Results for 'conscientious refusal'

994 found
Order:
  1.  9
    Conscientious refusal or conscientious provision: We can't have both.Ryan Kulesa & Alberto Giubilini - forthcoming - Bioethics.
    Some authors argue that it is permissible for clinicians to conscientiously provide abortion services because clinicians are already allowed to conscientiously refuse to provide certain services. Call this the symmetry thesis. We argue that on either of the two main understandings of the aim of the medical profession—what we will call “pathocentric” and “interest‐centric” views—conscientious refusal and conscientious provision are mutually exclusive. On pathocentric views, refusing to provide a service that takes away from a patient's health is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Conscientious Refusals and Reason‐Giving.Jason Marsh - 2013 - Bioethics 28 (6):313-319.
    Some philosophers have argued for what I call the reason-giving requirement for conscientious refusal in reproductive healthcare. According to this requirement, healthcare practitioners who conscientiously object to administering standard forms of treatment must have arguments to back up their conscience, arguments that are purely public in character. I argue that such a requirement, though attractive in some ways, faces an overlooked epistemic problem: it is either too easy or too difficult to satisfy in standard cases. I close by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  3. Conscientious Refusal and Access to Abortion and Contraception.Chloe Fitzgerald & Carolyn McLeod - 2015 - In John Arras, Elizabeth Fenton & Rebecca Kukla (eds.), Routledge Companion to Bioethics. New York: Routledge. pp. 343-356.
    An overview of the philosophical and bioethics literature on conscientious refusals by health care professionals to provide abortion and contraceptive services.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Conscientious refusal by physicians and pharmacists: Who is obligated to do what, and why?Dan W. Brock - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (3):187-200.
    Some medical services have long generated deep moral controversy within the medical profession as well as in broader society and have led to conscientious refusals by some physicians to provide those services to their patients. More recently, pharmacists in a number of states have refused on grounds of conscience to fill legal prescriptions for their customers. This paper assesses these controversies. First, I offer a brief account of the basis and limits of the claim to be free to act (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  5.  55
    Provider Conscientious Refusal of Abortion, Obstetrical Emergencies, and Criminal Homicide Law.Lawrence Nelson - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (7):43-50.
    Catholic doctrine’s strict prohibition on abortion can lead clinicians or institutions to conscientiously refuse to provide abortion, although a legal duty to provide abortion would apply to anyone who refused. Conscientious refusals by clinicians to end a pregnancy can constitute murder or reckless homicide under American law if a woman dies as a result of such a refusal. Such refusals are not immunized from criminal liability by the constitutional right to the free exercise of religion or by statutes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6. Conscientious Refusal and Health Professionals: Does Religion Make a Difference?Daniel Weinstock - 2013 - Bioethics 28 (1):8-15.
    Freedom of Conscience and Freedom of Religion should be taken to protect two distinct sets of moral considerations. The former protects the ability of the agent to reflect critically upon the moral and political issues that arise in her society generally, and in her professional life more specifically. The latter protects the individual's ability to achieve secure membership in a set of practices and rituals that have as a moral function to inscribe her life in a temporally extended narrative. Once (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  7.  88
    Conscientious refusal and a doctors's right to quit.John K. Davis - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (1):75 – 91.
    Patients sometimes request procedures their doctors find morally objectionable. Do doctors have a right of conscientious refusal? I argue that conscientious refusal is justified only if the doctor's refusal does not make the patient worse off than she would have been had she gone to another doctor in the first place. From this approach I derive conclusions about the duty to refer and facilitate transfer, whether doctors may provide 'moral counseling,' whether doctors are obligated to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8.  9
    Conscientious refusal in healthcare: the Swedish solution.Christian Munthe - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):257-259.
    The Swedish solution to the legal handling of professional conscientious refusal in healthcare is described. No legal right to conscientious refusal for any profession or class of professional tasks exists in Sweden, regardless of the religious or moral background of the objection. The background of this can be found in strong convictions about the importance of public service provision and related civic duties, and ideals about rule of law, equality and non-discrimination. Employee's requests to change work (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9. Conscientious Refusals without Conscience.Michael W. Hickson - 2010 - Philo 13 (2):167-184.
    In this paper I uncover and critically analyze a methodological assumption in the literature on conscientious refusals in health care. The assumption is what I call the “Priority of Conscience Principle,” which says the following: to determine the moral status of any act of conscientious refusal, it is first necessary to determine the nature and value of conscience. I argue that it is not always necessary to discuss conscience in the debate on conscientious refusals, and that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  8
    Ought Conscientious Refusals to Implement Reverse Triage Decisions be Accommodated?Nathan Emmerich - 2020 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 17 (4):783-787.
    Although one can argue that they do not represent a radical departure from existing practices, protocols for reverse triage certainly step beyond what is ordinarily done in medicine and healthcare. Nevertheless, there seems to be some degree of moral concern regarding the ethical legitimacy of practicing reverse triage in the context of a pandemic. Such concern can be taken as a reflection of the moral antipathy some exhibit towards current practices of withdrawing treatment—that is, when withdrawal of treatment is arguably (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  9
    Democratizing Conscientious Refusal in Healthcare.David C. Scott - forthcoming - HEC Forum:1-31.
    Settling the debate over conscientious refusal (CR) in liberal democracies requires us to develop a conception of the healthcare provider’s moral role. Because CR claims and resulting policy changes take place in specific sociopolitical contexts with unique histories and diverse polities, the _method_ we use for deriving the healthcare norms should itself be a democratic, context-dependent inquiry. To this end, I begin by describing some prerequisites—which I call _publicity conditions_—for any democratic account of healthcare norms that conflict or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  29
    Futility, Conscientious Refusal, and Who Gets to Decide.J. K. Davis - 2008 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 33 (4):356-373.
    Most discussions of medical futility try to answer the Futility Question: when is a medical procedure futile? No answer enjoys universal support. Some futility policies say that the health care provider will answer this question when the provider and patient cannot agree. This raises the Decision Question: who has the moral authority to decide what to do in cases where futility is disputed? I look for a procedural answer to this question, an answer that does not turn on whether a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Conscientious Refusal of Abortion in Emergency Life-Threatening Circumstances and Contested Judgments of Conscience.Wojciech Ciszewski & Tomasz Żuradzki - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (7):62-64.
    Lawrence Nelson (2018) criticizes conscientious objection (CO) to abortion statutes as far as they permit health care providers to escape criminal liability for what would otherwise be the legally wrongful taking of a pregnant woman’s life by refusing treatment (i.e. abortion). His key argument refers to the U.S. Supreme Court judgment (Roe v. Wade 1973) that does not treat the unborn as constitutional persons under the Fourteenth Amendment. Therefore, Nelson claims that within the U.S. legal system any vital interests (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Wrongness, Responsibility, and Conscientious Refusals in Health Care.Alida Liberman - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (7):495-504.
    In this article, I address what kinds of claims are of the right kind to ground conscientious refusals. Specifically, I investigate what conceptions of moral responsibility and moral wrongness can be permissibly presumed by conscientious objectors. I argue that we must permit HCPs to come to their own subjective conclusions about what they take to be morally wrong and what they take themselves to be morally responsible for. However, these subjective assessments of wrongness and responsibility must be constrained (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15.  6
    Conscientious Refusals in Pharmacy Practice.Zuzana Deans - 2017 - In Dien Ho (ed.), Philosophical Issues in Pharmaceutics: Development, Dispensing, and Use. Springer.
    It is widely accepted in the pharmacy profession that pharmacists have the right to conscientiously refuse to participate in certain practices on grounds of conscience. This is allowed in recognition of differences in moral and religious views and out of respect for moral integrity. However, the “conscience clause” does not necessarily sit easily in a professional code of ethics owing to the potential tensions between a professional’s personal moral integrity and her professional obligations. At the heart of these tensions are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  43
    Protecting reasonable conscientious refusals in health care.Jason T. Eberl - 2019 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 40 (6):565-581.
    Recently, debate over whether health care providers should have a protected right to conscientiously refuse to offer legal health care services—such as abortion, elective sterilization, aid in dying, or treatments for transgender patients—has grown exponentially. I advance a modified compromise view that bases respect for claims of conscientious refusal to provide specific health care services on a publicly defensible rationale. This view requires health care providers who refuse such services to disclose their availability by other providers, as well (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17.  60
    Conscientious refusals to refer: findings from a national physician survey.M. P. Combs, R. M. Antiel, J. C. Tilburt, P. S. Mueller & F. A. Curlin - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (7):397-401.
    Background Regarding controversial medical services, many have argued that if physicians cannot in good conscience provide a legal medical intervention for which a patient is a candidate, they should refer the requesting patient to an accommodating provider. This study examines what US physicians think a doctor is obligated to do when the doctor thinks it would be immoral to provide a referral. Method The authors conducted a cross-sectional survey of a random sample of 2000 US physicians from all specialties. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  61
    Conscientious Refusals by Hospitals and Emergency Contraception.Mark R. Wicclair - 2011 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 20 (1):130-138.
