Results for 'Speusippus'

60 found
Order:
See also
  1.  3
    Frammenti.Speusippus - 1980 - Napoli: Bibliopolis. Edited by Margherita Isnardi Parente.
  2.  69
    Speusippus of Athens: A Critical Study with a Collection of the Related Texts and Commentary.Leonardo Tarán (ed.) - 1981 - Leiden: Brill.
    CHAPTER ONE LIFE The extant evidence about Speusippus' life is scanty, and little of it is reliable. The reasons are not difficult to discover : the greater ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  3. Speusippus and Xenocrates on the Pursuit and Ends of Philosophy.Phillip Sidney Horky - 2017 - In Harold Tarrant, Danielle A. Layne, Dirk Baltzly & François Renaud (eds.), Brill’s Companion to the Reception of Plato in Antiquity. Leiden: Brill. pp. 29-45.
    The philosophical practices undertaken in Plato's Academy remain, in the words of Cherniss, a 'riddle'. Yet surviving accounts of the views of the first two scholarchs of Plato's Academy after his death, Speusippus and Xenocrates, reveal a sophisticated engagement with their teacher's ideas concerning the pursuit of knowledge and the ends of philosophy. Speusippus and Xenocrates transform Plato's views on epistemology and happiness, and thereby help to lay the groundwork for the transformation of philosophy in the Hellenistic era.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  16
    Speusippus’ Omniscience Puzzle.Edoardo Benati - 2024 - Ancient Philosophy 44 (1):99-122.
    Aristotle and Eudemus report a Speusippean argument to the effect that defining anything requires knowing everything. Scholars have failed to make sense of this argument. This paper argues that the main preoccupations to which the Puzzle is meant to respond are: (i) to ensure the co-extensiveness of the definition with the definiendum; (ii) to rule out a particular definitional mistake—underdivision. The implications of the Puzzle for Speusippus’ conception of knowledge are further explored.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  24
    Speusippus on Cognitive Sense Perception: Sextus Empiricus M 7.145‐6.Eleni Kaklamanou - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (6):1183-1193.
    (2012). Speusippus on Cognitive Sense Perception: Sextus Empiricus M 7.145‐6. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 20, No. 6, pp. 1183-1193. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2012.731246.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Speusippus, teleology and the metaphysics of value: Theophrastus’ Metaphysics 11a18–26.Wei Cheng - 2020 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 140:143-175.
    This paper reexamines Theophrastus’ Metaphysics 11a18–26, an obscure testimony about Speusippus, the second head of the Platonic Academy. As opposed to the traditional interpretation, which takes this passage as Theophrastus’ polemic against Speusippus’ doctrine of value, I argue that he here dialectically takes advantage of, rather than launches an attack on, the Platonist. Based on this new reading, I further propose a revision and a reassessment of the ‘gloomy metaphysics’ of Speusippus which will shed new light on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  48
    Aristotle, Speusippus, and the method of division.Andrea Falcon - 2000 - Classical Quarterly 50 (02):402-.
    As Aristotle himself says, A.Po. 2.13 is an attempt to provide some rules to hunt out the items predicated in what something is, namely to discover definitions. Since most of this chapter is devoted to the discussion of some rules of division , it may be inferred that somehow division plays a central role in the discovery of definitions. However, in the following pages I shall not discuss what this role is. Nor shall I discuss what place division has in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  21
    Aristotle, Speusippus, and the method of division.Andrea Falcon - 2000 - Classical Quarterly 50 (2):402-414.
    As Aristotle himself says, A.Po. 2.13 is an attempt to provide some rules to hunt out the items predicated in what something is, namely to discover definitions. Since most of this chapter is devoted to the discussion of some rules of division, it may be inferred that somehow division plays a central role in the discovery of definitions. However, in the following pages I shall not discuss what this role is. Nor shall I discuss what place division has in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  4
    II. Speusippus.Christian August Brandis - 1853 - In Theil 2, Abtheilung 2, Hälfte 1: Aristoteles, Seine Akademischen Zeitgenossen Und Nächsten Nachfolger. De Gruyter. pp. 6-19.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Speusippus and Aristotle on Homonymy and Synonymy.Leonardo Tarán - 1978 - Hermes 106 (1):73-99.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  11
    Speusippus' ontological classification.H. A. S. Tarrant - 1974 - Phronesis 19 (1):130-145.
