Results for 'right to believe'

999 found
Order:
  1.  10
    The Right to Believe: Perspectives in Religious Epistemology.Dariusz Łukasiewicz & Roger Pouivet (eds.) - 2011 - De Gruyter.
    In the twentieth century, many contemporary epistemologists in the analytic tradition have entered into debate regarding the right to belief with new tools: Richard Swinburne, Anthony Kenny, Alvin Plantinga, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Peter van Inwagen defend or contest the requirement of evidence for any justified belief. The best things we can do, it seems, is to examine more attentively the true notion of "right to believe," especially about religious matters. This is exactly what the contributors in this book (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  77
    The right to believe truth paradoxes of moral regret for no belief and the role(s) of logic in philosophy of religion.Billy Joe Lucas - 2012 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72 (2):115-138.
    I offer you some theories of intellectual obligations and rights (virtue Ethics): initially, RBT (a Right to Believe Truth, if something is true it follows one has a right to believe it), and, NDSM (one has no right to believe a contradiction, i.e., No right to commit Doxastic Self-Mutilation). Evidence for both below. Anthropology, Psychology, computer software, Sociology, and the neurosciences prove things about human beliefs, and History, Economics, and comparative law can provide (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. The right to believe at one's own risk.George Stuart Fullerton - 1907 - Philosophical Review 16 (4):408-418.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Justification and the right to believe.Jeffrey Glick - 2010 - Philosophical Quarterly 60 (240):532-544.
    Some philosophers have attempted to utilize the conceptual tools of ethics in order to understand epistemology. One instantiation of this understands justification in terms of having a certain kind of epistemic right, namely, a right to believe. In variations of this theme, some hold that justification involves having the authority to believe, or being entitled to believe. But by examining the putative analogies between different versions of rights and justification, I demonstrate that justification should not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  5
    A Right to Believe.Richard L. Barber - 1955 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 4:19-30.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  78
    A Right to Believe.Richard L. Barber - 1955 - Tulane Studies in Philosophy 4:19-30.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The Right to Believe.Peter S. Williams - 1997 - The Philosophers' Magazine 1 (1):49-51.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  54
    The Right to Believe and Skepticism.Edward Shirley - 1989 - Southwest Philosophy Review 5 (1):87-95.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  6
    The Right to Believe.Peter S. Williams - 1997 - The Philosophers' Magazine 1:49-51.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  14
    Epistemic Entitlement: The Right to Believe.Hannes Ole Matthiessen - 2014 - New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
    In Epistemic Entitlement. The Right to Believe Hannes Ole Matthiessen develops a social externalist account of epistemic entitlement and perceptual knowledge. The basic idea is that positive epistemic status should be understood as a specific kind of epistemic right, that is a right to believe. Since rights have consequences for how others are required to treat the bearer of the right, they have to be publicly accessible. The author therefore suggests that epistemic entitlement can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The nature and value of the.Moral Right To Privacy - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):329.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. On moral arguments against.A. Legal Right To Unilateral - 2006 - Public Affairs Quarterly 20 (2):115.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  4
    The Right to Believe[REVIEW]E. Stettheimer - 1910 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 7 (12):330-333.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  10
    In Which Religion Do I Have the Right to Believe? An Analysis of the Will-to-Believe Argument.Betül Akdemi̇r-süleyman - 2022 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 26 (3):1197-1213.
    The ethics of belief involves an inquiry into what beliefs are legitimate to hold, including religious beliefs. Whatever the criteria determined in such an investigation, adopting a belief that does not meet this criterion is seen as illegitimate and it is considered an ethical violation. English mathematician W. K. Clifford (d. 1879) defines “sufficient evidence” as a criterion in his famous essay, “The Ethics of Belief”. Clifford’s evidence-centered argument becomes one of the most frequent references in the evidentialist objection against (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  4
    Rowland's Right to Believe.E. Stettheimer - 1910 - Journal of Philosophy 7:330.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  9
    Clifford's Principle and Its Opponents. Critical Notes on the Right to Believe.Michał Rogalski - 2022 - Zagadnienia Naukoznawstwa 55 (4):79-93.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  34
    James's doctrine of "the right to believe".Dickinson S. Miller - 1942 - Philosophical Review 51 (6):541-558.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  14
    James's Doctrine of "The Right to Believe".Dickinson S. Miller - 1942 - Philosophical Review 51 (6):541.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  34
    James's doctrine of "the right to believe".Jared S. Moore & Dickinson S. Miller - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52 (1):69-70.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  9
    William James, the Transcendent, and the''Right to Believe''.William Sweet - 2007 - Budhi: A Journal of Ideas and Culture 11 (1):183-214.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  95
    The right to hope. Text: Romans 4, 18: »In hope he believed against hope«.Paul Tillich † - 1965 - Neue Zeitschrift für Systematicsche Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 7 (3):371-377.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  8
    Rousseau's doctrine of the right to believe.Norman Wilde - 1917 - Mind 26 (101):12-28.
