Results for 'automorphism invariance'

999 found
Order:
  1.  7
    Automorphism invariant measures and weakly generic automorphisms.Gábor Sági - 2022 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 68 (4):458-478.
    Let be a countable ℵ0‐homogeneous structure. The primary motivation of this work is to study different amenability properties of (subgroups of) the automorphism group of ; the secondary motivation is to study the existence of weakly generic automorphisms of. Among others, we present sufficient conditions implying the existence of automorphism invariant probability measures on certain subsets of A and of ; we also present sufficient conditions implying that the theory of is amenable. More concretely, we show that if (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  28
    Automorphism–invariant measures on ℵ0-categorical structures without the independence property.Douglas E. Ensley - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):640 - 652.
    We address the classification of the possible finitely-additive probability measures on the Boolean algebra of definable subsets of M which are invariant under the natural action of $\operatorname{Aut}(M)$ . This pursuit requires a generalization of Shelah's forking formulas [8] to "essentially measure zero" sets and an application of Myer's "rank diagram" [5] of the Boolean algebra under consideration. The classification is completed for a large class of ℵ 0 -categorical structures without the independence property including those which are stable.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  59
    On automorphism groups of countable structures.Su Gao - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):891-896.
    Strengthening a theorem of D.W. Kueker, this paper completely characterizes which countable structures do not admit uncountable L ω 1 ω -elementarily equivalent models. In particular, it is shown that if the automorphism group of a countable structure M is abelian, or even just solvable, then there is no uncountable model of the Scott sentence of M. These results arise as part of a study of Polish groups with compatible left-invariant complete metrics.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4.  48
    Invariance and Definability, with and without Equality.Denis Bonnay & Fredrik Engström - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (1):109-133.
    The dual character of invariance under transformations and definability by some operations has been used in classical works by, for example, Galois and Klein. Following Tarski, philosophers of logic have claimed that logical notions themselves could be characterized in terms of invariance. In this article, we generalize a correspondence due to Krasner between invariance under groups of permutations and definability in L∞∞ so as to cover the cases that are of interest in the logicality debates, getting McGee’s (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  12
    Automorphism groups of differentially closed fields.Reinhold Konnerth - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 118 (1-2):1-60.
    We examine the connections between several automorphism groups associated with a saturated differentially closed field U of characteristic zero. These groups are: Γ, the automorphism group of U; the automorphism group of Γ; , the automorphism group of the differential combinatorial geometry of U and , the group of field automorphisms of U that respect differential closure.Our main results are:• If U is of cardinality λ+=2λ for some infinite regular cardinal λ, then the set of subgroups (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  10
    Invariant measures in simple and in small theories.Artem Chernikov, Ehud Hrushovski, Alex Kruckman, Krzysztof Krupiński, Slavko Moconja, Anand Pillay & Nicholas Ramsey - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (2).
    We give examples of (i) a simple theory with a formula (with parameters) which does not fork over [Formula: see text] but has [Formula: see text]-measure 0 for every automorphism invariant Keisler measure [Formula: see text] and (ii) a definable group [Formula: see text] in a simple theory such that [Formula: see text] is not definably amenable, i.e. there is no translation invariant Keisler measure on [Formula: see text]. We also discuss paradoxical decompositions both in the setting of discrete (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Ian I-iacking.Linguistically Invariant Inductive Logic - 1970 - In Paul Weingartner & Gerhard Zecha (eds.), Induction, physics, and ethics. Dordrecht,: Reidel.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. the Equivalence of Frames”.Invariance Covariance - 1989 - Foundations of Physics 4:267-289.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Isaac Levi.Comments on‘Linguistically Invariant & Inductive Logic’by Ian Hacking - 1970 - In Paul Weingartner & Gerhard Zecha (eds.), Induction, physics, and ethics. Dordrecht,: Reidel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Well, certain changes can indeed be, and often are, the very subject of a scientific investigation, but normally only tacitly. So let me state the obvious. Once we turn our attention from physics to the biological sciences, let alone the human sciences, we note that change, as a phenomenon. [REVIEW]Context Invariance - 1999 - In S. Smets J. P. Van Bendegem G. C. Cornelis (ed.), Metadebates on Science. Vub-Press & Kluwer. pp. 6--71.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Deriving dimensions of comparison.Jeremy Kuhn, David Nicolas & Brian Buccola - 2022 - Snippets 43:1-3.
