Results for 'criterion of rightness'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  1
    The Criterion of Right Action in Kant’s Rechtslehre.Sven Arntzen - 2021 - In Camilla Serck-Hanssen & Beatrix Himmelmann (eds.), The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter. pp. 1689-1696.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  31
    Punishment and the utilitarian criterion of right and wrong.Walter E. Schaller - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):109-125.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  11
    Punishment and the Utilitarian Criterion of Right and Wrong.Walter E. Schaller - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):109-125.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On the Utilitarian Criterion of Right Action.Joel Thomas Tierno - 2014 - In G. John M. Abbarno (ed.), Inherent and Instrumental Values: Excursions in Value Inquiry. University Press of America.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  53
    A Realistic and Effective Constraint on the Resort to Force? Pre-commitment to Jus in Bello and Jus Post Bellum as Part of the Criterion of Right Intention.Annalisa Koeman - 2007 - Journal of Military Ethics 6 (3):198-220.
    This paper explores Brian Orend's contribution to the just war tradition, specifically his proposed jus post bellum criteria and his idea of pre-commitment to jus in bello and jus post bellum as part of an expanded jus ad bellum criterion of right intention. The latter is based on his interpretation of Kant's work: that as part of the original decision to begin a war, a state should commit itself to certain rules of conduct and appropriate war termination, and if (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6.  8
    James gs Wilson.Taxonomy of Rights Hohfeld’S. - 2007 - In Richard E. Ashcroft (ed.), Principles of Health Care Ethics. Wiley.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  47
    Prioritarianism: Ex Ante, Ex Post, or Factualist Criterion of Rightness?Nils Holtug - 2019 - Journal of Political Philosophy 27 (2):207-228.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  12
    “Benefit to the World” and “Heaven’s Intent”: The Prospective and Retrospective Aspects of the Mohist Criterion for Rightness.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - forthcoming - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy.
    “Benefit to the world” and “Heaven’s intent” are not, as is often assumed, separate criteria for action in Mozi’s 墨子 ethics; they are the same in extension but not intension. When Mozi speaks in terms of “Heaven’s intent,” it is to highlight the criterion’s retrospective orientation and its scope; taking a cue from Heaven’s reactions to past deeds, agents specify the scope of “the world” by reference to the past performance of persons regarding benefit to the world. This diverges (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Katharina Nieswandt, Concordia University. Authority & Interest in the Theory Of Right - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  28
    The Criterions of the Scientific Character of Jurisprudence in the Modern Legal Philosophy.Saulius Arlauskas - 2009 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 118 (4):247-264.
    In this article the paradoxical role of legal science in legal practice is discussed. On the one hand, legal scientists do not agree on the criterions of the scientific character of legal science. On the other hand, even in the legal cases that are especially complicated it is possible to arrive at theoretically unquestionable decisions. The author of the article concludes that legal practice is based on fundamental theoretical insights; however, in legal practice these insights are used more intuitively than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  16
    A local criterion of fairness in sport: Comparing the property advantages of Caster Semenya and Eero Mäntyranta with implications for the construction of categories in sport.Silvia Camporesi & Mika Hämäläinen - 2020 - Bioethics 35 (3):262-269.
    This paper aims to bring a novel approach to the discussion of unfair advantages in sport by looking for a local criterion of fairness instead of a universal criterion. A local criterion of fairness would not solve the general dispute over what counts as an unfair advantage, but it would be beneficial in evaluating specific cases and could guide further discussion about them. We seek a local criterion of fairness by comparing the specific property advantages of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Is Popper’s ‘Criterion of Demarcation’ outmoded?Sebastian Boţic - 2010 - Cultura 7 (1):41-53.
    This paper is concerned with the ′criterion of demarcation′ that Karl Popper put forward, while trying to show that it can be safely said that it is still standing. In doing so, I turn to two main objections to it: a Lakatos-Kuhn vision on the growth of science, and the famous Quine-Duhem thesis. The point that I hopefully made here is that the basic message of this prescriptive method is as respectful as ever, and, although not the subject of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  53
    Kant’s Categorical Imperative as a Criterion of the Rightness of Actions. [REVIEW]Gerhard Robbers - 1991 - Philosophy and History 24 (1-2):45-45.
  14.  63
    Why the Epistemic Objection Against Using Sentience as Criterion of Moral Status is Flawed.Leonard Dung - 2022 - Science and Engineering Ethics 28 (6):1-15.
    According to a common view, sentience is necessary and sufficient for moral status. In other words, whether a being has intrinsic moral relevance is determined by its capacity for conscious experience. The _epistemic objection_ derives from our profound uncertainty about sentience. According to this objection, we cannot use sentience as a _criterion_ to ascribe moral status in practice because we won’t know in the foreseeable future which animals and AI systems are sentient while ethical questions regarding the possession of moral (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  5
    Just Interpretations: Law Between Ethics and Politics.Michel Rosenfeld & Professor of Human Rights and Director Program on Global and Comparative Constitutional Theory Michel Rosenfeld - 1998 - Univ of California Press.
    "An important contribution to contemporary jurisprudential debate and to legal thought more generally, Just Interpretations is far ahead of currently available work."--Peter Goodrich, author of Oedipus Lex "I was struck repeatedly by the clarity of expression throughout the book. Rosenfeld's description and criticism of the recent work of leading thinkers distinguishes his work within the legal theory genre. Furthermore, his own theory is quite original and provocative."--Aviam Soifer, author of Law and the Company We Keep.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. Deeper problems for Noonan's probability argument against abortion: On a charitable reading of Noonan's conception criterion of humanity.Alan Clune - 2009 - Bioethics 25 (5):280-289.
    In ‘An Almost Absolute Value in History’ John T. Noonan criticizes several attempts to provide a criterion for when an entity deserves rights. These criteria, he argues are either arbitrary or lead to absurd consequence. Noonan proposes human conception as the criterion of rights, and justifies it by appeal to the sharp shift in probability, at conception, of becoming a being possessed of human reason. Conception, then, is when abortion becomes immoral.The article has an historical and a philosophical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Locke's Principle is an Applicable Criterion of Identity.Rafael De Clercq - 2011 - Noûs 47 (4):697-705.
    According to Locke’s Principle, material objects are identical if and only if they are of the same kind and once occupy the same place at the same time. There is disagreement about whether this principle is true, but what is seldom disputed is that, even if true, the principle fails to constitute an applicable criterion of identity. In this paper, I take issue with two arguments that have been offered in support of this claim by arguing (i) that we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Virtue Ethics and the Search for an Account of Right Action.Frans Svensson - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (3):255-271.
    Conceived of as a contender to other theories in substantive ethics, virtue ethics is often associated with, in essence, the following account or criterion of right action: VR: An action A is right for S in circumstances C if and only if a fully virtuous agent would characteristically do A in C. There are serious objections to VR, which take the form of counter-examples. They present us with different scenarios in which less than fully virtuous persons would be acting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  17
    What is the Verifiability Criterion a Criterion of?Stuart Brown - 1975 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 9:137-153.
    As my title implies, I think the verifiability criterion is indeed a criterion of something. I do not intend, therefore, merely to commemorate it. On the other hand I am not sure that those who put it forward in its more liberal forms as a criterion of ‘factual significance’ or ‘literal meaningfulness’ were right in what they identified as the consequence of a sentence's failing to satisfy it. What I want to argue for, in a somewhat reductionist (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    What is the Verifiability Criterion a Criterion of?Stuart Brown - 1975 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 9:137-153.
    As my title implies, I think the verifiability criterion is indeed a criterion of something. I do not intend, therefore, merely to commemorate it. On the other hand I am not sure that those who put it forward in its more liberal forms as a criterion of ‘factual significance’ or ‘literal meaningfulness’ were right in what they identified as the consequence of a sentence's failing to satisfy it. What I want to argue for, in a somewhat reductionist (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Hegel's Nonfoundationalism: A Phenomenological Account of the Structure of Philosophy of Right.Mark Tunick - 1994 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 11 (3):317 - 337.
    In the Phenomenology Hegel insists there are no presupposed standards of truth: standards are internal. "Consciousness provides its own criterion from within itself, so that the investigation becomes a comparison of consciousness with itself"(PhdG 84). We need only contemplate "the matter in hand as it is in and for itself"(PhdG 84). The Phenomenology is a characterisation of consciousness taking on increasingly adequate forms, testing its own internal standards against experience. The Philosophy of Right is a search for right, not, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  28
    Right Intention and the Ends of War.Duncan Purves & Ryan Jenkins - 2016 - Journal of Military Ethics 15 (1):18-35.
    ABSTRACTThe jus ad bellum criterion of right intention is a central guiding principle of just war theory. It asserts that a country’s resort to war is just only if that country resorts to war for the right reasons. However, there is significant confusion, and little consensus, about how to specify the CRI. We seek to clear up this confusion by evaluating several distinct ways of understanding the criterion. On one understanding, a state’s resort to war is just only (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23. A Defence of Moderate Communitarianism: A Place of Rights in African Moral-Political Thought.Motsamai Molefe - 2018 - Phronimon 18:181 - 203.
    This article attempts to defend Kwame Gyekye’s moderate communitarianism (MC) from the trenchant criticism that it is as defective as radical communitarianism (RC) since they both fail to take rights seriously. As part of my response, I raise two critical questions. Firstly, I question the supposition in the literature that there is such a thing as radical communitarianism. I point out that talk of radical communitarianism is tantamount to attacking a “straw-man.” Secondly, I question the efficacy of the criticism that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Can the subject-of-a-life criterion help grant rights to non-persons?Lisa Bortolotti - 2010 - In Matti Häyry (ed.), Arguments and Analysis in Bioethics. Rodopi.
    In this paper I compare different criteria for moral status, and assess Regan's notion of a "subject of a life".
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Diego Marconi.I. Glock & Twofold Criterion - 2011 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 30 (1):00-00.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  2
    Uniting What Right Permits with What Interest Prescribes: Rawls's Law of Peoples in Context.David Boucher - 2006-01-01 - In Rex Martin & David A. Reidy (eds.), Rawls's Law of Peoples. Blackwell. pp. 19–37.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Criteria of State Conduct Against Realism and Natural Law The Kantian Inheritance Rawls's Debt to Rousseau ‐ the Third Criterion Conclusion Notes.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  36
    J. S. Mill's Concept of Maturity as the Criterion in Determining Children's Eligibility for Rights.Ki Kim - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 24 (2):235-244.
    Ki Su Kim; J. S. Mill's Concept of Maturity as the Criterion in Determining Children's Eligibility for Rights, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 24, Is.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. On the moral status of social robots: considering the consciousness criterion.Kestutis Mosakas - 2021 - AI and Society 36 (2):429-443.
    While philosophers have been debating for decades on whether different entities—including severely disabled human beings, embryos, animals, objects of nature, and even works of art—can legitimately be considered as having moral status, this question has gained a new dimension in the wake of artificial intelligence (AI). One of the more imminent concerns in the context of AI is that of the moral rights and status of social robots, such as robotic caregivers and artificial companions, that are built to interact with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  29. An examination and defense of one argument concerning animal rights.Tom Regan - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):189 – 219.
    An argument is examined and defended for extending basic moral rights to animals which assumes that humans, including infants and the severely mentally enfeebled, have such rights. It is claimed that this argument proceeds on two fronts, one critical, where proposed criteria of right-possession are rejected, the other constructive, where proposed criteria are examined with a view to determining the most reasonable one. This form of argument is defended against the charge that it is self-defeating, various candidates for the title, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  30.  11
    Beyond Right Choices: The Art of Wise Decision Making.Mario Graziano - forthcoming - Topoi:1-12.