  12.  67
    Homonymy in Aristotle and Speusippus.Jonathan Barnes - 1971 - Classical Quarterly 21 (01):65-.
    ‘There are important differences between Aristotle's account of homonymy and synonymy on the one hand, and Speusippus' on the other; in particular, Aristotle treated homonymy and synonymy as properties of things, whereas Speusippus treated them as properties of words. Despite this difference, in certain significant passages Aristotle fell under the influence of Speusippus and used die words “homonymous” and “synonymous” in their Speusippan senses.’.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  27
    Speusippus.Russell Dancy - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  14.  27
    Speusippus in Iamblichus.John Dillon - 1984 - Phronesis 29 (3):325-332.
  15. Plotinus, Speusippus and the Platonic Parmenides.John Dillon - 1999 - Kairos.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Aristotle on Speusippus on Eudoxus on pleasure.James Warren - 2009 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36:249-81.
  17. Aristotle on Speusippus on Eudoxus on Pleasure.James Warren - 2009 - In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume Xxxvi. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  24
    Speusippus Leonardo Tarán: Speusippus of Athens: A Critical Study, with a Collection of the Related Texts and Commentary. (Philosophia Antiqua, 39.) Pp. xxvii + 521. Leiden: Brill, 1981. Paper, fl. 244. [REVIEW]John Dillon - 1983 - The Classical Review 33 (02):225-227.
  19.  7
    Speusippus[REVIEW]John Dillon - 1983 - The Classical Review 33 (2):225-227.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  11
    The Chicken or the Egg? Aristotle on Speusippus’ Reasons to Deny the Principle is (the) Good.Giulia De Cesaris - 2023 - Apeiron 56 (1):105-130.
    In Metaphysics Λ7 1072b30–1073a3, Aristotle introduces a Speusippean theory according to which ‘what is most beautiful and best is not en archēi’. Through a detailed analysis of the passage, I argue that Aristotle’s refutation of Speusippus’ thesis is favoured by the introduction of the seed example, which conflates both ontological and temporal priority. The elements gathered from the analysis of Aristotle’s polemical strategy will support a broader conclusion: Speusippus’ reason not to characterise his principle(s) as (the) good is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Tarán, L., Speusippus of Athens. [REVIEW]C. Steel - 1984 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 46:326.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  15
    Support of Athenian intellectuals for Philip: a study of Isocrates' Philippus and Speusippus' Letter to Philip.Minor Millikin Markle - 1976 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 96:80-99.
  23. The role of numbers in the metaphysics of speusippus-analysis of ancient testimonial principles and comparison with the dottrine-non-scritte of Plato.A. Chiroli - 1986 - Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 78 (2):185-197.
  24.  4
    [Recensão a] Anthony Francis Natoli: The Letter of Speusippus to Philip II. Introduction, Text, Translation and Commentary.Stefan Schorn - 2007 - Plato Journal 7.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Ideas, Numbers, and Magnitudes: Remarks on Plato, Speusippus, and Aristotle.L. Tarán - 1991 - Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 9 (2):199-231.
  26.  18
    From mathematical intermediates to an intermediate position? The case of Speusippus’ soul.Giulia De Cesaris - 2022 - Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 1:47-77.
    Cet article vise à comprendre si une quelconque notion d’“intermédiaire” joue un rôle dans le système de Speusippe. Je commence en étudiant cette question vis-à-vis des objets mathématiques. Étant donné que je souscris au modèle épisodique du monde de Speusippe, je propose que la seule signification possible de μεταξύ dans son système est celle d’une simple position. En effet, dans un monde épisodique, la distinction ontologique radicale qui délimite chaque couche de réalité demande une signification de μεταξύ qui n’indique rien (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Dyschereia and Aporia: The Formation of a Philosophical Term.Wei Cheng - 2018 - TAPA 148 (1):75-110.