  12.  7
    Measures induced by units.Giovanni Panti & Davide Ravotti - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (3):886-910.
    The half-open real unit interval an automorphism-invariant positive normalized linear functional onH. SinceHis representable as a uniformly dense set of continuous functions on its maximal spectrum, such functionals—in this context usually called states—amount to automorphism-invariant finite Borel measures on the spectrum. Different choices for the unit may be algebraically unrelated, but our second main result shows that the corresponding measures are always absolutely continuous w.r.t. each other, and provides an explicit expression for the reciprocal density.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  14
    Closed Normal Subgroups.James H. Schmerl - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):489-492.
    Let ℳ be a countable, recursively saturated model of Peano Arithmetic, and let Aut be its automorphism group considered as a topological group with the pointwise stabilizers of finite sets being the basic open subgroups. Kaye proved that the closed normal subgroups are precisely the obvious ones, namely the stabilizers of invariant cuts. A proof of Kaye's theorem is given here which, although based on his proof, is different enough to yield consequences not obtainable from Kaye's proof.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  15
    A Galois correspondence for countable short recursively saturated models of PA.Erez Shochat - 2010 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 56 (3):228-238.
    In this paper we investigate the properties of automorphism groups of countable short recursively saturated models of arithmetic. In particular, we show that Kaye's Theorem concerning the closed normal subgroups of automorphism groups of countable recursively saturated models of arithmetic applies to automorphism groups of countable short recursively saturated models as well. That is, the closed normal subgroups of the automorphism group of a countable short recursively saturated model of PA are exactly the stabilizers of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  34
    Direct and local definitions of the Turing jump.Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 7 (2):229-262.
    We show that there are Π5 formulas in the language of the Turing degrees, [Formula: see text], with ≤, ∨ and ∧, that define the relations x″ ≤ y″, x″ = y″ and so {x ∈ L2 = x ≥ y|x″ = y″} in any jump ideal containing 0. There are also Σ6&Π6 and Π8 formulas that define the relations w = x″ and w = x', respectively, in any such ideal [Formula: see text]. In the language with just ≤ (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  16.  8
    The Structure of Models of Peano Arithmetic.Roman Kossak & James Schmerl - 2006 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Aimed at graduate students, research logicians and mathematicians, this much-awaited text covers over 40 years of work on relative classification theory for nonstandard models of arithmetic. The book covers basic isomorphism invariants: families of type realized in a model, lattices of elementary substructures and automorphism groups.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  17. Uniqueness of simultaneity.Domenico Giulini - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (4):651-670.
    We consider the problem of uniqueness of certain simultaneity structures in flat spacetime. Absolute simultaneity is specifiled to be a non-trivial equivalence relation which is invariant under the automorphism group Aut of spacetime. Aut is taken to be the identity-component of either the inhomogeneous Galilei group or the inhomogeneous Lorentz group. Uniqueness of standard simultaneity in the first, and absence of any absolute simultaneity in the second case are demonstrated and related to certain group theoretic properties. Relative simultaneity with (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  38
    On orbits, of prompt and low computably enumerable sets.Kevin Wald - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (2):649-678.
    This paper concerns automorphisms of the computably enumerable sets. We prove two results relating semilow sets and prompt degrees via automorphisms, one of which is complementary to a recent result of Downey and Harrington. We also show that the property of effective simplicity is not invariant under automorphism, and that in fact every promptly simple set is automorphic to an effectively simple set. A major technique used in these proofs is a modification of the Harrington-Soare version of the method (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  45
    On Luce's theory of meaningfulness.Fred S. Roberts - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (3):424-433.
    This paper studies the theory of uniqueness of scales of measurement, and in particular, the theory of meaningfulness of statements using scales. The paper comments on the general theory of meaningfulness adopted by Luce in connection with his work on dimensionally invariant numerical laws. It comments on Luce's generalization of the concept of meaningfulness of a statement involving scales to a concept of meaningfulness of an arbitrary relation relative to the defining relations in a relational structure. It is argued that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  54
    Amenable versus hyperfinite borel equivalence relations.Alexander S. Kechris - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (3):894-907.
