Results for 'almost sure frame validity'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. The modal logic of the countable random frame.Valentin Goranko & Bruce Kapron - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (3):221-243.
    We study the modal logic M L r of the countable random frame, which is contained in and `approximates' the modal logic of almost sure frame validity, i.e. the logic of those modal principles which are valid with asymptotic probability 1 in a randomly chosen finite frame. We give a sound and complete axiomatization of M L r and show that it is not finitely axiomatizable. Then we describe the finite frames of that logic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  23
    Zero-one laws for modal logic.Joseph Y. Halpern & Bruce Kapron - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (2-3):157-193.
    We show that a 0–1 law holds for propositional modal logic, both for structure validity and frame validity. In the case of structure validity, the result follows easily from the well-known 0–1 law for first-order logic. However, our proof gives considerably more information. It leads to an elegant axiomatization for almost-sure structure validity and to sharper complexity bounds. Since frame validity can be reduced to a Π11 formula, the 0–1 law for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  19
    Zero-one laws for modal logic (vol 69, pg 157, 1994).Joseph Y. Halpern & Bruce Kapron - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (2-3):281-283.
    We show that a 0–1 law holds for propositional modal logic, both for structure validity and frame validity. In the case of structure validity, the result follows easily from the well-known 0–1 law for first-order logic. However, our proof gives considerably more information. It leads to an elegant axiomatization for almost-sure structure validity and to sharper complexity bounds. Since frame validity can be reduced to a Π11 formula, the 0–1 law for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  26
    Bucky flies, almost!Govinda Srinivasan - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 43 (2):pp. 109-117.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Bucky Flies, Almost!Govinda SrinivasanOne day Bucky the monkey saw birds high up in the sky. He was looking at the Harpy Eagle soaring beautifully in the sky. He wished he too could fly like that. He knew how to get to the top of the canopy, but then how to fly free in the sky? That was the great problem. Click for larger view View full resolution[End Page (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  8
    Frame-validity Games and Lower Bounds on the Complexity of Modal Axioms.Philippe Balbiani, David Fernández-Duque, Andreas Herzig & Petar Iliev - 2022 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 30 (1):155-185.
    We introduce frame-equivalence games tailored for reasoning about the size, modal depth, number of occurrences of symbols and number of different propositional variables of modal formulae defining a given frame property. Using these games, we prove lower bounds on the above measures for a number of well-known modal axioms; what is more, for some of the axioms, we show that they are optimal among the formulae defining the respective class of frames.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  94
    Thomas Nagel: Mind and Cosmos. Why the Materialist, Neo-Darwinian Conception is Almost Certainly False.Julian Nida-Rümelin - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (2):403-406.
    Anti-naturalists share the conviction that something is wrong with the naturalistic conceptual frame and with the idea that in principle all events are explainable by using the means of physics. Physicalist naturalism is the modern form of old fashioned materialism. And there is no doubt that naturalism is still going strong notwithstanding its critiques. In ethics the boom of present-day Kantian constructivism can be understood as the last and maybe the most sophisticated “naturalist” answer to the realist challenge in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  17
    Simple structures axiomatized by almost sure theories.Ove Ahlman - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (5):435-456.
  8.  4
    Optimal cost almost-sure reachability in POMDPs.Krishnendu Chatterjee, Martin Chmelík, Raghav Gupta & Ayush Kanodia - 2016 - Artificial Intelligence 234 (C):26-48.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Calibration, coherence, and scoring rules.Teddy Seidenfeld - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):274-294.
    Can there be good reasons for judging one set of probabilistic assertions more reliable than a second? There are many candidates for measuring "goodness" of probabilistic forecasts. Here, I focus on one such aspirant: calibration. Calibration requires an alignment of announced probabilities and observed relative frequency, e.g., 50 percent of forecasts made with the announced probability of.5 occur, 70 percent of forecasts made with probability.7 occur, etc. To summarize the conclusions: (i) Surveys designed to display calibration curves, from which a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  10.  46
    Aristotle and euclid's postulates.Fabio Acerbi - 2013 - Classical Quarterly 63 (2):680-685.
    Book 1 of Euclid's Elements opens with a set of unproved assumptions: definitions, postulates, and ‘common notions’. The common notions are general rules validating deductions that involve the relations of equality and congruence. The attested postulates are five in number, even if a part of the manuscript tradition adds a sixth, almost surely spurious, that in some manuscripts features as the ninth, and last, common notion. The postulates are called αἰτήματα both in the manuscripts of the Elements and in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. Rational framing effects and morally valid reasons.Tomasz Żuradzki - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 247 (45):e247.
    I argue that the scope of rational framing effects may be broader than Bermúdez assumes. Even in many “canonical experiments,” the explanation of the judgment reversals or shifts may refer to reasons, including moral ones. Referring to the Asian disease paradigm (ADP), I describe how non-consequentialist reasons related to fairness and the distinction between doing and allowing may help explain and justify the typical pattern of choices in the cases like ADP.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  21
    Frege's Way Out.James L. Hudson - 1975 - Philosophy Research Archives 1:135-140.
    I show that Frege's statement (In the Epilogue to his Grundgesetze der Arithmetic v. II) of a way to avoid Russell's paradox is defective, in that he presents two different methods as if they were one. One of these "ways out" is notably more plausible than the other, and is almost surely what Frege really intended. The well-known arguments of Lesniewski, Geach, and Quine that Frege's revision of his system is inadequate to avoid paradox are not affected by the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  60
    Hyperfinite law of large numbers.Yeneng Sun - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):189-198.
    The Loeb space construction in nonstandard analysis is applied to the theory of processes to reveal basic phenomena which cannot be treated using classical methods. An asymptotic interpretation of results established here shows that for a triangular array (or a sequence) of random variables, asymptotic uncorrelatedness or asymptotic pairwise independence is necessary and sufficient for the validity of appropriate versions of the law of large numbers. Our intrinsic characterization of almost sure pairwise independence leads to the equivalence (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  33
    How framing statistical statements affects subjective veracity: Validation and application of a multinomial model for judgments of truth.Benjamin E. Hilbig - 2012 - Cognition 125 (1):37-48.
  15.  31
    Frame constructions, truth invariance and validity preservation in many-valued modal logic.Pantelis E. Eleftheriou & Costas D. Koutras - 2005 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 15 (4):367-388.
    In this paper we define and examine frame constructions for the family of manyvalued modal logics introduced by M. Fitting in the '90s. Every language of this family is built on an underlying space of truth values, a Heyting algebra H. We generalize Fitting's original work by considering complete Heyting algebras as truth spaces and proceed to define a suitable notion of H-indexed families of generated subframes, disjoint unions and bounded morphisms. Then, we provide an algebraic generalization of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  33
    Consent's Been Framed: When Framing Effects Invalidate Consent and How to Validate It Again.Eric Chwang - 2015 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (3):270-285.
    In this article I will argue first that if ignorance poses a problem for valid consent in medical contexts then framing effects do too, and second that the problem posed by framing effects can be solved by eliminating those effects. My position is thus a mean between two mistaken extremes. At one mistaken extreme, framing effects are so trivial that they never impinge on the moral force of consent. This is as mistaken as thinking that ignorance is so trivial that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  17.  40
    The time frame of preferences, dispositions, and the validity of advance directives for the mentally ill.Julian Savulescu & Donna Dickenson - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):225-246.
  18.  14
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Dan W. Brock - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):251-253.
  19.  18
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Sally Burgess - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):255-258.
  20.  9
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Rebecca Dresser - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):247-249.
  21.  13
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Nigel Lg Eastman - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):259-261.
  22. Do framing effects make moral intuitions unreliable?Joanna Demaree-Cotton - 2016 - Philosophical Psychology 29 (1):1-22.