    During the course of life, it is common to make some decisions that prove to be correct. Some of these choices are made without a specific reason, but only out of habit or intuitively, while others are based on judgments and motivations. However, when we claim that a decision is “right”, what kind of judgment are we referring to? On the one hand, the term “right” (or “wrong”) often refers to abstract norms. Usually, truth and falsehood serve as criteria in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  10
    From Conflict to Confluence of Interest.Intellectual Property Rights - 2010 - In Thomas H. Murray & Josephine Johnston (eds.), Trust and Integrity in Biomedical Research: The Case of Financial Conflicts of Interest. Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  40
    The Right to Resist and the Right of Rebellion.Yulia Razmetaeva - 2014 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 21 (3):758-784.
    The right to resist and the right to rebel have again become relevant as legal problems. Their justifications traditionally derive from natural law, human rights, the principle of the lesser evil or of the social contract. Interpretation of the right to resist expresses the tendencies to the law of people, in particular, the right to self-determination, distinguishing national and international understanding, and underscores the special nature of such right. Also, two-level research of the right to resist should be distinguished research (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  40
    From Value to Rightness: Consequentialism, Action-Guidance, and the Perspective-Dependence of Moral Duties.Vuko Andric - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
    This book develops an original version of act-consequentialism. It argues that act-consequentialists should adopt a subjective criterion of rightness. The book develops new arguments which strongly suggest that, according to the best version of act-consequentialism, the rightness of actions depends on expected rather than actual value. Its findings go beyond the debate about consequentialism and touch on important debates in normative ethics and metaethics. The distinction between criterion of rightness and decision procedures addresses how, why, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Kant's innate right as a rational criterion for human rights.Otfried Höffe - 2010 - In Lara Denis (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.
  35. Index to Volume Fifty-Six.Wim De Reu & Right Words Seem Wrong - 2006 - Philosophy East and West 56 (4):709-714.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Index to Volume Fifty-SixArticlesBernier, Bernard, National Communion: Watsuji Tetsurō's Conception of Ethics, Power, and the Japanese Imperial State, 1 : 84-105Between Principle and Situation: Contrasting Styles in the Japanese and Korean Traditions of Moral Culture, Chai-sik Chung, 2 : 253-280Buxton, Nicholas, The Crow and the Coconut: Accident, Coincidence, and Causation in the Yogavāiṣṭha, 3 : 392-408Chan, Sin Yee, The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect), Sin Yee Chan, 2 : (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Raymond plant.Welfare Rights - 1988 - In J. Donald Moon (ed.), Responsibility, Rights, and Welfare: The Theory of the Welfare State. Westview Press. pp. 55.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The nature and value of the.Moral Right To Privacy - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):329.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. “Rule of Law and International Human Rights".Vincent Samar - 2022 - Cardozo International and Comparative Law Review 5:569-25.
    This article reviews the field of international human rights with particular attention to the way that the International Court of Justice, the International Criminal Court, the Human Rights Committee, and local domestic courts operate to resolve human rights cases. It first notes what internationally recognized human rights there are and the sources that give rise to them. It then explains how relativism enters human rights decision-making, especially at the domestic court level, in part because a common grounding for the human (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  8
    Right and good: The contradiction of morality: Journal of philosophical studies.W. G. de Burgh - 1930 - Philosophy 5 (20):582-593.
    We were led, at the close of the last paper, to the conclusion that the moral judgment lays claim to a knowledge of what is unknowable. It is not merely that our volition is imperfect, that the act of necessity falls short of what we know to be right. This seems bad enough; but the plight in which we actually find ourselves is even worse. The paradox is that we never know, and never can know, in any particular situation, what (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  71
    The Right Side of History and Higher-Order Evidence.Adam Green - 2021 - Episteme 18 (1):1-15.