    Hospitals sometimes refuse to provide goods and services or honor patients’ decisions to forgo life-sustaining treatment for reasons that appear to resemble appeals to conscience. For example, based on the Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health Care Services , Catholic hospitals have refused to forgo medically provided nutrition and hydration , and Catholic hospitals have refused to provide emergency contraception and perform abortions or sterilization procedures. I consider whether it is justified to refuse to offer EC to victims of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  14
    Conscientious refusals to provide reproductive health care: Carolyn McLeod: Conscience in reproductive health care: prioritizing patient interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020, 224 pp, £40.00 HB.Carolyn Mason - 2020 - Metascience 30 (1):131-134.
  20.  16
    Provider Conscientious Refusal, Medical Malpractice, and the Right to Civil Recourse.Jane A. Hartsock - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (7):66-68.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  63
    Conscientious Refusal in Schools of Social Work: Rights, Remedies, and Responsibilities.Jay Sweifach - 2012 - Teaching Ethics 13 (1):37-53.
  22.  88
    Dispensing with liberty: Conscientious refusal and the "morning-after pill".Elizabeth Fenton & Loren Lomasky - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (6):579 – 592.
    Citing grounds of conscience, pharmacists are increasingly refusing to fill prescriptions for emergency contraception, or the "morning-after pill." Whether correctly or not, these pharmacists believe that emergency contraception either constitutes the destruction of post-conception human life, or poses a significant risk of such destruction. We argue that the liberty of conscientious refusal grounds a strong moral claim, one that cannot be defeated solely by consideration of the interests of those seeking medication. We examine, and find lacking, five arguments (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23.  47
    Obstetrician-gynaecologists' opinions about conscientious refusal of a request for abortion: results from a national vignette experiment.K. A. Rasinski, J. D. Yoon, Y. G. Kalad & F. A. Curlin - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (12):711-714.
    Background and objectives Conscientious refusal of abortion has been discussed widely by medical ethicists but little information on practitioners' opinions exists. The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) issued recommendations about conscientious refusal. We used a vignette experiment to examine obstetrician-gynecologists' (OB/GYN) support for the recommendations. Design A national survey of OB/GYN physicians contained a vignette experiment in which an OB/GYN doctor refused a requested elective abortion. The vignette varied two issues recently addressed by the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  9
    Reformed Theology and Conscientious Refusal of Medical Treatment.Ruth Groenhout - 2020 - Christian Bioethics 26 (1):56-80.
    Traditionally, healthcare workers have had the right to refuse to participate in abortions or physician-assisted suicide, but more recently there has been a movement in white Evangelical circles to expand these rights to include the refusal of any treatment at all to same-sex couples or their children, transgender individuals, or others who offend the provider’s moral sensibilities. Religious freedom of conscience exists in an uneasy tension with laws protecting equal rights in a liberal polity, and it is a particularly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  9
    What Makes Conscientious Refusals Concerning Abortion Different.Jason T. Eberl - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (8):62-64.
    Fritz argues that there is an “unjustified asymmetry” in legislation that allows physicians and health care institutions to refuse to provide elective abortions and other morally contested l...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  25
    Comparing policies on conscientious refusals: A feminist perspective.Patrick Clipsham - 2013 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 6 (1):159-165.
    Many professional associations have policies explaining when it is or is not acceptable for health-care professionals to refuse to participate in the administration of certain interventions on grounds of conscience. In both Canada and the United States, nursing associations tend to have much more detailed, permissive policies than medical associations. There are reasons to think that this distinction is not justifiable, and I argue that some specific North American medical associations should endorse policies regarding conscientious refusals that are modeled (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  49
    Comparing Policies on Conscientious Refusals: A Feminist Perspective.Patrick Clipsham - 2013 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 6 (1):159-165.
    Given numerous ethical concerns with conscientious refusals by healthcare professionals, there is a need for detailed policies outlining the permissibility of conscientious refusals. I suggest that the Canadian Medical Association (CMA) and American Medical Association (AMA) policies are inadequate and that these associations have good reason to endorse more restrictive, more detailed policies regarding conscientious refusals, much like those endorsed by nursing associations.Health-care professionals sometimes refuse to participate in the administration of legal interventions because the administration of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  15
    Should professional associations sanction conscientious refusals?Inmaculada de Melo-Martin - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):23 – 24.
  29.  20
    Objection or Obstacle: Applying Amartya Sen’s Capability Approach to the Conscientious Refusal of Emergency Contraception.Claire M. Moore - 2022 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 15 (2):40-50.