    Plato’s nephew Speusippus has been widely accepted as the historical person behind the mask of the anti-hedonists in Phlb. 42b–44c. This hypothesis is supported by, inter alia, the link between Socrates’ char- acterization of them as δυσχερεῖς and the frequent references of δυσχέρεια as ἀπορία to Speusippus in Aristotle’s Metaphysics MN. This study argues against assigning any privileged status to Speusippus in the assimilation of δυσχέρεια with ἀπορία. Instead, based on a comprehensive survey of how δυσχερ- words (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Aristotle and Eudoxus on the Argument from Contraries.Wei Cheng - 2020 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 102 (4):588-618.
    The debate over the value of pleasure among Eudoxus, Speusippus, and Aristotle is dramatically documented by the Nicomachean Ethics, particularly in the dialectical pros-and-cons concerning the so-called argument from contraries. Two similar versions of this argument are preserved at EN VII. 13, 1153b1–4, and X. 2, 1172b18–20. Many scholars believe that the argument at EN VII is either a report or an appropriation of the Eudoxean argument in EN X. This essay aims to revise this received view. It will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  26
    Two Studies in the Early Academy.R. M. Dancy - 1991 - State University of New York Press.
    Dancy (philosophy, Florida State U.) presents two new interpretations of the evidence regarding the metaphysical ideas of two important figures in Plato's Academy, Eudoxus and Speusippus, and of Aristotle's reaction to those ideas.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  7
    Speusipps Reise nach Makedonien.Tobias Hirsch - 2023 - Hermes 151 (3):373-378.
    A journey to Macedonia, which, according to Diogenes Laertius and Flavius Philostratus, Speusippus, the Academy’s head after the death of Plato, is said to have made in order to attend the wedding of Cassander, the later Macedonian king, has puzzled scholars long since. They either consider it a story of pure fiction denying its historical relevance or by conveniently altering Cassander’s year of birth try to reconcile both events. This article argues for changing ‘Cassander’ into ‘Asander’, as both names (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Ontological Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.Emily Katz - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (1):26-68.
    Ontological separation plays a key role in Aristotle’s metaphysical project: substances alone are ontologically χωριστόν. The standard view identifies Aristotelian ontological separation with ontological independence, so that ontological separation is a non-symmetric relation. I argue that there is strong textual evidence that Aristotle employs an asymmetric notion of separation in the Metaphysics—one that involves the dependence of other entities on the independent entity. I argue that this notion allows Aristotle to prevent the proliferation of substance-kinds and thus to secure the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32. Греческая арифмология: Пифагор или платон?Leonid Zhmud - 2017 - Schole 11 (2):428-459.
    This essay considers the origins of the arithmological genre, the first specimen of which was an anonymous Neopythagorean treatise of the first century BCE. Arithmology as a special genre of philosophical writings dealing with the properties of the first ten numbers should be distinguished from number symbolism, which is a universal cultural phenomenon related to individual significant numbers. As our analysis shows, the philosophical foundations of arithmology were laid down in the treatise of Plato’s successor Speusippus On Pythagorean Numbers, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33. Supplementum Academicum Per l'Integrazione E la Revisione di Speusippo, Frammenti E Senocrate-Ermodoro, Frammenti, "la Scuola di Platone" I E Ii.Margherita Isnardi Parente - 1995 - Accademia Nazionale Dei Lincei.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  64
    The riddle of the early Academy.Harold Fredrik Cherniss - 1945 - New York, N.Y.: Garland.
    Plato's lectures: a hypothesis for an enigma.--Speusippus, Xenocrates, and the polemical method of Aristotle.--The Academy: orthodoxy, heresy, or philosophical interpretation?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  35. Aristotle on Homonymy: Dialectic and Science.Julie K. Ward - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Julie K. Ward examines Aristotle's thought regarding how language informs our views of what is real. First she places Aristotle's theory in its historical and philosophical contexts in relation to Plato and Speusippus. Ward then explores Aristotle's theory of language as it is deployed in several works, including Ethics, Topics, Physics, and Metaphysics, so as to consider its relation to dialectical practice and scientific explanation as Aristotle conceived it.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  36.  32
    Plato’s Critique of Antisthenes on Pleasure and the Good Life.Sean McConnell - 2015 - Ancient Philosophy 35 (2):329-349.
    The anonymous anti-hedonists at Philebus 44a–53c make three bold claims: (1) there are in fact no such things as pleasures; (2) what the hedonist followers of Philebus call pleasure is really nothing but escape from pain; (3) there is nothing healthy in pleasure (pleasure is never a good). These anti-hedonists are commonly identified with Speusippus, Plato’s nephew and his successor as head of the Academy. In this paper I first argue that this widely favoured view should be rejected. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  36
    Parmenides in Plato’s Parmenides.Andreas Graeser - 2000 - Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 5 (1):1-16.
    This essay examines the role of Parmenides in Plato’s dialogue of the same name. Over against the widely held view that this literary figure exemplifies the philosopher par excellence of an all-encompassing systematic of Eleatic provenience, it is maintained that Parmenides represents a particular frame of mind about certain philosophical matters, namely one which regards forms in a reified manner. It is suggested that by means of the literary figure of Parmenides, Plato is addressing in his dialogue inner-Academic debates about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  2
    Космогонски реализам Тимејеве „вјероватне приче“.Душан Крцуновић - 2006 - Philotheos 6:102-115.
    This paper deals with the reasons for literal interpretation of Plato’s Timaeus (Aristoteles) against non-literal (Speusippus and Xenocrates). Its starting point is “dichotomy” between poetry (mythos) and philosophy that we can find, as well, in some commentary on the Genesis of Moses. But, instead dichotomy here is suggested some kind of iterative reading: the Timaeus of Plato is the poetry because God’s act of creation is the poetry, too. Artistic elements in this dialogue of Plato are in the function (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  17
    Plato's Timaeus as Cultural Icon (review).Gerard Naddaf - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (3):335-337.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Plato's Timaeus as Cultural IconGerard NaddafGretchen J. Reydams-Schils, editor. Plato's Timaeus as Cultural Icon. Notre Dame, IN.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2003. Pp. xiv + 334. Cloth, $59.95. Paper, $29.95.This volume emanates from an international conference entitled "Plato's Timaeus as Cultural Icon" held at the University of Notre Dame in 2000. In the introduction, the editor and organizer, Gretchen Reydams-Schils (GRS), contends that the title is meant (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  36
    The Number Ten Reconsidered: Did the Pythagoreans Have an Account of the Dekad?Irina Deretić & Višnja Knežević - 2020 - Rhizomata 8 (1):37-58.
    We critically reconsider an old hypothesis of the role of the dekad in Pythagorean philosophy. Unlike Zhmud, we claim that: 1) the dekad did play a role in Philolaus’ astronomical system, and 2) Aristotle did not project Plato’s theory of the ten eidetic numbers onto the Pythagoreans. We claim that the dekad, as the τέλειος ἀριθμός, should be understood in Philolaus’ philosophy as completeness and the basis of counting in Greek – as in most other languages – in a decimal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  9
    Między dobrem a jednością: związek dobra i jedna w filozofii Platona, Starej Akademii i Arystotelesa.Artur Pacewicz - 2004 - Wrocław: Wydawn. Uniwersytetu Wrocławskiego.
    The aim of the work is to preent the connection between the conception of One - έν and the Good - τάγαθόν in Plato's late writings , in the fragments of writings of the members of the First Plato Academy: Philip of Opus , Eudoxos of Knidos, Speusippus, Xenocrates and the chosen Aristotle's writings . In the analysis of the texts all the derivatives of the conception of One and the Good are taken into account. As a research hypothesis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  46
    On some academic theories of mathematical objects.Ian Mueller - 1986 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 106:111-120.
    In his critical study of Speusippus Leonardo Tarán (T.) expounds an interpretation of a considerable part of the controversial books M and N of Aristotle's Metaphysics. In this essay I want to consider three aspects of the interpretation, the account of Plato's ‘ideal numbers’ (section I), the account of Speusippus’ mathematical ontology (section II), and the account of the principles of that ontology (section III). T. builds his interpretation squarely on the work of Harold Cherniss (C.), to whom (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  30
    Polyclitus and Pythagoreanism.J. E. Raven - 1951 - Classical Quarterly 1 (3-4):147-.
