maxwell Gregg Bloche - 1997 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 7 (4):381-386.
    : The market success of managed health plans in the 1990s is bringing to medicine the easy availability of electronically stored information that is characteristic of the securities and consumer credit industries. Protection for medical confidentiality, however, has not kept pace with this information revolution. Employers, the managed care industry, and legal and ethics commentators frequently look to the concept of informed consent to justify particular uses of health information, but the elastic use of informed consent as a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  17
    Which factors influence the resort to surrogate consent in stroke trials, and what are the patient outcomes in this context?Anne-Marie Mendyk, Julien Labreuche, Hilde Henon, Marie Girot, Charlotte Cordonnier, Alain Duhamel, Didier Leys & Régis Bordet - 2015 - BMC Medical Ethics 16 (1):26.
    The provision of informed consent is a prerequisite for inclusion of a patient in a clinical research project. In some countries, the legislation on clinical research authorizes a third person to provide informed consent if the patient is unable to do so directly . This is the case during acute stroke, when the symptoms may prevent the patient from providing informed consent and thus require a third party to be approached. Identification of factors associated (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  14
    Disclosure to genetic relatives without consent – Australian genetic professionals’ awareness of the health privacy law.Jane Fleming, Ainsley J. Newson, Kate Dunlop, Kristine Barlow-Stewart & Natalia Meggiolaro - 2020 - BMC Medical Ethics 21 (1):1-10.
    Background: When a genetic mutation is identified in a family member, internationally, it is usually the proband’s or another responsible family member’s role to disclose the information to at-risk relatives. However, both active and passive non-disclosure in families occurs: choosing not to communicate the information or failing to communicate the information despite intention to do so, respectively. The ethical obligations to prevent harm to at-risk relatives and promote the duty of care by genetic health professionals is in conflict with Privacy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  40
    Ethical issues arising from the requirement to sign a consent form in palliative care.I. Plu, I. Purssell-Francois, G. Moutel, F. Ellien & C. Herve - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (4):279-280.
    French healthcare networks aim to help healthcare workers to take care of patients by improving cooperation, coordination and the continuity of care. When applied to palliative care in the home, they facilitate overall care including medical, social and psychological aspects. French legislation in 2002 required that an information document explaining the functioning of the network should be given to patients when they enter a healthcare network. The law requires that this document be signed. Ethical issues arise from this legislation with (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  28
    Family tree and ancestry inference: is there a need for a ‘generational’ consent?Susan E. Wallace, Elli G. Gourna, Viktoriya Nikolova & Nuala A. Sheehan - 2015 - BMC Medical Ethics 16 (1):1-9.
    BackgroundGenealogical research and ancestry testing are popular recreational activities but little is known about the impact of the use of these services on clients’ biological and social families. Ancestry databases are being enriched with self-reported data and data from deoxyribonucleic acid analyses, but also are being linked to other direct-to-consumer genetic testing and research databases. As both family history data and DNA can provide information on more than just the individual, we asked whether companies, as a part of the (...) process, were informing clients, and through them clients’ relatives, of the potential implications of the use and linkage of their personal data.MethodsWe used content analysis to analyse publically-available consent and informational materials provided to potential clients of ancestry and direct-to-consumer genetic testing companies to determine what consent is required, what risks associated with participation were highlighted, and whether the consent or notification of third parties was suggested or required.ResultsWe identified four categories of companies providing: 1) services based only on self-reported data, such as personal or family history; 2) services based only on DNA provided by the client; 3) services using both; and 4) services using both that also have a research component. The amount of information provided on the potential issues varied significantly across the categories of companies. ‘Traditional’ ancestry companies showed the greatest awareness of the implications for family members, while companies only asking for DNA focused solely on the client. While in some cases companies included text recommending clients inform their relatives, showing they recognised the issues, often it was located within lengthy terms and conditions or privacy statements that may not be read by potential clients.ConclusionsWe recommend that companies should make it clearer that clients should inform third parties about their plans to participate, that third parties’ data will be provided to companies, and that that data will be linked to other databases, thus raising privacy and issues on use of data. We also suggest investigating whether a ‘generational consent’ should be created that would include more than just the individual in decisions about participating in genetic investigations. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  10
    Non-Consensual Liability of a Contractual Party: Contract, Negligence, Both, or In-Between?Israel Gilead - 2002 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 3 (2).
