Results for 'Unsurveyability'

14 found
Order:
  1.  2
    Our Unsurveyable Grammar.Hans Sluga - 2011 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), Wittgenstein. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 95–111.
    This chapter contains sections titled: From the Synoptic View to the Album “I don't know my way about” The Problem of Grammar Essential Complexity The Practice of Language Hyper ‐ complexity.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  9
    Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps.David Wagner - 2011 - In David Wagner, Wolfram Pichler, Elisabeth Nemeth & Richard Heinrich (eds.), Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society - N.S. 17. De Gruyter. pp. 365-376.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  63
    Wayne Martin on judgment. [REVIEW]Hans Sluga - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 137 (1):109 - 119.
    Wayne Martin’s Theories of Judgment marks a significant advance in the philosophical analysis of judgment. He understands that the domain of judgment is so large that it allows only a selective treatment. We can expand Martin’s insight by acknowledging that this domain is, in fact, hypercomplex and therefore unsurveyable in Wittgenstein’s sense. Martin’s treatment of judgments can, however, be extended in a number of directions. Of particular importance is it to understand the linguistic aspect of theoretical judgments, the challenges to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. "A mathematical proof must be surveyable" what Wittgenstein meant by this and what it implies.Felix Mühlhölzer - 2006 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 71 (1):57-86.
    In Part III of his Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics Wittgenstein deals with what he calls the surveyability of proofs. By this he means that mathematical proofs can be reproduced with certainty and in the manner in which we reproduce pictures. There are remarkable similarities between Wittgenstein's view of proofs and Hilbert's, but Wittgenstein, unlike Hilbert, uses his view mainly in critical intent. He tries to undermine foundational systems in mathematics, like logicist or set theoretic ones, by stressing the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  5. Computers, justification, and mathematical knowledge.Konstantine Arkoudas & Selmer Bringsjord - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):185-202.
    The original proof of the four-color theorem by Appel and Haken sparked a controversy when Tymoczko used it to argue that the justification provided by unsurveyable proofs carried out by computers cannot be a priori. It also created a lingering impression to the effect that such proofs depend heavily for their soundness on large amounts of computation-intensive custom-built software. Contra Tymoczko, we argue that the justification provided by certain computerized mathematical proofs is not fundamentally different from that provided by surveyable (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  6. The epistemological status of computer-assisted proofs.Mark McEvoy - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):374-387.
    Several high-profile mathematical problems have been solved in recent decades by computer-assisted proofs. Some philosophers have argued that such proofs are a posteriori on the grounds that some such proofs are unsurveyable; that our warrant for accepting these proofs involves empirical claims about the reliability of computers; that there might be errors in the computer or program executing the proof; and that appeal to computer introduces into a proof an experimental element. I argue that none of these arguments withstands scrutiny, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7.  77
    Relying on Experts as We Reason Together.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 22 (2):91-110.
    In various contexts, it is thought to be important that we reason together. For instance, an attractive conception of democracy requires that citizens reach lawmaking decisions by reasoning with one another. Reasoning requires that reasoners survey the considerations that they take to be reasons, proceed by a coherent train of thought, and reach conclusions freely. De facto reliance on experts threatens the possibility of collective reasoning by making some reasons collectively unsurveyable, raising questions about the coherence of the resulting train (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8. Kripke Models.John P. Burgess - 2011 - In Alan Berger (ed.), Saul Kripke. Cambridge University Press.
    Saul Kripke has made fundamental contributions to a variety of areas of logic, and his name is attached to a corresponding variety of objects and results. 1 For philosophers, by far the most important examples are ‘Kripke models’, which have been adopted as the standard type of models for modal and related non-classical logics. What follows is an elementary introduction to Kripke’s contributions in this area, intended to prepare the reader to tackle more formal treatments elsewhere.2 2. WHAT IS A (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  34
    Wittgenstein on Perspicuous Presentations and Grammatical Self-Knowledge.Christian Georg Martin - 2016 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (1):79-108.
    The task of this paper is to exhibit Wittgenstein’s method of perspicuous presentation as aiming at a distinctive kind of self-knowledge. Three influential readings of Wittgenstein’s concept of perspicuous presentation – Hacker’s, Baker’s and Sluga’s – are examined. All of them present what Wittgenstein calls the “unsurveyablity of our grammar” as a result of the “complexity” of our language. Contrary to this, a fundamental difference between matter-of-factual complexity and the unsurveyability of grammar is pointed out. What perspicuous presentations are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  11
    Nietzsche and "an Architecture of Our Minds".Alexandre Kostka & Irving Wohlfarth (eds.) - 1999 - Getty Research Institute.
    Appropriated as an icon by an astonishingly diverse spectrum of people, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche has been the subject of countless volumes of literature. Until now, though, there has been no in-depth study devoted specifically to Nietzsches thoughts and impact on architecture. In the essays comprising Nietzsche and An Architecture of Our Minds, thirteen eminent scholars from a wide variety of disciplines--including art history, architecture and architecture theory, literature, philosophy, and city planning--address his far-reaching notion of an architecture commensurate with the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  28
    Logical Revisionism: Logical Rules vs. Structural Rules.Fabrice Pataut - unknown
    As far as logic is concerned, the conclusion of Michael Dummett's manifestability argument is that intuitionistic logic, as first developed by Heyting, satisfies the semantic requirements of antirealism. The argument may be roughly sketched as follows: since we cannot manifest a grasp of possibly justification-transcendent truth conditions, we must countenance conditions which are such that, at least in principle and by the very nature of the case, we are able to recognize that they are satisfied whenever they are. Intuitionistic logic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  12
    Kripke, Quine and Steiner on Representing Natural Numbers in Set Theory.Oliver R. Marshall - 2023 - In Carl Posy & Yemima Ben-Menahem (eds.), Mathematical Knowledge, Objects and Applications: Essays in Memory of Mark Steiner. Springer. pp. 157-192.
    Saul Kripke’s analysis of the concept of the natural numbers that we are taught in school yields a novel and axiomatically economical way of representing arithmetic in standard set theory—one that helps to answer Benacerraf’s objection from extraneous content as well as Wittgenstein’s objection from unsurveyability. After describing Kripke’s proposal in some detail, we examine it in the light of work by Quine, Steiner, Parsons, Boolos and Burgess. Although the primary aim of this paper is to present and explicate (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  70
    The philosophy of strict finitism.Ernest J. Welti - 1987 - Theoria 2 (2):575-582.
    The philosolphy of strict finitism is a research programme containing developmental theory and mathematics as its main branches. The first branch is concerned with the ontogenetic and historicaldevelopment of various concepts of infinity. The frame work is Jean Piaget’s genetic epistemology. Based upon these develop mental studies, the mathematical branch introduces a new concept of infinity into mathematics. Cantor propagated the actual infinite, Brouwer and the constructivists the potential infinite. Still more radical is strict finitism, favoring the natural infinite, i.e. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  22
    Review: Wayne Martin on Judgment. [REVIEW]Hans Sluga - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 137 (1):109-119.
    Wayne Martin 's Theories of Judgment marks a significant advance in the philosophical analysis of judgment. He understands that the domain of judgment is so large that it allows only a selective treatment. We can expand Martin 's insight by acknowledging that this domain is, in fact, hypercomplex and therefore unsurveyable in Wittgenstein's sense. Martin 's treatment of judgments can, however, be extended in a number of directions. Of particular importance is it to understand the linguistic aspect of theoretical judgments, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark