Results for 'practical interests'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Knowledge, Practical Interests, and Rising Tides.Stephen R. Grimm - 2015 - In John Greco & David Henderson (eds.), Epistemic Evaluation: Point and Purpose in Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    Defenders of pragmatic encroachment in epistemology (or what I call practicalism) need to address two main problems. First, the view seems to imply, absurdly, that knowledge can come and go quite easily—in particular, that it might come and go along with our variable practical interests. We can call this the stability problem. Second, there seems to be no fully satisfying way of explaining whose practical interests matter. We can call this the “whose stakes?” problem. I argue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  2.  9
    Over-Constrained Systems.Michael Jampel, Eugene C. Freuder, Michael Maher & International Conference on Principles and Practice of Constraint Programming - 1996 - Springer Verlag.
    This volume presents a collection of refereed papers reflecting the state of the art in the area of over-constrained systems. Besides 11 revised full papers, selected from the 24 submissions to the OCS workshop held in conjunction with the First International Conference on Principles and Practice of Constraint Programming, CP '95, held in Marseilles in September 1995, the book includes three comprehensive background papers of central importance for the workshop papers and the whole field. Also included is an introduction by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Practical Interests, Relevant Alternatives, and Knowledge Attributions: An Empirical Study.Joshua May, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Jay G. Hull & Aaron Zimmerman - 2010 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2):265–273.
    In defending his interest-relative account of knowledge in Knowledge and Practical Interests (2005), Jason Stanley relies heavily on intuitions about several bank cases. We experimentally test the empirical claims that Stanley seems to make concerning our common-sense intuitions about these bank cases. Additionally, we test the empirical claims that Jonathan Schaffer seems to make in his critique of Stanley. We argue that our data impugn what both Stanley and Schaffer claim our intuitions about such cases are. To account (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  4. Knowledge, practical interests, and rising tides.Stephen R. Grimm - 2015 - In David K. Henderson & John Greco (eds.), Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology. Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Knowledge and practical interests.Jason Stanley - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Jason Stanley presents a startling and provocative claim about knowledge: that whether or not someone knows a proposition at a given time is in part determined by his or her practical interests, i.e. by how much is at stake for that person at that time. In defending this thesis, Stanley introduces readers to a number of strategies for resolving philosophical paradox, making the book essential not just for specialists in epistemology but for all philosophers interested in philosophical methodology. (...)
  6.  57
    Précis of Knowledge and Practical Interests.Jason Stanley - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):168-172.
    Jason Stanley's "Knowledge and Practical Interests" is a brilliant book, combining insights about knowledge with a careful examination of how recent views in epistemology fit with the best of recent linguistic semantics. Although I am largely convinced by Stanley's objections to epistemic contextualism, I will try in what follows to formulate a version that might have some prospect of escaping his powerful critique.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   513 citations  
  7. Knowledge, Experiments, and Practical Interests.Ángel Pinillos - 2012 - In Jessica Brown & Mikkel Gerken (eds.), Knowledge Ascriptions. Oxford University Press. pp. 192.
    Recently, some philosophers have defended the idea that knowledge is an interest-relative notion. According to this thesis, whether an agent knows P may depend on the practical costs of her being wrong about P. This perspective marks a radical departure from traditional accounts that take knowledge to be a purely intellectual concept. I think there is much to say on behalf of the interest-relative notion. In this paper, I report on some new evidence which strongly suggests that ordinary people’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  8. Knowledge and Practical Interests.Jason Stanley - 2006 - Critica 38 (114):98-107.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   615 citations  
  9.  98
    Lies, Harm, And Practical Interests.Andreas Stokke - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 98 (2):329-345.
    This paper outlines an account of the ethics of lying, which accommodates two main ideas about lying. The first of these, Anti-Deceptionalism, is the view that lying does not necessarily involve intentions to deceive. The second, Anti-Absolutism, is the view that lying is not always morally wrong. It is argued that lying is not wrong in itself, but rather the wrong in lying is explained by different factors in different cases. In some cases such factors may include deceptive intentions on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  10. Vagueness and Practical Interests.Paula Sweeney & Elia Zardini - 2011 - In Paul Egre & Nathan Klinedinst (eds.), Vagueness and Language Use. Palgrave MacMillan.
    In this paper we focus mainly on a kind of contextualism theory of vagueness according to which the context dependence has its source in the variation of our practical interests. We largely focus on Fara's version of the theory but our observations work at different levels of generality, some relevant only to the specifics of Fara's theory others relevant to all contextualist theories of a certain type.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  12
    Précis of Knowledge and Practical Interests.Jason Stanley - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):168-172.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  59
    Knowledge and Practical Interests.Ram Neta - 2012 - Philosophical Review 121 (2):298-301.