    LetXbe a standard Borel space, and letEbe acountableBorel equivalence relation onX, i.e., a Borel equivalence relationEfor which every equivalence class [x]Eis countable. By a result of Feldman-Moore [FM],Eis induced by the orbits of a Borel action of a countable groupGonX.The structure of general countable Borel equivalence relations is very little understood. However, a lot is known for the particularly important subclass consisting of hyperfinite relations. A countable Borel equivalence relation is calledhyperfiniteif it is induced by a Borel ℤ-action, i.e., by (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  25
    Local definitions in degeree structures: The Turing jump, hyperdegrees and beyond.Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):226-239.
    There are $\Pi_5$ formulas in the language of the Turing degrees, D, with ≤, ∨ and $\vedge$ , that define the relations $x" \leq y"$ , x" = y" and so $x \in L_{2}(y)=\{x\geqy|x"=y"\}$ in any jump ideal containing $0^(\omega)$ . There are also $\Sigma_6$ & $\Pi_6$ and $\Pi_8$ formulas that define the relations w = x" and w = x', respectively, in any such ideal I. In the language with just ≤ the quantifier complexity of each of these definitions (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Invariance and Logicality in Perspective.Gila Sher - 2021 - In Gil Sagi & Jack Woods (eds.), The Semantic Conception of Logic : Essays on Consequence, Invariance, and Meaning. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. pp. 13-34.
    Although the invariance criterion of logicality first emerged as a criterion of a purely mathematical interest, it has developed into a criterion of considerable linguistic and philosophical interest. In this paper I compare two different perspectives on this criterion. The first is the perspective of natural language. Here, the invariance criterion is measured by its success in capturing our linguistic intuitions about logicality and explaining our logical behavior in natural-linguistic settings. The second perspective is more theoretical. Here, the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  15
    The Automorphism Group of the Fraïssé Limit of Finite Heyting Algebras.Kentarô Yamamoto - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (3):1310-1320.
    Roelcke non-precompactness, simplicity, and non-amenability of the automorphism group of the Fraïssé limit of finite Heyting algebras are proved among others.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Invariance and Necessity.Gila Sher - 2019 - In Gabriele Mras, Paul Weingartner & Bernhard Ritter (eds.), Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics: Proceedings of the 41st International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 55-70.
    Properties and relations in general have a certain degree of invariance, and some types of properties/relations have a stronger degree of invariance than others. In this paper I will show how the degrees of invariance of different types of properties are associated with, and explain, the modal force of the laws governing them. This explains differences in the modal force of laws/principles of different disciplines, starting with logic and mathematics and proceeding to physics and biology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  15
    The automorphism tower of a centerless group without Choice.Itay Kaplan & Saharon Shelah - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (8):799-815.
    For a centerless group G, we can define its automorphism tower. We define G α : G 0 = G, G α+1 = Aut(G α ) and for limit ordinals ${G^{\delta}=\bigcup_{\alpha<\delta}G^{\alpha}}$ . Let τ G be the ordinal when the sequence stabilizes. Thomas’ celebrated theorem says ${\tau_{G}<(2^{|G|})^{+}}$ and more. If we consider Thomas’ proof too set theoretical (using Fodor’s lemma), we have here a more direct proof with little set theory. However, set theoretically we get a parallel theorem without (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  26
    Invariants versus non-accidental properties as information used in affine pattern matching.Johan Wagemans, A. De Troy, Luc Van Gool, Wood Jr & D. H. Foster - 1993 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 31:385.
    A series of experiments was performed in which subjects indicated whether two four-dot patterns were the same, although possibly viewed from different directions, or different, paired at random. Analyses of responses times and error rates suggest that the subjects' performance in this affine matching task is based on non-accidental properties such as convexity, parallelism, collinearity, and proximity, rather than on real affine invariants such as the ratio of triangular areas.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  41
    The automorphism group of a resplendent model.James H. Schmerl - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (5-6):647-649.
  28. CPT Invariance, the Spin-Statistics Connection, and the Ontology of Relativistic Quantum Field Theories.Jonathan Bain - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (4):797-821.
    CPT invariance and the spin-statistics connection are typically taken to be essential properties in relativistic quantum field theories (RQFTs), insofar as the CPT and Spin-Statistics theorems entail that any state of a physical system characterized by an RQFT must possess these properties. Moreover, in the physics literature, they are typically taken to be properties of particles. But there is a Received View among philosophers that RQFTs cannot fundamentally be about particles. This essay considers what proofs of the CPT and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  50
    On automorphism criteria for comparing amounts of mathematical structure.Thomas William Barrett, J. B. Manchak & James Owen Weatherall - 2023 - Synthese 201 (6):1-14.
