Results for 'non-assertoric sentences'

993 found
Order:
  1. Non-Declarative Sentences and the Theory of Definite Descriptions.John-Michael Kuczynski - 2004 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 8 (1):119–154.
    This paper shows that Russell’s theory of descriptions gives the wrong se-mantics for definite descriptions occurring in questions and imperatives. Depending on how that theory is applied, it either assigns nonsense to per-fectly meaningful questions and assertions or it assigns meanings that di-verge from the actual semantics of such sentences, even after all pragmatic and contextual variables are allowed for. Given that Russell’s theory is wrong for questions and assertions, it must be wrong for assertoric state-ments; for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  40
    Non-Declarative Sentences and the Theory of Definite Descriptions.John Michael Kuczynski - 2004 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 8 (1):119-154.
    This paper shows that Russell’s theory of descriptions gives the wrong semantics for definite descriptions occurring in questions and imperatives. Depending on how that theory is applied, it either assigns nonsense to perfectly meaningful questions and assertions or it assigns meanings that diverge from the actual semantics of such sentences, even after all pragmatic and contextual variables are allowed for. Given that Russell’s theory is wrong for questions and assertions, it must be wrong for assertoric statements; for the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Against the identification of assertoric content with compositional value.Brian Rabern - 2012 - Synthese 189 (1):75-96.
    This essay investigates whether or not we should think that the things we say are identical to the things our sentences mean. It is argued that these theoretical notions should be distinguished, since assertoric content does not respect the compositionality principle. As a paradigmatic example, Kaplan's formal language LD is shown to exemplify a failure of compositionality. It is demonstrated that by respecting the theoretical distinction between the objects of assertion and compositional values certain conflicts between compositionality and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  4.  22
    Non-sentential assertions and the dependence thesis of word meaning.Tim Kenyon - 1999 - Mind and Language 14 (4):424–440.
    To assert is to utter a sentence under certain conventions, claims Michael Dummett. This view runs afoul of empirical evidence indicating the widespread assertoric use of non‐elliptical words and phrases. Dummett also advances two theses apparently related to his sentence conventionalism: that word meaning depends on sentence meaning, and that language is (in some sense) prior to thought. I argue that these latter two theses are independent of the empirically dubious Sentential Thesis. Plausibly, the wider Dummettian logico‐metaphysical programme is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Belief-like imaginings and perceptual (non-)assertoricity.Alon Chasid & Assaf Weksler - 2020 - Philosophical Psychology 33 (5):731-751.
    A commonly-discussed feature of perceptual experience is that it has ‘assertoric’ or ‘phenomenal’ force. We will start by discussing various descriptions of the assertoricity of perceptual experience. We will then adopt a minimal characterization of assertoricity: a perceptual experience has assertoric force just in case it inclines the perceiver to believe its content. Adducing cases that show that visual experience is not always assertoric, we will argue that what renders these visual experiences non-assertoric is that they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  17
    Non-Assertoric Inference.Robert P. McArthur & David Welker - 1974 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15 (2):225--244.
  7. The Truth about Moods.Kirk Ludwig - 1997 - ProtoSociology 10:19-66.
    Assertoric sentences are sentences which admit of truth or falsity. Non-assertoric sentences, imperatives and interrogatives, have long been a source of difficulty for the view that a theory of truth for a natural language can serve as the core of a theory of meaning. The trouble for truth-theoretic semantics posed by non-assertoric sentences is that, prima facie, it does not make sense to say that imperatives, such as 'Cut your hair', or interrogatives such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  8. Non-declarative Sentences and Communication in Husserl’s Logical Investigations. Contributions to a Theory on Communicative Acts in the Light of Husserl and Austin.Pedro Alves - unknown - Phainomena 74.
    In this paper I discuss the consistency and accuracy of Husserl’s sketch of a theory about non-declarative sentences in the last chapter of Logical Investigations. Whereas the consistency is acknowledged, the accuracy is denied, because Husserl’s treatment of non-declarative phrases such as questions or orders implies that those phrases contain, in some way, a declarative sentence and an objectifying act. To construct a question like »is A B?« as being equivalent to a declarative sentence such as »I ask whether (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  65
    Non-declarative sentences.John-Michael Kuczynski - forthcoming - Principia.
    If S is any well-formed and significant question or command having the form "...the phi...", Russell's Theory of Descriptions entails (i) that S is syntactically ambiguous, and (ii) that there is at least one disambiguation of S that is syntactically ill-formed. Given that each of (i) and (ii) is false, so is the Theory of Descriptions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Frege plagiarized the Stoics.Susanne Bobzien - 2021 - In Fiona Leigh (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy, Keeling Lectures 2011-2018, OPEN ACCESS. University of Chicago Press. pp. 149-206.