    I address Sinnott-Armstrong's argument that evidence of framing effects in moral psychology shows that moral intuitions are unreliable and therefore not noninferentially justified. I begin by discussing what it is to be epistemically unreliable and clarify how framing effects render moral intuitions unreliable. This analysis calls for a modification of Sinnott-Armstrong's argument if it is to remain valid. In particular, he must claim that framing is sufficiently likely to determine the content of moral intuitions. I then re-examine the evidence which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  23. Framing Effects Do Not Undermine Consent.Samuel Director - forthcoming - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice:1-15.
    Suppose that a patient is receiving treatment options from her doctor. In one case, the doctor says, “the surgery has a 90% survival rate.” Now, suppose the doctor instead said, “the procedure has a 10% mortality rate.” Predictably, the patient is more likely to consent on the first description and more likely to dissent on the second. This is an example of a framing effect. A framing effect occurs when “the description of [logically-equivalent] options in terms of gains (positive (...)) rather than losses (negative frame) elicits systematically different choices.” Framing effects are ubiquitous, but they are particularly troublesome in medicine. Many worry that there is tension between valuing informed consent and using framing effects in clinical settings. In this paper, I answer this question: if an individual is subject to a framing effect when she gives her consent, does this undermine the validity of her consent? I argue that framing effects do not undermine consent in general. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Sure-wins under coherence: a geometrical perspective.Stefano Bonzio, Tommaso Flaminio & Paolo Galeazzi - 2019 - In Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning with Uncertainty. ECSQARU 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science.
    In this contribution we will present a generalization of de Finetti's betting game in which a gambler is allowed to buy and sell unknown events' betting odds from more than one bookmaker. In such a framework, the sole coherence of the books the gambler can play with is not sucient, as in the original de Finetti's frame, to bar the gambler from a sure-win opportunity. The notion of joint coherence which we will introduce in this paper characterizes those (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  12
    Need, frames, and time constraints in risky decision-making.Adele Diederich, Marc Wyszynski & Stefan Traub - 2020 - Theory and Decision 89 (1):1-37.
    In two experiments, participants had to choose between a sure and a risky option. The sure option was presented either in a gain or a loss frame. Need was defined as a minimum score the participants had to reach. Moreover, choices were made under two different time constraints and with three different levels of induced need to be reached within a fixed number of trials. The two experiments differed with respect to the specific amounts to win and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  18
    Physicians’ framing and recommendations. Are they nudging? And do they violate the requirements of informed consent?Thomas Ploug - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (8):543-544.
    In his recent article ‘Nudging, Informed Consent and Bullshit’, William Simkulet1 convincingly argues that certain types of nudging satisfy Frankfurt’s criteria of bullshit. As a prelude to this argument, Simkulet considers whether recommendations and framing are types of nudging and whether they satisfy the requirement of adequate disclosure essential for a valid informed consent. He defines nudging as the systematic attempt at altering behaviour by non-rational means, and describes adequate disclosure as providing the patient with true information that enables an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  15
    Physicians framing and recommendations. Are they nudging? And do they violate the requirements of informed consent?Thomas Ploug - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics Recent Issues 44 (8):543-544.
    In his recent article ‘Nudging, Informed Consent and Bullshit’, William Simkulet 1 convincingly argues that certain types of nudging satisfy Frankfurt’s criteria of bullshit. As a prelude to this argument, Simkulet considers whether recommendations and framing are types of nudging and whether they satisfy the requirement of adequate disclosure essential for a valid informed consent. He defines nudging as the systematic attempt at altering behaviour by non-rational means, and describes adequate disclosure as providing the patient with true information that enables (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  36
    The prism of rules.Mark Greenberg - unknown
    Most legal theorists, including almost all positivists and many others, take for granted or are implicitly committed to an assumption that is not an official part of positivism. The assumption is that the content of the law is determined by the contents of legally authoritative pronouncements. I call it the Pronouncement View (PV, for short). The kind of determination at issue here is constitutive, not epistemic. That is, PV concerns what makes the content of the law what it is, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  4
    Framing, equivalence, and rational inference.David R. Mandel - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e234.
