Results for 'coercive offers'

974 found
Order:
  1.  25
    Coercive offers and research participation: a comment on Wertheimer and Miller.J. McMillan - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (7):383-384.
    Concepts such as ‘coercion’ and ‘inducement’ are often used within bioethics without much reflection upon what they mean. This is particularly so in research ethics where they are assumed to imply that payment for research participation is unethical. Wertheimer and Miller advance our thinking about these concepts and research ethics in a significant way, specifically by questioning the possibility of genuine offers ever being coercive. This commentary argues that they are right to question this assumption, however, more needs (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  60
    Coercive offers.Robert Stevens - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (1):83 – 95.
  3.  15
    On Coercive Offers.Cansu Canca - 2017 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (2):149-162.
    A prominent argument against a market in kidneys is the Argument from Coercion. AfC claims that a market would violate the autonomy of typical suppliers by presenting them with coercive offers. Engaging with Cherry’s response to AfC, this paper argues that while a consistent AfC could be constructed, it would still fail to justify a prohibition of a market. AfC, as fully formulated, only holds if we assume that the state is obligated to provide for the basic needs (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  16
    On Coercive Offers.Cansu Canca - 2017 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (2):149-162.
    A prominent argument against a market in kidneys is the Argument from Coercion. AfC claims that a market would violate the autonomy of typical suppliers by presenting them with coercive offers. Engaging with Cherry’s response to AfC, this paper argues that while a consistent AfC could be constructed, it would still fail to justify a prohibition of a market. AfC, as fully formulated, only holds if we assume that the state is obligated to provide for the basic needs (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Coercive Offers Without Coercion as Subjection.William R. Smith & Benjamin Rossi - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (9):64-66.
    Volume 19, Issue 9, September 2019, Page 64-66.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Coercive Offers: A Study of the Nature and Ethics of Coercion.J. Gregory Dees - 1986 - Dissertation, The Johns Hopkins University
    In 1969 Robert Nozick published the first extensive philosophical analysis of the concept of coercion. His analysis has since generated a great deal of controversy. This dissertation is an attempt to resolve much of the controversy. It begins with a detailed review of recent work on coercion. Based on the lessons learned in this review, a new theory of coercion and its ethics is proposed. The theory identifies the essential features of a coerced choice and distinguishes several senses in which (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Coercive Offers and Public Benefits.Michael D. Bayles - 1974 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 55 (2):139.
  8.  75
    There are (STILL) no coercive offers.A. Wertheimer & F. G. Miller - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):592-593.
    John McMillan's article raises numerous important points about the ethics of surgical castration of sex offenders.1 In this commentary, we focus solely on and argue against the claim that the offer of release from detention conditional upon surgical castration is a coercive offer that compromises the validity of the offender's consent. We take no view on the question as to whether castration for sex offenders is ethically permissible. But, we reject the claim that it is ethically permissible only if (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  19
    Exploitative, irresistible, and coercive offers: why research participants should be paid well or not at all.Sara Belfrage - 2016 - Journal of Global Ethics 12 (1):69-86.
    ABSTRACTThis paper begins with the assumption that it is morally problematic when people in need are offered money in exchange for research participation if the amount offered is unfair. Such offers are called ‘coercive’, and the degree of coerciveness is determined by the offer's potential to cause exploitation and its irresistibility. Depending on what view we take on the possibility to compensate for the sacrifices made by research participants, a wish to avoid ‘coercive offers’ leads to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  35
    Surgical castration, coercive offers and coercive effects: it is still not about consent.John McMillan - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):596-596.
    In my reply to Wertheimer and Miller's paper on coercive offers and payment for research participation1 I claim that ‘… it's not unreasonable to suppose that there is another normative aspect to these cases, over and above the voluntariness of consent. While the parents of children at Willowbrook and the millionaire's mistress might have given consent that was voluntary and informed, they are still wronged by taking up this offer…’2 Furthermore, nowhere in my paper on surgical castration do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  47
    Welcome Threats and Coercive Offers.Daniel Lyons - 1975 - Philosophy 50 (194):425 - 436.
    In American legal journals over the last decade there were hundreds of pages of articles worrying over threats to justice and freedom arising from the power to withhold benefits. Government officials have tremendous discretion to offer or withhold foreign aid, ration-books, government contracts and jobs, welfare subsidies, public housing, tariff protection, academic grants, alien resident status, paroles, or exemption from conscription or combat, from arrest or prosecution or imprisonment. Right-wing economists have worried about welfare-state emphasis on administrative discretion rather than (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  12.  29
    The Last Word on Coercive Offers …(?).Daniel Lyons - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:393-414.
    A dozen philosophers have recently groped for a formula to pick out coercive offers: when P proposes to give a benefit or withhold a harm for Q’s compliance, when does p’s proposal count as coercive? Five formulae are analyzed here. One account is completely “moralized,” claiming that we can’t pick out coercive offers without first settling questions of rights. Two accounts are completely “non-moral,” using as criterion a baseline of “What would in fact have happened” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  29
    “Undue Inducement' as Coercive Offers.Joan McGregor - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (5):24 – 25.
  14.  6
    The Last Word on Coercive Offers …(?).Daniel Lyons - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:393-414.
    A dozen philosophers have recently groped for a formula to pick out coercive offers: when P proposes to give a benefit or withhold a harm for Q’s compliance, when does p’s proposal count as coercive? Five formulae are analyzed here. One account is completely “moralized,” claiming that we can’t pick out coercive offers without first settling questions of rights. Two accounts are completely “non-moral,” using as criterion a baseline of “What would in fact have happened” (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  53
    The Sexual Harassment Coercive Offer.James Rocha - 2010 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (2):203-216.
    There is disagreement in the coercion literature over whether an offer, which necessarily lacks a threat, could be coercive, which tends to imply at least some affinity with coercion, which, in paradigm cases, includes a threat. In one difficult sexual harassment case, someone is offered a promotion in exchange for sex, but there is, due to the arrangement of the case, no implied threat or repercussion for refusal. I argue this case counts as coercive since the offer-making attempts (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  61
    The kindest cut? Surgical castration, sex offenders and coercive offers.John McMillan - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):583-590.
    The European Committee for the Prevention of Torture and Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment have conducted visits and written reports criticising the surgical castration of sex offenders in the Czech Republic and Germany. They claim that surgical castration is degrading treatment and have called for an immediate end to this practice. The Czech and German governments have published rebuttals of these criticisms. The rebuttals cite evidence about clinical effectiveness and point out this is an intervention that must be requested (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  17.  69
    Payment for research participation: a coercive offer?A. Wertheimer & F. G. Miller - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (5):389-392.
    Payment for research participation has raised ethical concerns, especially with respect to its potential for coercion. We argue that characterising payment for research participation as coercive is misguided, because offers of benefit cannot constitute coercion. In this article we analyse the concept of coercion, refute mistaken conceptions of coercion and explain why the offer of payment for research participation is never coercive but in some cases may produce undue inducement.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  18. Coercive wage offers.David Zimmerman - 1981 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (2):121-145.
  19.  15
    Coercive Threats and Offers in Psychiatry.Thomas Schramme - 2003 - In Thomas Schramme & Johannes Thome (eds.), Philosophy and Psychiatry. De Gruyter. pp. 357-369.
    If a patient complies voluntarily with a certain proposal, we generally regard the treatment as legitimate. But a competent patient may also assent to a certain treatment only because he was compelled to do so. Influences on the formation of his decision may render his choice contrary to his will. It is my aim to focus on these particular forms of coercion which are often neglected in discussions of informed consent.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Coercive Wage Offers.Scott Anderson - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell. pp. 847-850.
  21. Zimmerman on coercive wage offers.Lawrence A. Alexander - 1983 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (2):160-164.
  22.  51
    More on coercive wage offers: A reply to Alexander.David Zimmerman - 1983 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (2):165-171.
  23.  40
    The Interpersonal Aspects of Coercive Threats and Offers.Edmund Wall - 2002 - Dialogue 41 (4):681-.
    Je défends ici une conception interpersonnelle des menaces et des offres coercitives, centrée sur les intentions de ceux qui font de telles menaces ou de tellesoffres. Je critique, ce faisant, un groupe de conceptions fort influentes, appelées «baseline accounts». Robert Nozick, qui adopte une approche de ce genre, incorpore à son analyse des menaces coercitives des éléments non moraux aussi bien que des éléments moraux. Les approches de Daniel Lyons et de David Zimmerman peuvent être vues, à certains égards, comme (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  9
    The Interpersonal Aspects of Coercive Threats and Offers.Edmund Wall - 2002 - Dialogue 41 (4):681-702.