    In this extended essay, I argue that Frege plagiarized the Stoics --and I mean exactly that-- on a large scale in his work on the philosophy of logic and language as written mainly between 1890 and his death in 1925 (much of which published posthumously) and possibly earlier. I use ‘plagiarize' (or 'plagiarise’) merely as a descriptive term. The essay is not concerned with finger pointing or casting moral judgement. The point is rather to demonstrate carefully by means of detailed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  11.  34
    Assertive and non-Assertive Sentences. Classifications of the ’oratio perfecta’ in the Thirteenth Century.Christoph Kann - 2004 - In Alfonso Maierù & Luisa Valente (eds.), Medieval Theories on Assertive and Non-Assertive Language. Leo S. Olschki. pp. 245--257.
    Since logic in the 13th century is focussed on syllogistics as its main subject, textbooks on logic provide us with large and detailed treatments of the proposition as the immediate and constitutive basis of the syllogism. In the present paper I will give a survey of these treatments and pay special attention to a certain side-issue, namely to non-assertive sentences and to some difficulties concerning their classification. I will focus on William of Sherwood's apporach to the subject and compare (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  89
    Mood and the Analysis of Non-Declarative Sentences.Deirdre Wilson & Dan Sperber - 1988 - In J. Dancy, J. M. E. Moravcsik & C. C. W. Taylor (eds.), Human Agency: Language, Duty, and Value : Philosophical Essays in Honor of J.O. Urmson. Stanford, Calif: Stanford University Press. pp. 77--101.
    How are non-declarative sentences understood? How do they differ semantically from their declarative counterparts? Answers to these questions once made direct appeal to the notion of illocutionary force. When they proved unsatisfactory, the fault was diagnosed as a failure to distinguish properly between mood and force. For some years now, efforts have been under way to develop a satisfactory account of the semantics of mood. In this paper, we consider the current achievements and future prospects of the mood-based semantic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  13. Two surprisingly non-paradoxical sentences.A. Kukla - 1985 - Logique Et Analyse 28 (9):109.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  33
    Sobre la teoría Fregeana de las oraciones no extensionales (on Frege's theory of non-extensional sentences).Matthias Schirn - 1999 - Theoria 14 (1):131-156.
    En este articulo quiero discutir algunos temas centrales deI tratamiento fregeano de los contextos no extensionales. Limitaré mi discusión al análisis de oraciones de creencia y de la oratio obliqua. En la primera parte, voy a describir dos tipos de teoría dentro deI marco de la semántica de Frege. En particular, compararé y evaluaré los análisis de oraciones no extensionales de primer y segundo nivel que se pueden llevar a cabo en las teorías de ambos tipos. En la segunda parte, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  10
    Motor activation in literal and non-literal sentences: does time matter?Cristina Cacciari & Francesca Pesciarelli - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
  16.  7
    Epistemic stance in Korean assessment pairs: The role of evidential and non-evidential sentence-ending suffixes.Kyoungmi Ha - 2022 - Discourse Studies 24 (6):692-718.
    Studies in conversation analysis have shown that in assessments, various linguistic resources are used to express epistemic stance in ordinary conversation. In Korean conversation, although the evidential and non-evidential functions of sentence-ending suffixes are well recognized, little research has been done on their relation to epistemic stance and their use in assessments. In this study, using naturally-occurring conversation data and the CA framework, I analyze 59 cases of a speaker’s first assessment regarding his/her interlocutor and 49 responses to these first (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Insincerity.Andreas Stokke - 2012 - Noûs 48 (3):496-520.
    This paper argues for an account of insincerity in speech according to which an utterance is insincere if and only if it communicates something that does not correspond to the speaker's conscious attitudes. Two main topics are addressed: the relation between insincerity and the saying-meaning distinction, and the mental attitude underlying insincere speech. The account is applied to both assertoric and non-assertoric utterances of declarative sentences, and to utterances of non-declarative sentences. It is shown how the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  18. Minimalism and Truth-Value Gaps.Richard Holton - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (2):137-168.
    The question is asked whether one can consistently both be a minimalist about truth, and hold that some meaningful assertoric sentences fail to be either true or false. It is shown that one can, but the issues are delicate, and the price is high: one must either refrain from saying that the sentences lack truth values, or else one must invoke a novel non-contraposing three-valued conditional. Finally it is shown that this does not help in reconciling minimalism (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  21
    Fictional force.Andreas Stokke - 2023 - Philosophical Studies 180 (10):3099-3120.