    Bermúdez's case for rational framing effects, while original, is unconvincing and gives only parenthetical treatment to the problematic assumptions of extensional and semantic equivalence of alternative frames in framing experiments. If the assumptions are false, which they sometimes are, no valid inferences about “framing effects” follow and, then, neither do inferences about human rationality. This commentary recaps the central problem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  22
    Framing the diagnosis and treatment of absolute uterine factor infertility: Insights from in-depth interviews with uterus transplant trial participants.Elliott G. Richards, Patricia K. Agatisa, Anne C. Davis, Rebecca Flyckt, Hilary Mabel, Tommaso Falcone, Andreas Tzakis & Ruth M. Farrell - 2019 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 10 (1):23-35.
    Background: Despite procedural innovations and increasing numbers of uterus transplant attempts worldwide, the perspectives of uterus transplant (UTx) trial participants are lacking. Methods: We conducted a mixed-methods study with women with absolute uterine factor infertility (AUFI). Participants included women who had previously contacted the Cleveland Clinic regarding the Uterine Transplant Trial and met the initial eligibility criteria for participation. In-depth interviews were conducted in conjunction with FertiQoL, a validated and widely used tool to measure the impact of infertility on the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. This paper surely contains some errors.Brian Kim - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (4):1013-1029.
    The preface paradox can be motivated by appealing to a plausible inference from an author’s reasonable assertion that her book is bound to contain errors to the author’s rational belief that her book contains errors. By evaluating and undermining the validity of this inference, I offer a resolution of the paradox. Discussions of the preface paradox have surprisingly failed to note that expressions of fallibility made in prefaces typically employ terms such as surely, undoubtedly, and bound to be. After (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  92
    Reichenbach's common cause principle.Frank Arntzenius - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Suppose that two geysers, about one mile apart, erupt at irregular intervals, but usually erupt almost exactly at the same time. One would suspect that they come from a common source, or at least that there is a common cause of their eruptions. And this common cause surely acts before both eruptions take place. This idea, that simultaneous correlated events must have prior common causes, was first made precise by Hans Reichenbach (Reichenbach 1956). It can be used to infer (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  33.  7
    How to think like Aquinas: the sure way to perfect your mental powers.Kevin Vost - 2018 - Manchester, New Hampshire: Sophia Institute Press.
    About St. Thomas Aquinas, Pope John XXII said: “A man can derive more profit in a year from his books than from pondering all his life the teaching of others.” And Pope Pius XI added: “We now say to all who are desirous of the truth: ‘Go to St. Thomas.’ ” But when we do go to Thomas – when we open his massive Summa Theologica or another of his works – we’re quickly overwhelmed, even lost. If we find him (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  6
    Surely not all experimental studies of bias need abandoning?Fiona A. White - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Cesario misrepresents experimental social psychology. The discipline encompasses significantly more than implicit bias research, including controlled decision making and real-world behavioral observations. Paradoxically, while critiquing popular implicit bias tasks, Cesario also describes task refinements that have significantly advanced their external validity and our contextual understanding of bias. Thus rather than abandonment, a call for “continued improvement” is a far more sensible proposition.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Validity rules for proportionally quantified syllogisms.Henry Albert Finch - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (1):1-18.
    Since the time, about a century ago, when DeMorgan, Boole and Jevons, inaugurated the study of the logic of numerically definite reasoning, no one has been concerned to establish the validity rules for a very general type of numerically definite inference which is a strong analogue of the classical syllogism. The reader will readily agree that the traditional rules of syllogistic inference cannot even begin to decide whether the following proportionally quantified syllogism is a valid argument: at most 4/7 (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. Contingency and Knowing Whether.Jie Fan, Yanjing Wang & Hans van Ditmarsch - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (1):75-107.
    A proposition is noncontingent, if it is necessarily true or it is necessarily false. In an epistemic context, ‘a proposition is noncontingent’ means that you know whether the proposition is true. In this paper, we study contingency logic with the noncontingency operator? but without the necessity operator 2. This logic is not a normal modal logic, because?→ is not valid. Contingency logic cannot define many usual frame properties, and its expressive power is weaker than that of basic modal logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  37.  26
    Experimental Validity and Pragmatic Modes in Empirical Science.Maria Caamaño Alegre - 2009 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 23 (1):19-45.