    Je défends ici une conception interpersonnelle des menaces et des offres coercitives, centrée sur les intentions de ceux qui font de telles menaces ou de tellesoffres. Je critique, ce faisant, un groupe de conceptions fort influentes, appelées «baseline accounts». Robert Nozick, qui adopte une approche de ce genre, incorpore à son analyse des menaces coercitives des éléments non moraux aussi bien que des éléments moraux. Les approches de Daniel Lyons et de David Zimmerman peuvent être vues, à certains égards, comme (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  16
    Plea Bargaining with Wrong Reasons: Coercive Plea-Offers and Responding to the Wrong Kind of Reason.Benjamin Newman - forthcoming - Criminal Law and Philosophy:1-25.
    The notion of a defendant submitting a false guilty plea due to the penal incentive offered is not an uncommon phenomenon. While the practice has been legitimised based on the defendant’s voluntary informed consent, it has often been argued that the structure of the plea-bargaining practice is coercive. Such can be the case whenever the plea offer entails a significant sentence differential, discrepancy in the form of punishment (a non-custodial sentence relative to a custodial one), or when the alternative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  54
    Is Coercive Treatment of Offenders Morally Acceptable? On the Deficiency of the Debate.Jesper Ryberg - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (4):619-631.
    Is it morally acceptable to instigate criminal offenders to participate in rehabilitative treatment by offering treatment in return for early release from prison? Some theorists have supported such treatment schemes by pointing to the beneficial consequences that follow from the treatment. Others have suggested that the schemes are unacceptably coercive, which implies that consent becomes an illusion. This paper argues that the discussion—with clear parallels to debates of other healthcare treatment offers in medical ethics—has adopted a too narrow (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27.  7
    Critical perspectives on coercive interventions: law, medicine and society.Claire Spivakovsky (ed.) - 2018 - New York: Routledge.
    Coercive medico-legal interventions are often employed to prevent people deemed to be unable to make competent decisions about their health, such as minors, people with mental illness, disability or problematic alcohol or other drug use, from harming themselves or others. These interventions can entail major curtailments of individuals' liberty and bodily integrity, and may cause significant harm and distress. The use of coercive medico-legal interventions can also serve competing social interests that raise profound ethical, legal and clinical questions. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  14
    The Philosophy of Blackmail: Indecent Offers or Coercive Proposals.Dan Fitzpatrick - 1998 - Journal of Social Philosophy 29 (1):37-48.
  29. Correction: Plea Bargaining with Wrong Reasons: Coercive Plea-Offers and Responding to the Wrong Kind of Reason.Benjamin Newman - forthcoming - Criminal Law and Philosophy:1-1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  14
    When Treatment Pressures Become Coercive: A Context-Sensitive Model of Informal Coercion in Mental Healthcare.Christin Hempeler, Esther Braun, Sarah Potthoff, Jakov Gather & Matthé Scholten - forthcoming - American Journal of Bioethics:1-13.
    Treatment pressures are communicative strategies that mental health professionals use to influence the decision-making of mental health service users and improve their adherence to recommended treatment. Szmukler and Appelbaum describe a spectrum of treatment pressures, which encompasses persuasion, interpersonal leverage, offers and threats, arguing that only a particular type of threat amounts to informal coercion. We contend that this account of informal coercion is insufficiently sensitive to context and fails to recognize the fundamental power imbalance in mental healthcare. Based (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Justifying Coercive and Non-Coercive Intervention: Strategic and Humanitarian Arguments.Rory J. Conces - 2001 - Acta Analytica 16 (27):133-52.
    The world's political and military leaders are under increasing pressure to intervene in the affairs of sovereign nations. Although the sovereignty of states and the corollary principle of nonintervention have been part of the foundation of international law, there is some latitude for states, as well as collective security organizations, to intervene in another state's domestic and foreign affairs, thus making sovereignty and the principle less than absolute. In this paper I first sketch a reasonable foundation for sovereignty of states (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  42
    When is coercive methadone therapy justified?Daniel D'Hotman, Jonathan Pugh & Thomas Douglas - 2018 - Bioethics 32 (7):405-413.