    This article makes a comparative examination of the widening spectrum of cases in which both tort law and contract law are employed, jointly or separately, to impose non-consensual liability on a contracting party. The article focuses on liability imposed on a contracting party either toward another contracting party or toward a third party for failure to perform an obligation that, on the one hand, is predicated on and arises from the contract, but, on the other (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  22
    Costly third-party punishment in young children.Katherine McAuliffe, Jillian J. Jordan & Felix Warneken - 2015 - Cognition 134 (C):1-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  37.  32
    Third-Party Certification, Sponsorship, and Consumers’ Ecolabel Use.Nicole Darnall, Hyunjung Ji & Diego A. Vázquez-Brust - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 150 (4):953-969.
    While prior ecolabel research suggests that consumers’ trust of ecolabel sponsors is associated with their purchase of ecolabeled products, we know little about how third-party certification might relate to consumer purchases when trust varies. Drawing on cognitive theory and a stratified random sample of more than 1200 consumers, we assess how third-party certification relates to consumers’ use of ecolabels across different program sponsors. We find that consumers’ trust of government and environmental NGOs to provide credible environmental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  89
    Third Parties and the Social Scaffolding of Forgiveness.Margaret Urban Walker - 2013 - Journal of Religious Ethics 41 (3):495-512.
    It is widely accepted that only the victim of a wrong can forgive that wrong. Several philosophers have recently defended “third-party forgiveness,” the scenario in which A, who is not the victim of a wrong in any sense, forgives B for a wrong B did to C. Focusing on Glen Pettigrove's argument for third-party forgiveness, I will defend the victim's unique standing to forgive, by appealing to the fact that in forgiving, victims must absorb severe and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  39. Third Party Duty of Justice.Kumie Hattori - 2024 - Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 110 (1):5-29.
    This paper explores the theoretical basis of the third party’s duty of justice as to grave human rights violations, presenting role obligations as the best complement to the literature. It begins with discussions on agents of justice in duty-based theories, notably O’Neill’s account on global justice, and rights-based theories, which are both included in the institution-centred perspective. I claim that these studies have failed to consider an individual duty bearer’s motive, autonomous reasoning and integrity in relation to justice, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  84
    Routine third party disclosure of hiv results to identifiable sexual partners in sub-Saharan Africa.Francis Masiye & Robert Ssekubugu - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (5):341-348.
    The challenges of dealing with disclosure of HIV status cause frustration to health care providers and counselors. This frustration follows from the already known high risk to the third party on one hand and our ethical obligation to “respect persons” in terms of privacy and confidentiality on the other side. Given the stubbornly low rates of voluntary disclosure (partner notification) among couples, however, it is quite tempting to suggest a paradigm of routine third party disclosure to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  46
    What Third-Party Forgiveness Has to Offer.Ashton Black - 2023 - Dialogue 62 (3):449-458.
    There are strong moral reasons to acknowledge that third parties can have the standing to forgive. Third-party refusals to forgive can reinforce the moral agency and value of women and disrupt the gendering of forgiveness. Third-party forgiveness can also be crucial for restorative justice aims, like recognizing the value of wrongdoers. Lastly, many victim-only accounts of forgiveness are problematic and utilize an individualistic conception of the self that reinforces the logic of misogyny. Victim-only accounts of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Third-Party Risks in Research: Should IRBs Address Them?Daniel Hausman - 2007 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 29 (3).