  13. Jason Stanley, Knowledge and practical interests.Iris Vidmar - 2008 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 22:167-173.
  14. Jason Stanley, Knowledge and Practical Interests.T. Basboll - 2007 - Philosophy in Review 27 (3):225.
  15. Aesthetic and Practical Interests and their Bodily Ground.Richard Shusterman - 2006 - William James Studies 1.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  28
    Pure science and practical interests: The origins of the Agricultural Research Council, 1930–1937. [REVIEW]Timothy DeJager - 1993 - Minerva 31 (2):129-150.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  17. Précis of knowledge and practical interests[REVIEW]Jason Stanley - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):168–172.
    Our intuitions about whether someone knows that p vary even fixing the intuitively epistemic features of that person’s situation. Sometimes they vary with features of our own situation, and sometimes they vary with features of the putative knower’s situation. If the putative knower is in a risky situation and her belief that p is pivotal in achieving a positive outcome of one of the actions available to her, or avoiding a negative one, we often feel she must be in a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  68
    Review of Knowledge and Practical Interests[REVIEW]Ram Neta - 2012 - Philosophical Review 121 (2):298-301.
  19.  22
    Knowledge and Practical Interests[REVIEW]Iris Vidmar - 2008 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1):167-173.
  20.  71
    Review: Knowledge and Practical Interests[REVIEW]K. DeRose - 2007 - Mind 116 (462):486-489.
  21. Critical study of John Hawthorne's knowledge and lotteries and Jason Stanley's knowledge and practical interests[REVIEW]Jeremy Fantl & Matthew McGrath - 2009 - Noûs 43 (1):178-192.
  22.  38
    Review of Jason Stanley, Knowledge and Practical Interests[REVIEW]Duncan Pritchard - 2006 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (6).
  23. Review of J. Stanley, Knowledge and Practical Interests[REVIEW]Keith DeRose - 2007 - Mind 116:486-489.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  66
    Correction: Is current practice around late termination of pregnancy eugenic and discriminatory? Maternal interests and abortion.Bmj Publishing Group Ltd And Institute Of Medical Ethics - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (2):132-132.
    Savulescu J. Is current practice around late termination of pregnancy eugenic and discriminatory? Maternal interests and abortion. J Med Ethics 2001;27:165–71. Lachlan de Crespigny contributed in a major way to the conceptualisation, design, administration of surveys, ….
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. In search of public interest lawyering : what does it take to give practical content to better professional norms?Richard Moorhead & Steven Vaughan - 2023 - In Julian S. Webb (ed.), Leading works in legal ethics. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Why Practical Rationality Is Not Interestingly Belief-Relative.Kurt Sylvan - manuscript
  27.  16
    Practice guidelines, patient interests, and risky procedures.Isobel A. Ross - 1996 - Bioethics 10 (4):310–322.
    A clinical scenario is described where an anaesthetist is concerned about the seemingly high risk/benefit ratio relating to laparoscopic versus standard inguinal hernia operations. Some options for further action by the anaesthetist are introduced. The remainder of the paper explores the question of who can legitimately assess the acceptability of risk/benefit ratios, and defends the use of practice guidelines at the expense of so called clinical freedom. It is argued that respect for persons is not breached by limiting the treatment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  9
    Practice Guidelines, Patient Interests, and Risky Procedures.Isobel A. Ross - 1996 - Bioethics 10 (4):310-323.
    A clinical scenario is described where an anaesthetist is concerned about the seemingly high risk/benefit ratio relating to laparoscopic versus standard inguinal hernia operations. Some options for further action by the anaesthetist are introduced. The remainder of the paper explores the question of who can legitimately assess the acceptability of risk/benefit ratios, and defends the use of practice guidelines at the expense of so called clinical freedom. It is argued that respect for persons is not breached by limiting the treatment (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  10
    Practice Guidelines, Patient Interests, and Risky Procedures.Isobel A. Ross - 2008 - Bioethics 10 (4):310-323.
    A clinical scenario is described where an anaesthetist is concerned about the seemingly high risk/benefit ratio relating to laparoscopic versus standard inguinal hernia operations. Some options for further action by the anaesthetist are introduced. The remainder of the paper explores the question of who can legitimately assess the acceptability of risk/benefit ratios, and defends the use of practice guidelines at the expense of so called clinical freedom. It is argued that respect for persons is not breached by limiting the treatment (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Conflict of interest policies in science and medical journals: Editorial practices and author disclosures.Sheldon Krimsky & L. S. Rothenberg - 2001 - Science and Engineering Ethics 7 (2):205-218.
