Results for 'Speaker’s meaning'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Beyond Speaker’s Meaning.Dan Sperber & Deirdre Wilson - 2015 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):117-149.
    Our main aim in this paper is to show that constructing an adequate theory of communication involves going beyond Grice’s notion of speaker’s meaning. After considering some of the difficulties raised by Grice’s three-clause definition of speaker’s meaning, we argue that the characterisation of ostensive communication introduced in relevance theory can provide a conceptually unified explanation of a much wider range of communicative acts than Grice was concerned with, including cases of both ‘showing that’ and ‘telling (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  2. Speaker's meaning.Frank Vlach - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (3):359 - 391.
    The strongest objection to (15) is that speaker's meaning is defined in terms of commitment, a notion which is itself something of a challenge and for which no definition has been given. This would be a strong reason to prefer a definition in terms of some more tractable concept, all things being equal; but it does not lessen the probability that commitment or some similar notion is indispensable to the definition of speaker's meaning.The philosophical writings discussed in this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  3. Change of Languages as a Result of Decay and Change of Culture.S. A. Wurm - 1987 - Diogenes 35 (137):39-51.
    In a number of areas, in particular in the Pacific region, it has been observed that languages have undergone simplification processes of their usually very elaborate grammatical structures, and that such elaborate grammatical features have decayed and in some cases entirely disappeared from some languages, hand in hand with the progressing decay, and falling into disuse, of the traditional cultures of the speakers of such languages. Such phenomena of simplification and decay of grammatical complexities are most readily observable in Papuan (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  45
    Speaker’s meaning and non-cancellability.Guangwu Feng - 2013 - Pragmatics and Cognition 21 (1):117-138.
    This article intends to reveal the unity between intention and other Gricean notions of signification, cancellability, and context. We argue that the total signification of an utterance is ultimately determined by speaker’s intention. We start with Grice’s conception of meaningNN and then proceed to argue that what is actually meant (both what is said and what is implicated) is hard to cancel without rendering the whole utterance self-contradictory. It is noted that cancelling p be differentiated from correcting p . (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  15
    Speaker’s meaning and non-cancellability.Guangwu Feng - 2013 - Pragmatics and Cognition 21 (1):117-138.
    This article intends to reveal the unity between intention and other Gricean notions of signification, cancellability, and context. We argue that the total signification of an utterance is ultimately determined by speaker’s intention. We start with Grice’s conception of meaningNN and then proceed to argue that what is actually meant is hard to cancel without rendering the whole utterance self-contradictory. It is noted that cancelling p be differentiated from correcting p. It is also noted that contextual factors do not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  8
    A Speaker-Meaning Theory of Moral Responsibility.Michael S. McKenna - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 26:53-59.
    In this paper I attempt to give an account of the moral criticizability of motive by appeal to some insights in semantic theory. I maintain that the actions for which we hold persons responsible cannot strictly be understood as expressive of semantic meaning. However, I argue that morally responsible actions can be understood on analogy with a basic Gricean distinction between speaker's and sentence meaning. The analogy suggests that morally responsible actions require a competent moral agent to operate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  4
    Speaker's meaning.Owen Barfield - 1967 - San Rafael: Barfield Press.
    The semantic approach to history and the historical approach to the study of meaning -- Imagery in language and metaphor in poetry -- The psychology of inspiration and of imaginationn -- Subject and object in the history of meaning.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  20
    Toward a Speaker Meaning Theory of Moral Responsibility.Michael S. McKenna - 2000 - In A. van den Beld (ed.), Moral Responsibility and Ontology. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 247--258.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. The Speaker Authority Problem for Context-Sensitivity.Karen S. Lewis - 2020 - Erkenntnis 85 (6):1527-1555.
    Context-sensitivity raises a metasemantic question: what determines the value of a context-sensitive expression in context? Taking gradable adjectives as a case study, this paper argues against various forms of intentionalist metasemantics, i.e. that speaker intentions determine values for context-sensitive expressions in context, including the coordination account recently defended by King :219–237, 2014a; in: Burgess, Sherman Metasemantics: New essays on the foundations of meaning, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 97–118, 2014b). The paper argues that all intentionalist accounts face the speaker (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  9
    The Epistemology of Speaker Meaning.S. E. BoËr - 1975 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 53:204.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. From Signaling and Expression to Conversation and Fiction.Mitchell S. Green - 2019 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 96 (3):295-315.
    This essay ties together some main strands of the author’s research spanning the last quarter-century. Because of its broad scope and space limitations, he prescinds from detailed arguments and instead intuitively motivates the general points which are supported more fully in other publications to which he provides references. After an initial delineation of several distinct notions of meaning, the author considers such a notion deriving from the evolutionary biology of communication that he terms ‘organic meaning’, and places it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  50
    Speaker's Meaning[REVIEW]M. R. C. - 1968 - Review of Metaphysics 21 (3):548-548.