    This paper argues for an account of fictional force, the central characteristic of the kind of non-assertoric speech act that authors of fictions are engaged in. A distinction is drawn between what is true in a fiction and the _fictional record_ comprising what the audience has been told. The papers argues that to utter a sentence with fictional force is to intend that its content be added to a fictional record. It is shown that this view accounts for phenomena (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Questions and Answers about Oppositions.Fabien Schang - 2011 - In Jean-Yves Beziau & Gillman Payette (eds.), The Square of Opposition: A General Framework for Cognition. Peter Lang. pp. 289-319.
    A general characterization of logical opposition is given in the present paper, where oppositions are defined by specific answers in an algebraic question-answer game. It is shown that opposition is essentially a semantic relation of truth values between syntactic opposites, before generalizing the theory of opposition from the initial Apuleian square to a variety of alter- native geometrical representations. In the light of this generalization, the famous problem of existential import is traced back to an ambiguous interpretation of assertoric (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21. Non-descriptive negation for normative sentences.Andrew Alwood - 2016 - Philosophical Quarterly 66 (262):1-25.
    Frege-Geach worries about embedding and composition have plagued metaethical theories like emotivism, prescriptivism and expressivism. The sharpened point of such criticism has come to focus on whether negation and inconsistency have to be understood in descriptivist terms. Because they reject descriptivism, these theories must offer a non-standard account of the meanings of ethical and normative sentences as well as related semantic facts, such as why certain sentences are inconsistent with each other. This paper fills out such a solution (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  22.  76
    Using non-sentences: An application of Relevance Theory.Robert J. Stainton - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (2):269-284.
    Michael Dummett has nicely expressed a rather widespread doctrine about the primacy of sentences. He writes: "you cannot DO anything with a word — cannot effect any conventional act by uttering it — save by uttering some sentence containing that word ...". In this paper we argue that this doctrine is mistaken: it is not only sentences, but also ordinary words and phrases which can be used in isolation. The argument involves two steps. First: we show — using (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  23.  16
    Using non-sentences: An application of Relevance Theory.Robert J. Stainton - 1994 - Pragmatics and Cognition 2 (2):269-284.
    Michael Dummett has nicely expressed a rather widespread doctrine about the primacy of sentences. He writes: "you cannot DO anything with a word — cannot effect any conventional act by uttering it — save by uttering some sentence containing that word...". In this paper we argue that this doctrine is mistaken: it is not only sentences, but also ordinary words and phrases which can be used in isolation. The argument involves two steps. First: we show — using Sperber (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24.  26
    Objects of Thought. [REVIEW]T. K. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (2):364-365.
    Prior apparently left a substantially completed manuscript dealing with the objects of thought when he died in 1969. Geach and Kenny have edited this material, supplementing it with both published and unpublished other writings, including an appendix on names in lieu of Prior's intended final chapter. The result is an interesting, often non-standard, discussion of many issues central to philosophical logic. There are two major concerns treated--what is it that we think?, and what is it that we think about?. These (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  5
    Non-Fregean Semantics for Sentences.Mieczysław Omyła - 1994 - In Jan Wolenski (ed.), Philosophical Logic in Poland. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 153--165.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. The sentence collection devs non habet initivm vel terminvm and its reworking, devs itaqve svmme atqve ineffabiliter bonvs.John C. Wei - 2011 - Mediaeval Studies 73:1-118.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  52
    "Non-accidental" and counterfactual sentences.Elizabeth Lane Beardsley - 1949 - Journal of Philosophy 46 (18):573-591.
  28.  11
    "Non-Accidental" and Counterfactual Sentences.Elizabeth Lane Beardsley - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (1):63-64.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  26
    Goedelian sentences: A non-numerical approach.J. Findlay - 1942 - Mind 51 (203):259-265.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  1
    Goedelian Sentences: A Non-Numerical Approach.J. Findlay - 1942 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):129-130.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Assertoric Semantics and the Computational Power of Self-Referential Truth.Stefan Wintein - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (2):317-345.
    There is no consensus as to whether a Liar sentence is meaningful or not. Still, a widespread conviction with respect to Liar sentences (and other ungrounded sentences) is that, whether or not they are meaningful, they are useless . The philosophical contribution of this paper is to put this conviction into question. Using the framework of assertoric semantics , which is a semantic valuation method for languages of self-referential truth that has been developed by the author, we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  65
    Future and non-future modal sentences.Tom Werner - 2006 - Natural Language Semantics 14 (3):235-255.