  24. Rousseau's Doctrine of the Right to Believe.Norman Wilde - 1917 - Philosophical Review 26:678.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  5
    Do We Have the Epistemic Right to Believe in Jesus?Jacek Wojtysiak - 2011 - In Dariusz Łukasiewicz & Roger Pouivet (eds.), The Right to Believe: Perspectives in Religious Epistemology. De Gruyter. pp. 103-114.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  21
    Pragmatismo Americano: O Direito de Crer diante da Morte de Deus (American Pragmatism: The Right to Believe ahead the Death of Good) - DOI: 10.5752/P.2175-5841.2010v8n18p104. [REVIEW]Rafael da Silva Mattos - 2010 - Horizonte 8 (18):104-126.
    Pragmatismo é um movimento filosófico que inclui aqueles que afirmam que uma proposição é verdadeira se funciona de forma satisfatória, que o significado de uma proposição pode ser encontrado nas conseqüências práticas de aceitá-la, e que as idéias pouco práticas devem ser rejeitadas. O Pragmatismo começou no final do século XIX, com Charles Sanders Peirce (Como tornar nossas idéias mais claras, Fixação da Crença) e foi desenvolvido na obra de William James (Peirce e James eram membros do Clube Metafísico). O (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. The Right Thing to Believe.Ralph Wedgwood - 2013 - In Timothy Chan (ed.), The Aim of Belief. Oxford University Press. pp. 123-139.
    Many philosophers have claimed that “belief aims at the truth”. But is there any interpretation of this claim on which it counts as true? According to some philosophers, the best interpretation of the claim takes it as the normative thesis that belief is subject to a truth-norm. The goal of this essay is to clarify this normative interpretation of the claim. First, the claim can be developed so that it applies to partial beliefs as well as to flat-out full beliefs. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  28.  22
    The right (not) to believe. A reply to Pascal Engel.Roger Pouivet - 2017 - Philosophia Scientiae 21:147-164.
    Pascal Engel a publié un article intitulé « Le droit de ne pas croire ». Il y défend la thèse que les croyances religieuses sont incapables de satisfaire la norme épistémique de preuve ou de raison suffisante. Dès lors, elles seraient irrationnelles. Ne peut-on pas mettre en question une telle norme? Les croyances religieuses ne sont certes pas légitimes si elles sont fausses. Mais elles n’ont pas besoin d’être justifiées pour être rationnelles. Ma réponse à Pascal Engel suppose une épistémologie (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Pragmatismo Americano: O Direito de Crer diante da Morte de Deus (American Pragmatism: The Right to Believe ahead the Death of Good)-DOI: 10.5752/P. 2175-5841.2010 v8n18p104. [REVIEW]Rafael da Silva Mattos - 2010 - Horizonte 8 (18):104-126.
  30.  24
    William James and the Right to Over-Believe.William Lad Sessions - 1981 - Philosophy Research Archives 7:996-1045.
    William James's essay, "The Will to Believe," is interpreted as a philosophical argument for two conclusions: (l) Some over-beliefs—i.e., beliefs going beyond the available evidence—are rationally justified under certain conditions; and (2) "The Religious Hypothesis" is justified for some people under these conditions. Section I defends viewing James as presenting arguments, Sections II-III try to formulate the dual conclusions more precisely, and Section IT defends this reading against alternative interpretations. Section 7, the heart of the paper, elaborates five logically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  22
    Nobody Has the Right to Tell Me What to Believe or Do.Stephen T. Davis - 2018 - Philosophia Christi 20 (1):169-181.
    The word “autonomy” has many uses in contemporary philosophy and culture, some of them helpful. But Joel Feinberg says, “I am autonomous if I rule me, and no one else rules I.” Certain philosophers turn this sort of sentiment into an argument against religion. A principle of obedience to God—so they say—violates one’s personal autonomy. In the present paper, I reply to such arguments and try to sort out what is acceptable and what is unacceptable about autonomy.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. From rights to prerogatives.Daniel Muñoz - 2020 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (3):608-623.