    The risks to groups posed by research involving human beings—including genetics research—should be conceived of as a species of third-party risks. The important task of protecting third parties from the risks posed by the conduct and the findings of research should not be assigned to IRBs because they are not designed or equipped to handle such a broad responsibility. The serious problems raised by third-party risks require an integration of policy-making and regulation that is beyond (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  14
    The ThirdParty Notification Dilemma.Ann K. Adams - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (s3):31-32.
    In their report in this supplement on research regulatory systems, Barbara Bierer and Mark Barnes note that, when research misconduct has been detected but not yet proven, the individual with institutional responsibility for oversight of research misconduct investigations “may determine that notification of relevant journals or professional societies and correction or full retraction of implicated papers or presentations is appropriate. In those cases, even when a finding of research misconduct per se has not been made or has not been explicitly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  21
    Third Party Funding in Arbitration: Questions and Justifications.Khaldoun S. Qtiashat & Ali K. Qtaishat - 2019 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 34 (2):341-356.
    Utility of third party funding is an undeniable fact, especially where a party is under financial strain, yet its increased usage in private arbitration has given rise to a number of substantive and procedural issues. In view of this, the present paper attempts to map the growing utility or otherwise of the mechanism of third party funding, and analyses its various nuances and legal sustainability within the framework of international arbitration. Further, an attempt is made (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  55
    The Third Party. Levinas on the Intersection of the Ethical and the Political.Robert Bernasconi - 1999 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 30 (1):76-87.
  46.  12
    Third-Party Punishment or Compensation? It Depends on the Reputational Benefits.Zhuang Li, Gengdan Hu, Lei Xu & Qiangqiang Li - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Third-party fairness maintenance could win some reputational benefits, and it includes two methods: punishment and compensation. We predicted that the third parties' preference between punishment and compensation are affected by whether they are free to choose between the two methods, and the affection could be interpreted through reputational benefits. The present study includes two sections. In Study 1, the participants acted as fourth parties who were asked to rate the reputations of the third parties who had (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Taking it Personally: Third-Party Forgiveness, Close Relationships, and the Standing to Forgive.Rosalind Chaplin - 2019 - Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 9:73-94.
    This paper challenges a common dogma of the literature on forgiveness: that only victims have the standing to forgive. Attacks on third-party forgiveness generally come in two forms. One form of attack suggests that it follows from the nature of forgiveness that third-party forgiveness is impossible. Another form of attack suggests that although third-party forgiveness is possible, it is always improper or morally inappropriate for third parties to forgive. I argue against both of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48. Equal Deeds, Different Needs – Need, Accountability, and Resource Availability in Third-Party Distribution Decisions.Alexander Max Bauer & Jan Romann - 2020 - In Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), The Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
    We present a vignette study conducted with a quota sample of the German population (n = 400). Subjects had to redistribute a good between two hypothetical persons who contributed equally to the available amount but differed in quantity needed and the reason for their neediness. On a within-subjects level, we tested for the effects of need, accountability, and resource availability on their third-party distribution decisions. Between subjects, we further varied the kinds of needs: The persons either needed the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  37
    Third-party apologies, theory and form.Marc A. Cohen - 2022 - American Philosophical Quarterly 59 (3):287-295.
    When A wrongs B while C observes, or when B tells C afterward, C might apologize. This could seem to be an imprecise or merely metaphorical use of the word ‘apology’ to refer to an expression of sympathy. But this short paper explains how third-party apologies function as apologies (they restore respect to B, the victim, that was undermined by the wrongdoer A); it explains why such an apology could be morally necessary on C's part; and it provides (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  15
    Third party sanctions in games with communication.Jan Obłój & Katarzyna Abramczuk - 2017 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 50 (1):109-138.
    This paper discusses the relation between communication and preservation of social norms guarded by third-party sanctions. In 2001 Jonathan Bendor and Piotr Swistak derived deductively the existence of such norms from a simple boundedly rational choice model. Their analysis was based on a perfect public information case. We take into account communication and analyse at the micro level the process of production and interpretation of information on which decisions are based. We show that when information is fully private (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991