    Wilhelm (Forthcom Synth 199:6357–6369, 2021) has recently defended a criterion for comparing structure of mathematical objects, which he calls Subgroup. He argues that Subgroup is better than SYM \(^*\), another widely adopted criterion. We argue that this is mistaken; Subgroup is strictly worse than SYM \(^*\). We then formulate a new criterion that improves on both SYM \(^*\) and Subgroup, answering Wilhelm’s criticisms of SYM \(^*\) along the way. We conclude by arguing that no criterion that looks only to the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  6
    Invariance.Matthew H. Kramer - 2009-04-10 - In Marcia Baron & Michael Slote (eds.), Moral Realism as a Moral Doctrine. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 152–172.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Invariance qua Uniform Applicability Invariance qua Transindividual Concurrence Invariance qua Timelessness and Ubiquity Limits on Invariance Concluding Remarks.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  37
    Automorphism group actions on trees.Alexandre Ivanov & Roman Kossak - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):71.
    We study the situation when the automorphism group of a recursively saturated structure acts on an ℝ-tree. The cases of and models of Peano Arithmetic are central in the paper.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  44
    Automorphism groups of trivial strongly minimal structures.Thomas Blossier - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):644-668.
    We study automorphism groups of trivial strongly minimal structures. First we give a characterization of structures of bounded valency through their groups of automorphisms. Then we characterize the triplets of groups which can be realized as the automorphism group of a non algebraic component, the subgroup stabilizer of a point and the subgroup of strong automorphisms in a trivial strongly minimal structure, and also we give a reconstruction result. Finally, using HNN extensions we show that any profinite group (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  15
    Automorphism Groups of Arithmetically Saturated Models.Ermek S. Nurkhaidarov - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):203 - 216.
    In this paper we study the automorphism groups of countable arithmetically saturated models of Peano Arithmetic. The automorphism groups of such structures form a rich class of permutation groups. When studying the automorphism group of a model, one is interested to what extent a model is recoverable from its automorphism group. Kossak-Schmerl [12] show that ifMis a countable, arithmetically saturated model of Peano Arithmetic, then Aut(M) codes SSy(M). Using that result they prove:Let M1. M2be countable arithmetically (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34. Background Independence, Diffeomorphism Invariance, and the Meaning of Coordinates.Oliver Pooley - 2016 - In Dennis Lehmkuhl, Gregor Schiemann & Erhard Scholz (eds.), Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories. New York, NY: Birkhauser.
    Diffeomorphism invariance is sometimes taken to be a criterion of background independence. This claim is commonly accompanied by a second, that the genuine physical magnitudes (the ``observables'') of background-independent theories and those of background-dependent (non-diffeomorphism-invariant) theories are essentially different in nature. I argue against both claims. Background-dependent theories can be formulated in a diffeomorphism-invariant manner. This suggests that the nature of the physical magnitudes of relevantly analogous theories (one background free, the other background dependent) is essentially the same. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  35.  13
    The automorphism group and definability of the jump operator in the $$\omega $$ ω -enumeration degrees.Hristo Ganchev & Andrey C. Sariev - 2021 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (7):909-925.
    In the present paper, we show the first-order definability of the jump operator in the upper semi-lattice of the \-enumeration degrees. As a consequence, we derive the isomorphicity of the automorphism groups of the enumeration and the \-enumeration degrees.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  14
    The automorphism group of the enumeration degrees.Mariya I. Soskova - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (10):982-999.
  37.  6
    Automorphism groups of countable arithmetically saturated models of peano arithmetic.James H. Schmerl - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (4):1411-1434.
  38. Invariances: the structure of the objective world.Robert Nozick - 2001 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    Excerpts from Robert Nozick's "Invariances" Necessary truths are invariant across all possible worlds, contingent ones across only some.
  39.  33
    Automorphism properties of stationary logic.Martin Otto - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1):231-237.
    By means of an Ehrenfeucht-Mostowski construction we obtain an automorphism theorem for a syntactically characterized class of Laa-theories comprising in particular the finitely determinate ones. Examples of Laa-theories with only rigid models show this result to be optimal with respect to a classification in terms of prenex quantifier type: Rigidity is seen to hinge on quantification of type $\ldots\forall\ldots\mathbf{\operatorname{stat}}\ldots$ permitting of the parametrization of families of disjoint stationary systems by the elements of the universe.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  12
    More Automorphism Groups of Countable, Arithmetically Saturated Models of Peano Arithmetic.James H. Schmerl - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (4):491-496.