    Deontologists believe in two key exceptions to the duty to promote the good: restrictions forbid us from harming others, and prerogatives permit us not to harm ourselves. How are restrictions and prerogatives related? A promising answer is that they share a source in rights. I argue that prerogatives cannot be grounded in familiar kinds of rights, only in something much stranger: waivable rights against oneself.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33. Deciding to Believe Redux.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2014 - In Jonathan Matheson Rico Vitz (ed.), The Ethics of Belief: Individual and Social. Oxford University Press. pp. 33-50.
    The ways in which we exercise intentional agency are varied. I take the domain of intentional agency to include all that we intentionally do versus what merely happens to us. So the scope of our intentional agency is not limited to intentional action. One can also exercise some intentional agency in omitting to act and, importantly, in producing the intentional outcome of an intentional action. So, for instance, when an agent is dieting, there is an exercise of agency both with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  43
    The Right and Duty to Will to Believe.Peter Kauber & Peter H. Hare - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):327 - 343.
    Rights and duties to will to believe have too long been considered an embarrassing indulgence by philosophers who pride themselves on their methodological rigor. A fresh look at William James's work will show how a more robust, though no less analytically rigorous, ethics of belief is possible.The history of James's ethics of belief is a stormy one, filled with mainly hostile criticisms on the part of others, with seminal suggestions, gropings, and retractions on the part of James himself. At (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  26
    The Right to Stay as a Control Right.Valeria Ottonelli - 2020 - In David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne & Steven Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 6. Oxford University Press. pp. 87-117.
    This chapter sides with those who believe that a right to stay should be counted among fundamental human rights. However, it also acknowledges that there are good reasons for objecting to the most popular justifications of the right to stay, which are based on the assumption that people have valuable ties to their community of residence and that people’s life plans are located where they live. In response to these qualms, this chapter argues that the best way (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. To Believe or not to Believe - That is not the (Only) Question: the Hybrid View of Privacy.Lauritz Munch & Jakob Mainz - 2023 - The Journal of Ethics 27 (3):245-261.
    In this paper, we defend what we call the ‘Hybrid View’ of privacy. According to this view, an individual has privacy if, and only if, no one else forms an epistemically warranted belief about the individual’s personal matters, nor perceives them. We contrast the Hybrid View with what seems to be the most common view of what it means to access someone’s personal matters, namely the Belief-Based View. We offer a range of examples that demonstrate why the Hybrid View is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  27
    The Right to Emigrate.Daniel Sharp - 2023 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 24 (3).
    It is widely believed that there’s a right to emigrate. But what justifies this right? This paper explores this issue. It first argues that existing defenses of the right to emigrate are incomplete. It then outlines a novel egalitarian defense of the right to emigrate, on which that right is in part justified as a protection against social inequality. After considering objections, it argues that this account of the right to emigrate entails a limited (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. Scanlon's Promising Proposal and the Right Kind of Reasons to Believe.Mark van Roojen - 2013 - In Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Volume 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 59-78.
    T. M. Scanlon suggests that the binding nature of promises itself plays a role in allowing a promisee rationally to expect follow through even while that binding nature itself depends on the promisee’s rational expectation of follow through. Kolodny and Wallace object that this makes the account viciously circular. The chapter defends Scanlon’s theory from this objection. It argues that the basic complaint is a form of wrong kinds of reason objection. The thought is that the promisee’s reason to expect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Ectogenesis, abortion and a right to the death of the fetus.Joona Räsänen - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (9):697-702.
    Many people believe that the abortion debate will end when at some point in the future it will be possible for fetuses to develop outside the womb. Ectogenesis, as this technology is called, would make possible to reconcile pro-life and pro-choice positions. That is because it is commonly believed that there is no right to the death of the fetus if it can be detached alive and gestated in an artificial womb. Recently Eric Mathison and Jeremy Davis defended (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  40. The Limits of the Rights to Free Thought and Expression.Barrett Emerick - 2021 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 31 (2):133-152.
    It is often held that people have a moral right to believe and say whatever they want. For instance, one might claim that they have a right to believe racist things as long as they keep those thoughts to themselves. Or, one might claim that they have a right to pursue any philosophical question they want as long as they do so with a civil tone. In this paper I object to those claims and argue (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  18
    "This house believes that the state of Israel has the right to exist" -- oxford union debate speech in favour of the.Ted Honderich - manuscript
    What is it to have a moral right to get or to keep something? The answer comes from what is different -- having a legal right. To have a legal right to something is to have the support of the law of the land, positive law, good or bad, in getting or keeping the thing.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. The Right to Arms as a Means-Right.Lester Hunt - 2011 - Public Affairs Quarterly 25 (2):113-130.