    In this paper, I argue for two principles to determine the temporal interpretation of modal sentences in English, given a theory in which modals are interpreted against double conversational backgrounds and an ontology in which possible worlds branch towards the future, The Disparity Principle requires that a modal sentence makes distinctions between worlds in the modal base. The Non- disparity Principle requires that a modal sentence does not make distinctions on the basis of facts settled at speech time. Selection (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  33.  20
    Second Language Experience Facilitates Sentence Recognition in Temporally-Modulated Noise for Non-native Listeners.Jingjing Guan, Xuetong Cao & Chang Liu - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Non-native listeners deal with adverse listening conditions in their daily life much harder than native listeners. However, previous work in our laboratories found that native Chinese listeners with native English exposure may improve the use of temporal fluctuations of noise for English vowel identification. The purpose of this study was to investigate whether Chinese listeners can generalize the use of temporal cues for the English sentence recognition in noise. Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers sentence recognition in quiet condition, stationary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  41
    Aliquid amplius audire desiderat: Desire in Abelard’s Theory of Incomplete and Non-Assertive Complete Sentences.Luisa Valente - 2015 - Vivarium 53 (2-4):221-248.
    _ Source: _Volume 53, Issue 2-4, pp 221 - 248 One of the peculiarities of Peter Abelard’s analysis of incomplete and non-assertive sentences is his use of the notion of desire: in both _Dialectica_ and _Glosses on Peri hermeneias_ the terms _desiderium_ and _desidero_ move to the foreground side by side with _optatio, expectatio, suspensio_ and the related verbs. Desire plays a structural role in Abelard’s descriptions of the compositional way in which the linguistic message is received, changing step (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  6
    Guilty Pleas, Sentence Reductions, and Non-punishment of the Innocent.Zachary Hoskins - 2023 - In Julian V. Roberts & Jesper Ryberg (eds.), Sentencing the Self-Convicted: The Ethics of Pleading Guilty. Bloomsbury. pp. 51-69.
    It is common practice in the United Kingdom, the United States, and other common law countries to reduce criminal sentences in response to guilty pleas. This chapter contends that this practice violates the commonly accepted prohibiton on punishment of the innocent. I first consider various interpretations of what this prohibition requires of a system of punishment. Then I contend that insofar as sentence reductions provide significant prudential incentives to innocent people to plead guilty, these reductions run afoul of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  27
    How to get a non-intensionalist, propositional, moderately realist truthconditional account of internal metafictional sentences.Alberto Voltolini - 2006 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 72 (1):179-199.
    In what follows, I will first try to show that both anti-realist and realist intensionalist truthconditional accounts of internal metafictional sentences (i.e., sentences of the form "in the story S, p") are unsatisfactory. Moreover, I will claim that this does not mean that propositional truthconditional accounts of those sentences are to be dispensed with; simply, one has to provide a non-intensionalist propositional truthconditional account of those sentences. Finally, I will show that this account is fully compatible (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  30
    Question-like and non-question-like imperative sentences.Pavel Materna - 1981 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (3):393 - 404.
    There is a distinctive kind of command, namely commands to answer specific questions. An imperative sentence denoting such a command has an interrogative sentence corresponding to it-a sentence denoting the respective question. LetImp, Int, andQ be such an imperative sentence, the interrogative sentence corresponding to it, and the question denoted by the interrogative sentence, respectively. LetQ be an empirical question, i. e., and ((ητ)ω)-object. LetP be an ((ητ)ω)-construction constructingQ. Then the analysis ofImp has the form (QL).LetQ be an analytical question, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. Reply to ‘attempts’: a non-davidsonian account of trying sentences.David-Hillel Ruben - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (12):3817-3830.
    In various of my writings, both in Philosophical Studies and elsewhere, I have argued that an account of trying sentences is available that does not require quantification over alleged attempts or tryings. In particular, adverbial modification in such sentences can be dealt with, without quantification over any such particulars. In ‘Attempts’, Jonathan D. Payton (Payton, 2021) has sought to dispute my claim. In this paper, I consider his claims and reply to them. I believe that my account withstands (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  25
    Ni chose, ni non-chose: The Sentences-Commentary of Himbertus de Garda, OFM.William O. Duba & Christopher D. Schabel - 2011 - Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale 53:149 - 232.