    The conscientious refusal to dispense emergency contraception is legally protected in fourteen states. While the ethical dimensions of these objections have been explored within moral and feminist philosophy, conscientious refusal to the over-the-counter sale of EC has not been significantly studied through an egalitarian lens, especially with attention to the existing reproductive healthcare landscape in which these refusals occur. This article argues, through Amartya Sen’s capability approach, that conscientious refusal to EC creates a burdensome (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  23
    Genetic Testing, Conscientious Refusal of Medical Treatment to Children, and Organ Donation: An Introduction.A. E. Hinkley - 2010 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (2):81-85.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  11
    Legal Briefing: Conscience Clauses and Conscientious Refusal.Thaddeus Mason Pope - 2010 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 21 (2):163-180.
    This issue’s “Legal Briefing” column covers legal developments pertaining to conscience clauses and conscientious refusal. Not only has this topic been the subject of recent articles in this journal, but it has also been the subject of numerous public and professional discussions. Over the past several months, conscientious refusal disputes have had an unusually high profile not only in courthouses, but also in legislative and regulatory halls across the United States.Healthcare providers’ own moral beliefs have been (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  39
    A Thomistic Argument for Respecting Conscientious Refusals.Michał Głowala - 2016 - Diametros 47:19-34.
    The paper presents an argument for respecting conscientious refusals based on the Thomistic account of conscience; the argument does not employ the notion of right. The main idea is that acting against one’s conscience necessarily makes the action objectively wrong and performed in bad faith, and expecting someone to act against his or her conscience is incompatible with requiring him or her to act in good faith. In light of this idea I also examine the issue of obligations imposed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  32
    Let Conscience Be Their Guide? Conscientious Refusals in Health Care.Carolyn McLeod & Jocelyn Downie - 2013 - Bioethics 28 (1):ii-iv.
    The introduction to a special issue of the journal Bioethics that we edited.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  28
    The Dictates of Conscience: Can They Justify Conscientious Refusals in Healthcare Contexts?Mary Carman - 2019 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 28 (2):303-315.
    In a recent article in this journal, Steve Clarke (2017) identifies two different bases for conscience-based refusals in healthcare: (1) all-things-considered moral judgments, and (2) the dictates of conscience. He argues that these two bases have distinct roles in justifying conscientious objection. However, accepting that there are these two bases, I argue that both are not able to justify conscientious objection. In particular, I argue that the second basis of the dictates of conscience cannot justify conscience-based refusal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  30
    Pregnancy Is Not a Disease: Conscientious Refusal and the Argument from Concepts.Daniel Brudney - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (5):43-49.
    A new kind of argument has been proposed to explain why health-care workers can sometimes refuse to offer a service or treatment. But this new kind of argument must also be evaluated and invoked differently.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  35
    Toleration of Moral Diversity and the Conscientious Refusal by Physicians to Withdraw Life-Sustaining Treatment.S. Wear, S. Lagaipa & G. Logue - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (2):147-159.
    The removal of life-sustaining treatment often brings physicians into conflict with patients. Because of their moral beliefs physicians often respond slowly to the request of patients or their families. People in bioethics have been quick to recommend that in cases of conflict the physician should simply sign off the case and “step aside”. This is not easily done psychologically or morally. Such a resolution also masks a number of more subtle, quite trouble some problems that conflict with the commitment to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  24
    Moral Injury, Jus Ad Bellum, and Conscientious Refusal.Fiala Andrew - 2017 - Essays in Philosophy 18 (2):281-294.
    Although jus in bello violations create transgressive acts that cause moral injury, the primary consideration in thinking about moral injury should be jus ad bellum. If one is fighting in an ad bellum just war, then transgressive acts can be rationalized in a way that allows for consolation. But for morally sensitive combatants engaged in an ad bellum unjust war, consolation is more difficult since there is no way to justify or rationalize morally problematic deeds committed in defense of an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  33
    The Legal Ethical Backbone of Conscientious Refusal.Christian Munthe & Morten Ebbe Juul Nielsen - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1):59-68.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  17
    McLeod’s Conscience in Reproductive Health Care: Fiduciary Duties Beyond Reproductive Care, the Role of the Pharmacist, and the Harms and Wrongs of Conscientious Refusals.Javiera Perez Gomez - 2022 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 15 (2):137-143.