    Heroin use poses a significant health and economic burden to society, and individuals with heroin dependence are responsible for a significant amount of crime. Owing to its efficacy and cost-effectiveness, methadone maintenance therapy (MMT) is offered as an optional alternative to imprisonment for drug offenders in several jurisdictions. Some object to such 'MMT offers' on the basis that they involve coercion and thus invalidate the offender's consent to MMT. While we find these arguments unpersuasive, we do not attempt to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  44
    Coercion completion and conservativity in coercive subtyping.Sergei Soloviev & Zhaohui Luo - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 113 (1-3):297-322.
    Coercive subtyping offers a general approach to subtyping and inheritance by introducing a simple abbreviational mechanism to constructive type theories. In this paper, we study coercion completion in coercive subtyping and prove that the formal extension with coercive subtyping of a type theory such as Martin–Löf's type theory and UTT is a conservative extension. The importance of coherence conditions for the conservativity result is also discussed.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. How Payment For Research Participation Can Be Coercive.Joseph Millum & Michael Garnett - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (9):21-31.
    The idea that payment for research participation can be coercive appears widespread among research ethics committee members, researchers, and regulatory bodies. Yet analysis of the concept of coercion by philosophers and bioethicists has mostly concluded that payment does not coerce, because coercion necessarily involves threats, not offers. In this article we aim to resolve this disagreement by distinguishing between two distinct but overlapping concepts of coercion. Consent-undermining coercion marks out certain actions as impermissible and certain agreements as unenforceable. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  35. Economic Sanctions and Political Repression: Assessing the Impact of Coercive Diplomacy on Political Freedoms. [REVIEW]Dursun Peksen & A. Cooper Drury - 2009 - Human Rights Review 10 (3):393-411.
    This article offers a thorough analysis of the unintended impact economic sanctions have on political repression—referred to in this study as the level of the government respect for democratic freedoms and human rights. We argue that economic coercion is a counterproductive policy tool that reduces the level of political freedoms in sanctioned countries. Instead of coercing the sanctioned regime into reforming itself, sanctions inadvertently enhance the regime’s coercive capacity and create incentives for the regime’s leadership to commit political (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Coercion and the Neurocorrective Offer.Jonathan Pugh - forthcoming - In David Rhys Birks & Thomas Douglas (eds.), reatment for Crime: Philosophical Essays on Neurointerventions in Criminal Justice. Oxford, UK:
    According to what Douglas calls ‘the consent requirement’, neuro-correctives can only permissibly be provided with the valid consent of the offender who will undergo the intervention. Some of those who endorse the consent requirement have claimed that even though the requirement prohibits the imposition of mandatory neurocorrectives on criminal offenders, it may yet be permissible to offer offenders the opportunity to consent to undergoing such an intervention, in return for a reduction to their penal sentence. I call this the neurocorrective (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  9
    Offering Hospitality: Questioning Christian Approaches to War by Caron E. Gentry.Andrew C. Wright - 2015 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 35 (2):204-205.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Offering Hospitality: Questioning Christian Approaches to War by Caron E. GentryAndrew C. WrightOffering Hospitality: Questioning Christian Approaches to War Caron E. Gentry notre dame, in: university of notre dame press, 2013. 200 pp. $20.00Caron E. Gentry provides a constructive proposal for transforming jus ad bellum’s last-resort criterion through the reconceptualization of hospitality as “an essential practice” (2) in international relations, one that helps jus ad bellum “operate proactively (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  37
    Transfusion contracts for Jehovah's Witnesses receiving organ transplants: ethical necessity or coercive pact?K. A. Bramstedt - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (4):193-195.
    Jehovah’s Witnesses should be required to sign transfusion contracts in order to be eligible for transplant.Human donor organs continue to be in short supply, and many potential transplant recipients die while waiting for an allograft to become available.1 Because the organ supply is so limited and the offering of organs is based on the generosity of patients and families, proper stewardship of these organs is an ethical obligation for transplant teams, as well as organ recipients. Preventable graft loss must be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Voluntary Rehabilitation? On Neurotechnological Behavioural Treatment, Valid Consent and (In)appropriate Offers.Lene Bomann-Larsen - 2011 - Neuroethics 6 (1):65-77.
    Criminal offenders may be offered to participate in voluntary rehabilitation programs aiming at correcting undesirable behaviour, as a condition of early release. Behavioural treatment may include direct intervention into the central nervous system (CNS). This article discusses under which circumstances voluntary rehabilitation by CNS intervention is justified. It is argued that although the context of voluntary rehabilitation is a coercive circumstance, consent may still be effective, in the sense that it can meet formal criteria for informed consent. Further, for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  40.  48
    Divorcing threats and offers.Scott Altman - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (3):209 - 226.