    There is an infinite set T of Turing-equivalent completions of Peano Arithmetic such that whenever M and N are nonisomorphic countable, arithmetically saturated models of PA and Th, Th∈T, then Aut≇Aut.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  20
    Knight's model, its automorphism group, and characterizing the uncountable cardinals.Greg Hjorth - 2002 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 2 (01):113-144.
    We show that every ℵα can be characterized by the Scott sentence of some countable model; moreover there is a countable structure whose Scott sentence characterizes ℵ1 but whose automorphism group fails the topological Vaught conjecture on analytic sets. We obtain some partial information on Ulm type dichotomy theorems for the automorphism group of Knight's model.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  42.  10
    The Automorphism Group of the Fraïssé Limit of Finite Heyting Algebras—Addendum.Kentarô Yamamoto - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (3):1321-1322.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Invariance as a basis for necessity and laws.Gila Sher - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 178 (12):3945-3974.
    Many philosophers are baffled by necessity. Humeans, in particular, are deeply disturbed by the idea of necessary laws of nature. In this paper I offer a systematic yet down to earth explanation of necessity and laws in terms of invariance. The type of invariance I employ for this purpose generalizes an invariance used in meta-logic. The main idea is that properties and relations in general have certain degrees of invariance, and some properties/relations have a stronger degree (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  44.  7
    An automorphism group of an ω-stable structure that is not locally.Joseph Zielinski - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (6):547-551.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Invariance or equivalence: a tale of two principles.Caspar Jacobs - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):9337-9357.
    The presence of symmetries in physical theories implies a pernicious form of underdetermination. In order to avoid this theoretical vice, philosophers often espouse a principle called Leibniz Equivalence, which states that symmetry-related models represent the same state of affairs. Moreover, philosophers have claimed that the existence of non-trivial symmetries motivates us to accept the Invariance Principle, which states that quantities that vary under a theory’s symmetries aren’t physically real. Leibniz Equivalence and the Invariance Principle are often seen as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. Invariance, Structure, Measurement – Eino Kaila and the History of Logical Empiricism.Matthias Neuber - 2012 - Theoria 78 (4):358-383.
    Eino Kaila's thought occupies a curious position within the logical empiricist movement. Along with Hans Reichenbach, Herbert Feigl, and the early Moritz Schlick, Kaila advocates a realist approach towards science and the project of a “scientific world conception”. This realist approach was chiefly directed at both Kantianism and Poincaréan conventionalism. The case in point was the theory of measurement. According to Kaila, the foundations of physical reality are characterized by the existence of invariant systems of relations, which he called structures. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47.  7
    Automorphism groups of saturated models of peano arithmetic.Ermek S. Nurkhaidarov & James H. Schmerl - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (2):561-584.
  48.  30
    Typical automorphism groups of finite nonrigid structures.Vera Koponen - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):571-586.
    We work with a finite relational vocabulary with at least one relation symbol with arity at least 2. Fix any integer m > 1. For almost all finite structures such that at least m elements are moved by some automorphisms, the automorphism group is i\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${^{i}}$$\end{document} for some i≤/2\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${i \leq /2}$$\end{document}; and if some relation symbol has arity at least 3, then the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  7
    Invariance and necessity.Gila Sher - 2019 - In Gabriele Mras, Paul Weingartner & Bernhard Ritter (eds.), Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics: Proceedings of the 41st International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  84
    General Covariance, Diffeomorphism Invariance, and Background Independence in 5 Dimensions.Antonio Vassallo - 2015 - In Tomasz Bigaj & Christian Wüthrich (eds.), Metaphysics in Contemporary Physics. Boston: Brill | Rodopi.
    The paper considers the "GR-desideratum", that is, the way general relativity implements general covariance, diffeomorphism invariance, and background independence. Two cases are discussed where 5-dimensional generalizations of general relativity run into interpretational troubles when the GR-desideratum is forced upon them. It is shown how the conceptual problems dissolve when such a desideratum is relaxed. In the end, it is suggested that a similar strategy might mitigate some major issues such as the problem of time or the embedding of quantum (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999