    The purpose of this paper is to show how the degree of experimental validity of scientific procedures is crucially involved in determining two typical pragmatic modes in science, namely, the preservation of useful procedures and the disposal of useless ideas. The term 'pragmatic' will here be used following Schurz's characterisation of being internally pragmatic, as referring to that which proves useful for scientific or epistemic goals. The first part of the paper consists in a characterisation of the notion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  12
    Validation of Embedded Experience Sampling (EES) for Measuring Non-cognitive Facets of Problem-Solving Competence in Scenario-Based Assessments.Andreas Rausch, Kristina Kögler & Jürgen Seifried - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:441622.
    To measure non-cognitive facets of competence, we developed and tested a new method that we refer to as Embedded Experience Sampling (EES). Domain-specific problem-solving competence is a multi-faceted construct that is not limited to cognitive facets such as domain knowledge or problem-solving strategies but also comprises non-cognitive facets in the sense of domain-specific emotional and motivational dispositions such as interest and self-concept. However, in empirical studies non-cognitive facets are usually either neglected or measured by generalized self-report questionnaires that are detached (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  83
    Validity in Intensional Languages: A New Approach.William H. Hanson & James Hawthorne - 1985 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 26 (1):9-35.
    Although the use of possible worlds in semantics has been very fruitful and is now widely accepted, there is a puzzle about the standard definition of validity in possible-worlds semantics that has received little notice and virtually no comment. A sentence of an intensional language is typically said to be valid just in case it is true at every world under every model on every model structure of the language. Each model structure contains a set of possible worlds, and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  57
    Appreciating Anorexia: Decisional Capacity and the Role of Values.Thomas Grisso & Paul S. Appelbaum - 2006 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 13 (4):293-297.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Appreciating Anorexia:Decisional Capacity and the Role of ValuesThomas Grisso (bio) and Paul S. Appelbaum (bio)Keywordscompetence, consent, anorexia, appreciation, decision makingTan and her colleagues (2006) reported that persons with anorexia nervosa typically manifest no difficulty satisfying the criteria for abilities associated with competence to consent to or refuse treatment. Their results led them to conclude that these patients generally had no problem grasping the nature of anorexia and its possible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  41.  16
    Finite Frames Fail: How Infinity Works Its Way into the Semantics of Admissibility.Jeroen P. Goudsmit - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (6):1191-1204.
    Many intermediate logics, even extremely well-behaved ones such as IPC, lack the finite model property for admissible rules. We give conditions under which this failure holds. We show that frames which validate all admissible rules necessarily satisfy a certain closure condition, and we prove that this condition, in the finite case, ensures that the frame is of width 2. Finally, we indicate how this result is related to some classical results on finite, free Heyting algebras.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  27
    Frames for fusions of modal logics.Sławomir Kost - 2018 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 28 (1):1-19.
    Let us consider multimodal logics and. We assume that is characterised by a class of connected frames, and there exists an -frame with a so-called -starting point. Similarly, the logic is characterised by a class of connected frames, and there exists an -frame with a -starting point. Using isomorphic copies of the frames and, we construct a connected frame which characterises the fusion. The frame thus obtained has some useful properties. Among others, is countable if both (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  30
    Topological-Frame Products of Modal Logics.Philip Kremer - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (6):1097-1122.
    The simplest bimodal combination of unimodal logics \ and \ is their fusion, \, axiomatized by the theorems of \ for \ and of \ for \, and the rules of modus ponens, necessitation for \ and for \, and substitution. Shehtman introduced the frame product \, as the logic of the products of certain Kripke frames: these logics are two-dimensional as well as bimodal. Van Benthem, Bezhanishvili, ten Cate and Sarenac transposed Shehtman’s idea to the topological semantics and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  15
    Re-framing the Abyss: the Visual Writing.Ilektra Stampoulou - 2017 - Dialogue and Universalism 27 (3):97-113.