    McLeod's Conscience in Reproductive Health Care offers a number of valuable contributions to the literature, both within and beyond reproductive care. In this commentary, I begin by discussing two potential applications of her argument that healthcare professionals—specifically, those "who are charged with gatekeeping access to healthcare services" —have a fiduciary duty of loyalty to prioritize the interests of their patients over their own. Then, I turn to a couple of concerns one might raise about extending this fiduciary duty to pharmacists (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  13
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on ‘‘Provider Conscientious Refusal of Abortion, Obstetrical Emergencies, and Criminal Homicide Law’’.Lawrence Nelson - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (9):9-10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  17
    US primary care physicians’ opinions about conscientious refusal: a national vignette experiment.Simon G. Brauer, John D. Yoon & Farr A. Curlin - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):80-84.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Conscientious Objection in Healthcare: The Requirement of Justification, the Moral Threshold, and Military Refusals.Tomasz Żuradzki - 2023 - Journal of Religious Ethics 52 (1):133-155.
    A dogma accepted in many ethical, religious, and legal frameworks is that the reasons behind conscientious objection (CO) in healthcare cannot be evaluated or judged by any institution because conscience is individual and autonomous. This paper shows that this background view is mistaken: the requirement to reveal and explain the reasons for conscientious objection in healthcare is ethically justified and legally desirable. Referring to real healthcare cases and legal regulations, this paper argues that these reasons should be evaluated (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  28
    When conscientious objection runs amok: A physician refusing HIV preventative to a bisexual patient.Abram Brummett - 2021 - Clinical Ethics 16 (2):151-154.
    This paper reports of a case where a physician conscientiously objected to prescribing PrEP to a bisexual patient so as not to “enable immoral sexual behavior.” The case represents an instance of conscience creep, a phenomenon whereby clinicians invoke conscientious objection in sometimes objectionable ways that extend beyond the traditional contexts of abortion, sterilization, or physician aid in dying. This essay uses a reasonability view of conscientious objection to argue that the above case represents a discriminatory instance of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  12
    Refusing to Kill: Selective Conscientious Objection and Professional Military Duties.Andreas Yiannaros - 2018 - Journal of Military Ethics 17 (2-3):108-121.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  20
    Conscientious Objection and Clinical Judgement: The Right to Refuse to Harm.Toni C. Saad - 2019 - The New Bioethics 25 (3):248-261.
    This paper argues that healthcare aims at the good of health, that this pursuit of the good necessitates conscience, and that conscience is required in every practical judgement, including clinical...
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46. A defense of conscientious objection: Why health is integral to the permissibility of medical refusals.Ryan Kulesa - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (1):54-62.
    Bioethics, Volume 36, Issue 1, Page 54-62, January 2022.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. No conscientious objection without normative justification: Against conscientious objection in medicine.Benjamin Zolf - 2018 - Bioethics 33 (1):146-153.
    Most proponents of conscientious objection accommodation in medicine acknowledge that not all conscientious beliefs can justify refusing service to a patient. Accordingly, they admit that constraints must be placed on the practice of conscientious objection. I argue that one such constraint must be an assessment of the reasonability of the conscientious claim in question, and that this requires normative justification of the claim. Some advocates of conscientious object protest that, since conscientious claims are a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  62
    Conscientious objections in pharmacy practice in great Britain.Zuzana Deans - 2011 - Bioethics 27 (1):48-57.
    Pharmacists who refuse to provide certain services or treatment for reasons of conscience have been criticized for failing to fulfil their professional obligations. Currently, individual pharmacists in Great Britain can withhold services or treatment for moral or religious reasons, provided they refer the patient to an alternative source. The most high-profile cases have concerned the refusal to supply emergency hormonal contraception, which will serve as an example in this article.I propose that the pharmacy profession's policy on conscientious objections (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Conscientious objection and emergency contraception.Robert F. Card - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6):8 – 14.
    This article argues that practitioners have a professional ethical obligation to dispense emergency contraception, even given conscientious objection to this treatment. This recent controversy affects all medical professionals, including physicians as well as pharmacists. This article begins by analyzing the option of referring the patient to another willing provider. Objecting professionals may conscientiously refuse because they consider emergency contraception to be equivalent to abortion or because they believe contraception itself is immoral. This article critically evaluates these reasons and concludes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  50. Conscientious Objection in Health Care: An Ethical Analysis.Mark R. Wicclair - 2011 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Historically associated with military service, conscientious objection has become a significant phenomenon in health care. Mark Wicclair offers a comprehensive ethical analysis of conscientious objection in three representative health care professions: medicine, nursing and pharmacy. He critically examines two extreme positions: the 'incompatibility thesis', that it is contrary to the professional obligations of practitioners to refuse provision of any service within the scope of their professional competence; and 'conscience absolutism', that they should be exempted from performing any action (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
1 — 50 / 994