    Appeals to “being on the right side of history” or accusations of being on the wrong side of history are increasingly common on social media, in the media proper, and in the rhetoric of politics. One might well wonder, though, what the value is of invoking history in this manner. Is declaring who is on what side of history merely dramatic shorthand for one's being right and one's opponents wrong? Or is there something more to it than that? In this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. The Right Wrong‐Makers.Richard Yetter Chappell - 2020 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103 (2):426-440.
    Right- and wrong-making features ("moral grounds") are widely believed to play important normative roles, e.g. in morally apt or virtuous motivation. This paper argues that moral grounds have been systematically misidentified. Canonical statements of our moral theories tend to summarize, rather than directly state, the full range of moral grounds posited by the theory. Further work is required to "unpack" a theory's criterion of rightness and identify the features that are of ground-level moral significance. As a result, it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  7
    Right and Good: the Contradiction of Morality.W. G. de Burgh - 1930 - Philosophy 5 (20):582-.
    We were led, at the close of the last paper, to the conclusion that the moral judgment lays claim to a knowledge of what is unknowable. It is not merely that our volition is imperfect, that the act of necessity falls short of what we know to be right. This seems bad enough; but the plight in which we actually find ourselves is even worse. The paradox is that we never know, and never can know, in any particular situation, what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  2
    An Inquiry on the Commensurability between the Propriety[禮] as Criterion System of Confucian Philosophy and Human Rights, Privacy.Yeonseok Eom - 2011 - THE JOURNAL OF ASIAN PHILOSOPHY IN KOREA 35:1-31.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  13
    J. S. mill's concept of maturity as the criterion in determining children's eligibility for rights.K. I. M. SU - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 24 (2):235–244.
  45.  40
    Getting it Right: the teaching of philosophical health care ethics.J. Webb & C. Warwick - 1999 - Nursing Ethics 6 (2):150-156.
    This article seeks to show one way in which moral philosophy, considered by the authors to be essential to the nursing and midwifery curricula, can be presented to achieve an optimal learning experience for nurses and midwives. It demonstrates that what might be considered a standard approach, that is, one that begins with ethical principles concerned with rights and duties and then often follows a linear pattern of teaching, may be in danger of promoting a focus on standardized outcomes. Such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  4
    The right measure of guilt: Moral reasoning, transgression and the social construction of moral meanings.Cristian Tileagă - 2012 - Discourse and Communication 6 (2):203-222.
    Using a discursive and ethnomethodological analytic framework, this article explores the social construction of moral transgression and moral meanings in the context of coming to terms with the recent communist past in Eastern Europe. This article illustrates some significant aspects of everyday uses of morality and the socio-communicative organization of public judgements on moral transgression. The article considers the range of public reactions and commentaries to a public confession of having been an informer for the former Romanian secret police. Moral (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  14
    Explanatory Report to the Additional Protocol to the Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine, concerning Biomedical Research.Directorate General I. Council of Europe - 2005 - Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft Und Ethik 10 (1):403-431.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  17
    The Use of Works for Parody and Caricature. Legal Criterions.Jūratė Usonienė - 2009 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 118 (4):147-166.
    The article deals with the exception to copyright for the purposes of parody and caricature. This exception is one of the tools ensuring the balance between the authors’ interest to have the monopoly on the use of their works and the right of the members of the society to the freedom of expression. Another aim of parody exception is the promotion of creativity by the permission of the transformative use of copyrighted works. Three main aspects of this issue are discussed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  74
    Found Guilty by Association: In Defence of the Quinean Criterion.Karl Egerton - 2016 - Ratio 31 (1):37-56.
    Much recent work in metaontology challenges the so-called ‘Quinean tradition’ in metaphysics. Especially prominently, Amie Thomasson argues for a highly permissive ontology over ontologies which eliminate many entities. I am concerned with disputing not her ontological claim, but the methodology behind her rejection of eliminativism – I focus on ordinary objects. Thomasson thinks that by endorsing the Quinean criterion of ontological commitment eliminativism goes wrong; a theory eschewing quantification over a kind may nonetheless be committed to its existence. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000