    In a well-known quotation from Speusippus in the Theologumena Arithmeticae , said to have been derived from Pythagorean sources, especially Philolaus, occur the following sentences: And again a little later: Similarly Sextus Empiricus , drawing evidently on a relatively early Pythagorean source, writes as follows: And Aristotle himself writes of the Pythagoreans : There were, in fact, certain Pythagoreans who equated the number 2 with the line because they regarded the line as ‘length without breadth extended between two points’; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  27
    Plato's "Parmenides" a Report on New Source Material.Robert Brumbaugh - 1954 - Review of Metaphysics 8 (1):200 - 203.
    The volume contains, in addition to the final part of the Commentary, a critical text of the Parmenides through the first hypothesis, as it appears in the lemmata of the Latin Proclus, a new fragment of Speusippus, a new one-page summary of the Stoic-Peripatetic controversy over counterfactuals, and the marginalia of Cusanus on this final section of the Proclus in his Latin manuscript. There are, thus, primary sources in Hellenic, Hellenistic, Medieval and Renaissance philosophy appearing for the first time (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  39
    The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy, 347-274 B.C. (review).Carlos G. Steel - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (2):204-205.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347–274 BC)Carlos SteelJohn M. Dillon. The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347–274 BC). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003. Pp. x + 252. Cloth, $65.00.When Plato died, in 347 BC, he left behind not only the collection of philosophical dialogues we still read with admiration, but also a remarkable organization, the "Academy," wherein his students continued (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  12
    The Origins of Platonists' Dogmatism.John Dillon - 2007 - Schole 1 (1):25-37.
    The author argues, that the exigencies of inter‐school rivalry, initially between the Academy and the Peripatos, but then between later Platonists and both Stoics and Aristotelians, demanded that Platonism become more formalized than it was left by Plato himself, and that it was primarily Xenocrates, in a vast array of treatises, both general and particular, who provided the bones of this organized corpus of doctrine. Not that the Platonists were ever subject to anything like a monolithic orthodoxy. Platonic doctrine was (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  41
    The heirs of Plato: a study of the Old Academy, 347-274 B.C.John M. Dillon - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Heirs of Plato is the first book exclusively devoted to an in-depth study of the various directions in philosophy taken by Plato's followers in the first seventy years or so following his death in 347 BC--the period generally known as 'The Old Academy'. Speusippus, Xenocrates, and Polemon, the three successive heads of the Academy in this period, though personally devoted to the memory of Plato, were independent philosophers in their own right, and felt free to develop his heritage (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  48.  11
    Polyclitus and Pythagoreanism.J. E. Raven - 1951 - Classical Quarterly 1 (3-4):147-152.
    In a well-known quotation from Speusippus in the Theologumena Arithmeticae, said to have been derived from Pythagorean sources, especially Philolaus, occur the following sentences: And again a little later: Similarly Sextus Empiricus, drawing evidently on a relatively early Pythagorean source, writes as follows: And Aristotle himself writes of the Pythagoreans : There were, in fact, certain Pythagoreans who equated the number 2 with the line because they regarded the line as ‘length without breadth extended between two points’; and likewise (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  59
    Aristotle's alleged "revolt" against Plato.Anton-Hermann Chroust - 1973 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 11 (1):91.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Notes and Discussions ARISTOTLE'S ALLEGED "REVOLT" AGAINST PLATO Hermippus' most conspicuous contribution to Aristotle's biography probably was his determined effort to depict Aristotle as the founder of an original school of philosophy which was wholly independent of Plato and Platonic teachings. Among the several and, in all likelihood, fanciful stories about Aristotle he invented or propagated, the most startling was the account, subsequently widely accepted (and widely exploited by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  1
    Eine Verfeinerung von Speusipps einzigem Epigramm – Geschenke von und für Musen.Kilian Fleischer - 2019 - Hermes 147 (3):366.
    The only known epigram by Speusippus is preserved in Philodemus’ Index Academicorum (PHerc. 1021, col. 6,34-38) and was written on the occasion of his dedication of statues of the Charites to the Muses. A rereading of a crucial word in the papyrus reveals the true reason for Speusippus’ gift: The gifts of the Muses. Furthermore, the new reading leads to a second polyptoton in the epigram so that it now sounds much more polished and sophisticated.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 60