    This study examines the extent to which scientific and biomedical journals have adopted conflict of interest (COI) policies for authors, and whether the adoption and content of such policies leads to the publishing of authors’ financial interest disclosure statements by such journals. In particular, it reports the results of a survey of journal editors about their practices regarding COI disclosures. About 16 percent of 1396 highly ranked scientific and biomedical journals had COI policies in effect during 1997. Less than 1 (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  31.  39
    Kant’s Practical Reason As Will: Interest, Recognition, Judgment, and Choice.Yirmiyahu Yovel - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):267 - 294.
    IT IS CHARACTERISTIC OF KANT that he interprets pure practical reason as will. He thereby revolutionizes the notions of both reason and the will. Reason is conceived as interest, a motivating power, even a self-sufficient telos. Moreover, the will is understood as a rational power, that is, as initially structured by the form of law, and striving for universality in both its inner operation and the way it ought to shape the outside world. For such a will, being rational (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Practical reasoning, rationality and its limits-controversy concerning expropriation compensation for purposes in the public-interest.P. Foriers - 1979 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 33 (127):303-324.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  26
    Conflicts of interest in clinical practice and research.Roy G. Spece, David S. Shimm & Allen E. Buchanan (eds.) - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Our society has long sanctioned, at least tacitly, a degree of conflict of interest in medical practice and clinical research as an unavoidable consequence of the different interests of the physician or clinical investigator, the patient or clinical research subject, third party payers or research sponsors, the government, and society as a whole, to name a few. In the past, resolution of these conflicts has been left to the conscience of the individual physician or clinical investigator and to professional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34.  39
    Kant’s Practical Reason As Will: Interest, Recognition, Judgment, and Choice.Yirmiyahu Yovel - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):267-294.
    IT IS CHARACTERISTIC OF KANT that he interprets pure practical reason as will. He thereby revolutionizes the notions of both reason and the will. Reason is conceived as interest, a motivating power, even a self-sufficient telos. Moreover, the will is understood as a rational power, that is, as initially structured by the form of law, and striving for universality in both its inner operation and the way it ought to shape the outside world. For such a will, being rational (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Adjudicating rights or analyzing interests: ethicists’ role in the debate over conscience in clinical practice.Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (3):201-212.
    The analysis of a dispute can focus on either interests, rights, or power. Commentators often frame the conflict over conscience in clinical practice as a dispute between a patient’s right to legally available medical treatment and a clinician’s right to refuse to provide interventions the clinician finds morally objectionable. Multiple sources of unresolvable moral disagreement make resolution in these terms unlikely. One should instead focus on the parties’ interests and the different ways in which the health care delivery (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  59
    Conflicts of interest in drug development: The practices of merck & co., inc.Laurence J. Hirsch - 2002 - Science and Engineering Ethics 8 (3):429-442.
    Conflicts of interest are common and exist in academia, government, and many industries, including pharmaceutical development. Medical journal editors and others have recently criticized “the pharmaceutical industry,” citing concerns over investigator access to data, approaches to analysis of clinical trial data, and publication practices. Merck & Co., Inc. is a global, research-driven pharmaceutical company that discovers, develops, manufactures, and markets a broad range of human and animal health products, directly and through its joint ventures. Although part of its mission is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  17
    On the interest of practical reason in hope.Thomas McCarthy - 2021 - Constellations 28 (1):11-16.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Morality, self-interest, and two kinds of prudential practical rationality.John Lemos - 2006 - Philosophia 34 (1):85-93.
    : In this article it is assumed that human goodness is to be judged with respect to how well one does at practical reasoning. It is acknowledged that there is a difference between moral practical reasoning and prudential practical reasoning and what these would recommend sometimes conflict. A distinction is then made between absolute PPR and relative PPR and it is argued that doing well at absolute PPR is always consistent with MPR. It is also argued that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  19
    Conflicts of interest in divisions of general practice.N. Palmer, A. Braunack-Mayer, W. Rogers, C. Provis & G. Cullity - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (12):715-717.
    Community-based healthcare organisations manage competing, and often conflicting, priorities. These conflicts can arise from the multiple roles these organisations take up, and from the diverse range of stakeholders to whom they must be responsive. Often such conflicts may be titled conflicts of interest; however, what precisely constitutes such conflicts and what should be done about them is not always clear. Clarity about the duties owed by organisations and the roles they assume can help identify and manage some of these conflicts. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  23
    Balancing competing interests and obligations in mental health‐care practice and policy.Jeffrey Kirby - 2019 - Bioethics 33 (6):699-707.
    It is often challenging for mental health‐care providers and health organizations to perform their various roles and to meet their varied obligations. In complex mental health‐care circumstances the concurrent application of relevant ethical principles and values often leads to the emergence of completing obligations that need to be carefully weighed and balanced in the making of care‐related decisions. Although some clinical circumstances, such as those potentially triggering the duty to warn, are adequately guided by existing rules based on legal precedents, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  48
    Is current practice around late termination of pregnancy eugenic and discriminatory? Maternal interests and abortion.J. Savulescu - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (3):165-171.