    Theories of threats and offers can blind us to some wrongs even as they illuminate others. Spouses sometimes negotiate divorce settlements by proposing to litigate custody unless given financial concessions. Supported by theories that rely exclusively on rights, courts often uphold these settlements saying things like "[s]imply insisting upon ... what one believes to be his legal rights is not coercive." I suggest a means of distinguishing (divorcing) threats from offers that explains why it is sometimes (...) to insist on one's rights in negotiations. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  8
    In part, this 'Declaration of Dresden Against Coerced Psychiatric Treatment'stated.on Coercive Treatment Users’Views - 2011 - In Thomas W. Kallert, Juan E. Mezzich & John Monahan (eds.), Coercive treatment in psychiatry: clinical, legal and ethical aspects. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Sri Aurobindo's Views on Psychology.Can It Offer A. Better Therapeutic - 2007 - In Indrani Sanyal & Krishna Roy (eds.), Understanding Thoughts of Sri Aurobindo. D.K. Printworld in Association with Jadavpur Univ., Kolkata.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  16
    Methodological ‘Elsewheres’ in Queer Anthropology: A Conversation between Bob Offer-Westort and Shakthi Nataraj.Bob Offer-Westort & Shakthi Nataraj - 2023 - Feminist Review 133 (1):26-33.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  6
    The Challenge of Affluence: Self-Control and Well-Being in the United States and Britain Since 1950.Avner Offer - 2006 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Since the 1940s Americans and Britons have come to enjoy an era of rising material abundance. Yet this has been accompanied by a range of social and personal disorders, including family breakdown, addiction, mental instability, crime, obesity, inequality, economic insecurity, and declining trust.Avner Offer argues that well-being has lagged behind affluence in these societies, because they present an environment in which consistent choices are difficult to achieve over different time ranges and in which the capacity for personal and social commitment (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  10
    Herbert Spencer and social theory.John Offer - 2010 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Herbert Spencer remains a significant but poorly understood figure in 19th century intellectual life. His ideas on evolution ranged across the natural sciences and philosophy, and he pioneered new ideas in psychology and sociology. This book comprehensively examines his work and strips away common misconceptions about his sociology" --Provided by publisher.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  5
    The Challenge of Affluence: Self-Control and Well-Being in the United States and Britain Since 1950.Avner Offer - 2006 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Since the 1940s Americans and Britons have come to enjoy an era of rising material abundance. Yet this has been accompanied by a range of social and personal disorders, including family breakdown, addiction, mental instability, crime, obesity, inequality, economic insecurity, and declining trust. Avner Offer argues that well-being has lagged behind affluence in these societies, because they present an environment in which consistent choices are difficult to achieve over different time ranges and in which the capacity for personal and social (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  9
    Free Time and Emotional Well-Being: Do Dual-Earner Mothers and Fathers Differ?Shira Offer - 2016 - Gender and Society 30 (2):213-239.
    Previous research suggests that there are important gender disparities in the experience of leisure, but the issue of how mothers and fathers experience free time emotionally remains overlooked. The present study addressed this lacuna using the Experience Sampling Method and survey data from the 500 Family Study. Results showed that mothers and fathers spent the same amount of time on leisure activities. However, mothers had slightly less pure free time than fathers and were more likely to combine leisure with unpaid (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  74
    Self-interest, Sympathy and the Invisible Hand: From Adam Smith to Market Liberalism.Avner Offer - 2012 - Economic Thought 1 (2).
    Adam Smith rejected Mandeville's invisible-hand doctrine of 'private vices, publick benefits'. In The Theory of Moral Sentiments his model of the 'impartial spectator' is driven not by sympathy for other people, but by their approbation. The innate capacity for sympathy makes approbation credible. Approbation needs to be authenticated, and in Smith's model authentication relies on innate virtue, which is not realistic. An alternative model of 'regard' makes use of signalling and is more pragmatic. Modern versions of the invisible hand in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Charles Hilliard Feinstein 1932–2004.Avner Offer - 2008 - In Offer Avner (ed.), Proceedings of the British Academy, Volume 153 Biographical Memoirs of Fellows, VII. pp. 189-212.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. ch. 13. Herbert Spencer.John Offer - 2014 - In W. J. Mander (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 974