    Himbert of Garda was a little-known Franciscan theologian who studied at Paris around 1320 and probably served as Francis of Meyronnes’ secretary. His commentary on the Sentences provides precious insights on the development of Franciscan thought at Paris, connecting Francis of Meyronnes’ refined presentations of doctrine with raw academic debates between bachelors and masters in the Faculty of Theology. An appendix presents Himbert’s discussion of intrinsic degrees in Book I d.36, and both redactions of his treatment of the formal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  18
    The Pragmatics of Non-sentences.Robert J. Stainton - unknown
  41.  19
    Discussions: Goedelian sentences: A non-numerical approach.J. Findlay - 1942 - Mind 51 (203):259-265.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  36
    A Computational Evaluation of Sentence Processing Deficits in Aphasia.Umesh Patil, Sandra Hanne, Frank Burchert, Ria De Bleser & Shravan Vasishth - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (1):5-50.
    Individuals with agrammatic Broca's aphasia experience difficulty when processing reversible non-canonical sentences. Different accounts have been proposed to explain this phenomenon. The Trace Deletion account attributes this deficit to an impairment in syntactic representations, whereas others propose that the underlying structural representations are unimpaired, but sentence comprehension is affected by processing deficits, such as slow lexical activation, reduction in memory resources, slowed processing and/or intermittent deficiency, among others. We test the claims of two processing accounts, slowed processing and intermittent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. Principles of Non-Fregean Semantics for Sentences'.M. Omyla - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55:422-423.
  44.  29
    Davidson and non-trivial t-sentences.Michael J. White - 1976 - Erkenntnis 10 (1):87 - 97.
  45.  22
    Predicting Known Sentences: Neural Basis of Proverb Reading Using Non-parametric Statistical Testing and Mixed-Effects Models.Bruno Bianchi, Diego E. Shalom & Juan E. Kamienkowski - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.
  46. Mereology in Aristotle's Assertoric Syllogistic.Justin Vlasits - 2019 - History and Philosophy of Logic 40 (1):1-11.
    How does Aristotle think about sentences like ‘Every x is y’ in the Prior Analytics? A recently popular answer conceives of these sentences as expressing a mereological relationship between x and y: the sentence is true just in case x is, in some sense, a part of y. I argue that the motivations for this interpretation have so far not been compelling. I provide a new justification for the mereological interpretation. First, I prove a very general algebraic soundness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  23
    Findlay J.. Goedelian sentences: a non-numerical approach. Mind, n.s. vol. 51 , pp. 259–265.Alonzo Church - 1942 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):129-130.
  48.  12
    Deserved criminal sentences: an overview.Andrew Von Hirsch - 2017 - Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing.
    Introduction: the emergence of the proportionate sentence -- Sentence proportionality sketched briefly -- Why should the criminal sanction exist? -- Why punish proportionately? -- Ordinal and cardinal proportionality -- Seriousness, severity and the living-standard -- The role of previous convictions -- Proportionate non-custodial sanctions -- A "modified" desert model? -- The politics of the desert model -- Proportionate sentences for juveniles -- Appendix: the desert model's evolution : a brief chronology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  10
    What Machine Learning Can Tell Us About the Role of Language Dominance in the Diagnostic Accuracy of German LITMUS Non-word and Sentence Repetition Tasks.Lina Abed Ibrahim & István Fekete - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    This study investigates the performance of 21 monolingual and 56 bilingual children aged 5;6-9;0 on German-LITMUS-sentence-repetition (SRT; Hamann et al., 2013) and nonword-repetition-tasks (NWRT; Grimm et al., 2014), which were constructed according to the LITMUS-principles (Language Impairment Testing in Multilingual Settings; Armon-Lotem et al., 2015). Both tasks incorporate complex structures shown to be cross-linguistically challenging for children with Specific Language Impairment (SLI) and aim at minimizing bias against bilingual children while still being indicative of the presence of language impairment across (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Differences of Taste: An Investigation of Phenomenal and Non-Phenomenal Appearance Sentences.Rachel Etta Rudolph - 2022 - In Jeremy Wyatt, Dan Zeman & Julia Zakkou (eds.), Perspectives on Taste. Routledge. pp. 260-285.
    In theoretical work about the language of personal taste, the canonical example is the simple predicate of personal taste, 'tasty'. We can also express the same positive gustatory evaluation with the complex expression, 'taste good'. But there is a challenge for an analysis of 'taste good': While it can be used equivalently with 'tasty', it need not be (for instance, imagine it used by someone who can identify good wines by taste but doesn't enjoy them). This kind of two-faced behavior (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 993