    1. Two IssuesIn recent years, a number of philosophers have discussed the possibility that the widely recognized right of self-defense includes another, more controversial right: a right to arms, where “arms” is understood to include guns. I will argue in what follows that the right of self-defense does indeed have this feature, and I will offer a new explanation of why it does so—an explanation that, despite its novelty is, I believe, deeply rooted in common (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  22
    The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, and Human Immortality.William James - 2017 - Createspace Independent Publishing Platform.
    Several of William James' finest essays are brought together in this collection, including his spiritual masterwork The Will to Believe, and his famous lecture concerning immortality. The Will to Believe was first delivered as a lengthy lecture by William James in 1896. Following a strong reception, it was later published as a distinct book in its own right. Setting out to defend the right of individuals to be religious irrespective of pure logic and reason, the lecture (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  44.  28
    The Right to Choose: Why Governments Should Compel the Tobacco Industry To Disclose Their Ingredients.H. E. May & J. S. Wigand - 2005 - Essays in Philosophy 6 (2):405-422.
    Pursuant to the Doctrine of Consumer Sovereignty, we believe that tobacco companies should be compelled to disclose their ingredients so that the public health community can make more informed recommendations in order to protect consumer autonomy and sovereignty. However, a recent decision by the First Circuit precludes such a disclosure since it would be unduly burdensome to the industry, while granting only minimal gains to the public. We argue that many of the Court’s key claims rest on a misunderstanding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  13
    Hard to Believe: Produced by Ken Stone and Irene Silber, 2015, Swoop Films and Stone Soup Productions.Holly Louise Northam - 2016 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 13 (2):353-356.
    This article presents a review of Hard to Believe, a compelling documentary reporting the forced organ procurement and death of Chinese prisoners of conscience. The documentary is targeted to ignite political and public pressure to stop these practices that are thought to be motivated by financial and political gain. Narrated by journalist and author Ethan Gutmann, the documentary pricks at the collective conscience, as credible witnesses provide evidence that point to an abrogation of every ethical principle ascribed to legitimate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  36
    Rights to the Oceans: Foundational Arguments Reconsidered.Cara Nine - 2018 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 36 (4):626-642.
    This article examines theories of ocean rights based on the works of Hugo Grotius and Samuel von Pufendorf. Grotius's object‐centred view uses features of the natural world to justify claims to external objects. I show that Grotius's view is inadequate, because it relies on an outdated claim that oceanic resources are sufficiently abundant for anybody to use. Further, adaptations of his view are wanting, because they either rely on arbitrary distinctions or disregard the values of cultural minorities. Pufendorf's relational view (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  39
    The Right to Feel Comfortable: Implicit Bias and the Moral Potential of Discomfort.Ditte Marie Munch-Jurisic - 2020 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23 (1):237-250.
    An increasingly popular view in scholarly literature and public debate on implicit biases holds that there is progressive moral potential in the discomfort that liberals and egalitarians feel when they realize they harbor implicit biases. The strong voices among such discomfort advocates believe we have a moral and political duty to confront people with their biases even though we risk making them uncomfortable. Only a few voices have called attention to the aversive effects of discomfort. Such discomfort skeptics warn (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  19
    The Right to Mission in Human Rights Law, “Mission to Amish People” and “Jews for Jesus”.Maria Grazia Martino - 2015 - Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies 14 (42):78-99.
    This paper examines the position of international human rights law towards missionary or proselytizing activities with a special focus on the American context. By evaluating UN legal acts such as the 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the 1960 Arcot Krishnaswami Study and the 1981 Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief and the American Convention of Human Rights, it investigates the extent to which such activities fall within the scope of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Moral Right to Keep and Bear Firearms.C'Zar Bernstein, Timothy Hsiao & Matthew Palumbo - 2015 - Public Affairs Quarterly 29 (4).
    The moral right to keep and bear arms is entailed by the moral right of self-defense. We argue that the ownership and use of firearms is a reasonable means of exercising these rights. Given their defensive value, there is a strong presumption in favor of enacting civil rights to keep and bear arms ranging from handguns to ‘assault rifles.’ Thus, states are morally obliged as a matter of justice to recognize basic liberties for firearm ownership and usage. Throughout (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. A right to be lazy? Busyness in retrospective.Gary Cross - 2005 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 72 (2):263-286.
    I recall an old man selling Paul Lafargue’s Right to be Lazy on a busy street in the Latin Quarter in the 1980s. At the time, I was writing then my first book on the history of work time and leisure and felt by seeing this strange and grumpy man so energetically promoting the nearly forgotten work of Marx’s son-in-law somehow vindicated in my efforts. Paul Lafargue’s pamphlet makes an interesting assumption: The “natural” state of human being was relaxation (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999