    In this paper I intend to discuss some notions encountered in Jacques Derrida’s The Truth in Painting (1978) immediately linked to the manner in which the art object is understood and addressed, its limits, what it does/does not include/exclude, what it touches upon—if we can use such formalist terms in a deconstructive framework. These notions have perhaps formed in the past decades the art object, even though there is no frequent reference of Derridean deconstruction in texts regarding art.3 The ones (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  95
    Against external validity.Julian Reiss - 2019 - Synthese 196 (8):3103-3121.
    Francesco Guala once wrote that ‘The problem of extrapolation is a minor scandal in the philosophy of science’. This paper agrees with the statement, but for reasons different from Guala’s. The scandal is not, or not any longer, that the problem has been ignored in the philosophy of science. The scandal is that framing the problem as one of external validity encourages poor evidential reasoning. The aim of this paper is to propose an alternative—an alternative which constitutes much better (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  46.  66
    Framing the Issues: Moral Distress in Health Care. [REVIEW]Bernadette M. Pauly, Colleen Varcoe & Jan Storch - 2012 - HEC Forum 24 (1):1-11.
    Moral distress in health care has been identified as a growing concern and a focus of research in nursing and health care for almost three decades. Researchers and theorists have argued that moral distress has both short and long-term consequences. Moral distress has implications for satisfaction, recruitment and retention of health care providers and implications for the delivery of safe and competent quality patient care. In over a decade of research on ethical practice, registered nurses and other health care (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  47.  87
    Probabilistically Valid Inference of Covariation From a Single x,y Observation When Univariate Characteristics Are Known.Michael E. Doherty, Richard B. Anderson, Amanda M. Kelley & James H. Albert - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (2):183-205.
    Participants were asked to draw inferences about correlation from single x,y observations. In Experiment 1 statistically sophisticated participants were given the univariate characteristics of distributions of x and y and asked to infer whether a single x, y observation came from a correlated or an uncorrelated population. In Experiment 2, students with a variety of statistical backgrounds assigned posterior probabilities to five possible populations based on single x, y observations, again given knowledge of the univariate statistics. In Experiment 3, statistically (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  5
    Almost the same, but not quite’: Ontological politics of recognition in modern science fiction.Ingvil Hellstrand - 2016 - Feminist Theory 17 (3):251-267.
    This article explores how issues of ‘not quite human-ness’ expose the conditions of possibility of being considered human; of human ontology. I refer to these dynamics for identifying sameness and difference as ontological politics of recognition. Tracing the genealogies of passing, I situate passing and Othering socio-political regulation and ideological frameworks for conceptualising ontology. I am particularly concerned with how the notion of ontology is bound up in questions of race and gender, and with the entanglements of technology and biology (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  12
    Praktische Vernunft und System: Entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zur ursprunglichen Kant-Rezeption Johann Gottlieb Fichtes (review).Günter Zöller - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2):304-305.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.2 (2001) 304-305 [Access article in PDF] Wildfeuer, Armin G. Praktische Vernunft und System. Entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zur ursprünglichen Kant-Rezeption Johann Gottlieb Fichtes. Stuttgart-Bad/Cannstatt : Frommann-Holzboog, 1999. Pp. 596. Cloth, DM 168. The subtitle of this book, a slightly revised dissertation from the University of Bonn (1994), reads: "Investigations into the developmental history of Johann Gottlieb Fichte's original reception of Kant." The work comes (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Expanding the Duty to Rescue to Climate Migration.David N. Hoffman, Anne Zimmerman, Camille Castelyn & Srajana Kaikini - 2022 - Voices in Bioethics 8.
    Photo by Jonathan Ford on Unsplash ABSTRACT Since 2008, an average of twenty million people per year have been displaced by weather events. Climate migration creates a special setting for a duty to rescue. A duty to rescue is a moral rather than legal duty and imposes on a bystander to take an active role in preventing serious harm to someone else. This paper analyzes the idea of expanding a duty to rescue to climate migration. We address who should have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000