    The attitudes of Australian practitioners working in clinical genetics and obstetrical ultrasound were surveyed on whether termination of pregnancy (TOP) should be available for conditions ranging from mild to severe fetal abnormality and for non-medical reasons.These were compared for terminations at 13 weeks and 24 weeks. It was found that some practitioners would not facilitate TOP at 24 weeks even for lethal or major abnormalities, fewer practitioners support TOP at 24 weeks compared with 13 weeks for any condition, and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Underreporting of conflicts of interest in clinical practice guidelines: cross sectional study. [REVIEW]Julie Bolette Bindslev, Jeppe Schroll, Peter Gøtzsche & Andreas Lundh - 2013 - BMC Medical Ethics 14 (1):19.
    Conflicts of interest affect recommendations in clinical guidelines and disclosure of such conflicts is important. However, not all conflicts of interest are disclosed. Using a public available disclosure list we determined the prevalence and underreporting of conflicts of interest among authors of clinical guidelines on drug treatments.
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. The accountability problem in public interest practice: old paradigms and new directions.Scott lCummings - 2012 - In Leslie C. Levin & Lynn Mather (eds.), Lawyers in practice: ethical decision making in context. London: University of Chicago Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. The accountability problem in public interest practice : old paradigms and new directions.Scott lCummings - 2012 - In Leslie C. Levin & Lynn Mather (eds.), Lawyers in practice: ethical decision making in context. London: University of Chicago Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  16
    In the public interest: autonomy and resistance to methods of standardising nurses’ advice and practices from a health call centre in Perth, Western Australia.Ann-Claire Larsen - 2005 - Nursing Inquiry 12 (2):135-143.
    In the public interest: autonomy and resistance to methods of standardising nurses’ advice and practices from a health call centre in Perth, Western Australia The history of nursing is replete with examples of nurses battling for autonomy over their education, knowledge and work practices. The latest battleground is HealthDirect, Australia's first medial call centre, where nurses are required to meet externally imposed clinical standards while satisfying legal and financial obligations. These objectives are arguably achieved when nurses assess callers’ health problems (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  12
    Obesity Epidemic Entrepreneurs: Types, Practices and Interests.Gary Prtichard, Robert Hollands & Lee F. Monaghan - 2010 - Body and Society 16 (2):37-71.
    This article explores the enterprising act of socially constructing fatness, or overweight and obesity, as an individual and collective problem. We argue that this process is complex and hence draw liberally on and extend an eclectic range of scholarship (e.g. the sociology of the body, moral panic theory, critical weight studies) when presenting a typology of obesity epidemic entrepreneurs, that is, those who actively make fatness into a correctable health problem. Using a variety of data, we consider six main ideal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  36
    Task Demands, Task Interest, and Task Performance: Implications for Human Subjects Research and Practicing What We Preach.Arun Pillutla & Daniel M. Eveleth - 2003 - Ethics and Behavior 13 (2):153-172.
    Through the continuous investigation of humans in organizations, we have learned much about motivation, attitudes, and performance. For example, Yukl and others have helped increase our understanding of influence tactics and the effect they have on the performance of subordinates, supervisors, and peers. Some tactics (and combinations of tactics) lead to resistance, some lead to compliance, and some lead to commitment. In this study, we raise the question of whether or not we incorporate our knowledge of these research findings into (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  8
    The Practice of Historical Science. The Deorientation of Historical Interest. [REVIEW]Konrad Fuchs - 1974 - Philosophy and History 7 (2):230-230.
  49.  17
    Autonomy, Interests, Justice and Active Medical Euthanasia.Julian Savulescu - 2015 - In Michael Cholbi & Jukka Varelius (eds.), New Directions in the Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 31-48.
    There are 4 main arguments for euthanasia: (1) arguments appealing to consistency (e.g., from passive to active euthanasia); (2) the argument from respect for autonomy; (3) appeals to justice; and (4) the argument from interests (mercy or relief of suffering). I will argue that only the last is directly relevant to active euthanasia as a medical intervention, though arguments together from autonomy and justice can in practice (through the backdoor) provide a ground for voluntary active medical euthanasia (AME).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  4
    Practical Reason and the Status of Moral Obligation.Robert Audi - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 33 (sup1):197-229.
    The power of skepticism depends on the apparent possibility of rationally asking, for virtually any kind of proposition commonly thought to be known,howit is known or what justifies believing it. Moral claims are among those commonly subjected to skeptical challenges and doubts, even on the part of some people who are not skeptical about ordinary claims regarding the external world. There may be even more skepticism about the possibility of justifying moralactions,particularly if they are against the agent's self-interest. Both problems-how (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000