    Barfield considers the light the studies of history, language, and literature shed upon each other. He focuses his attention on the development of a theory of the emergence of individual consciousness. Barfield disputes some prevalent ramifications of evolutionist theories which hold that in language, literature, and history, a period of "active subjectivity" preceded one of "passive subjectivity." This would mean, according to Barfield, that in language, literal meaning preceded figurative meaning, just as imagination was prior to inspiration in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    How Speakers Orient to the Notable Absence of Talk: A Conversation Analytic Perspective on Silence in Psychodynamic Therapy.A. S. L. Knol, Tom Koole, Mattias Desmet, Stijn Vanheule & Mike Huiskes - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Silence has gained a prominent role in the field of psychotherapy because of its potential to facilitate a plethora of therapeutically beneficial processes within patients’ inner dynamics. This study examined the phenomenon from a conversation analytical perspective in order to investigate how silence emerges as an interactional accomplishment and how it attains interactional meaning by the speakers’ adjacent turns. We restricted our attention to one particular sequential context in which a patient’s turn comes to a point of possible completion (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  29
    What does it mean to predict one's own utterances?Antje S. Meyer & Peter Hagoort - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4):367 - 368.
    Many authors have recently highlighted the importance of prediction for language comprehension. Pickering & Garrod (P&G) are the first to propose a central role for prediction in language production. This is an intriguing idea, but it is not clear what it means for speakers to predict their own utterances, and how prediction during production can be empirically distinguished from production proper.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  18
    Again, Theory: On Speaker's Meaning, Linguistic Meaning, and the Meaning of a Text.George M. Wilson - 1992 - Critical Inquiry 19 (1):164-185.
  16.  16
    Αληθινοσ in amphis, fr. 26 and other late classical and early hellenistic authors.S. Douglas Olson - 2018 - Classical Quarterly 68 (2):712-714.
    LSJ s.v. A defines ἀληθινός as meaning ‘truthful, trusty’ of persons and ‘true, genuine’ of objects, and offers Amphis, fr. 26 as an example of the second sense:ὅστις ἀγοράζων ὄψον ἐξὸν ἀπολαύειν ἰχθύων ἀληθινῶνῥαφανῖδας ἐπιθυμεῖ πρίασθαι, μαίνεταιAnyone who, when shopping for dainties …wants to purchase radishes, when he has a chanceto enjoy alêthinoi fish, is crazy.The context of the fragment is unknown. But the speaker is patently drawing a contrast not between ‘real fish’ and something that resembles fish, as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Speaker’s reference, stipulation, and a dilemma for conceptual engineers.Max Deutsch - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (12):3935-3957.
    Advocates of conceptual engineering as a method of philosophy face a dilemma: either they are ignorant of how conceptual engineering can be implemented, or else it is trivial to implement but of very little value, representing no new or especially fruitful method of philosophizing. Two key distinctions frame this dilemma and explain its two horns. First, the distinction between speaker’s meaning and reference and semantic meaning and reference reveals a severe implementation problem for one construal of conceptual (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  18.  20
    Self Expressions: Mind, Morals, and the Meaning of Life.P. S. Greenspan & Owen Flanagan - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):128.
    Owen Flanagan is a highly prolific writer and speaker whose work brings together results of research in several empirical disciplines overlapping with philosophy, particularly neuroscience and other areas of psychology. This book of thirteen essays, most of them revisions of work published elsewhere, exhibits both his intellectual and his stylistic range. Many of the essays are light and chatty, others analytical and slower-going.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  19. After the storm : the vulnerability and resilience of locally owned business.Susan S. Kuo & Benjamin Means - 2013 - In Martha Fineman & Anna Grear (eds.), Vulnerability: reflections on a new ethical foundation for law and politics. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  44
    I Nomi Degli Dei: A Reconsideration of Agamben’s Oath Complex.Robert S. Leib - 2020 - Law and Critique 31 (1):73-92.
    This essay offers an exegesis and critique of the moment of community formation in Agamben’s Homo Sacer Project. In The Sacrament of Language, Agamben searches for the site of a non-sovereign community founded upon the oath [horkos, sacramentum]: an ancient institution of language that produces and guarantees the connection between speech and the order of things by calling the god as a witness to the speaker’s fidelity. I argue that Agamben’s account ultimately falls short of subverting sovereignty, however, because (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Davidson on first-person authority.P. M. S. Hacker - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (188):285-304.
    Davidson’s explanation of first‐person authority in utterance of sentences of the form ‘I V that p’ derives first‐person authority from the requirements of interpretation of speech. His account is committed to the view that utterance sentences are truth‐bearers, that believing that p is a matter of holding true an utterance sentence, and that a speaker’s knowledge of what he means gives him knowledge of what belief he expresses by his utterance. These claims are here faulted. His explanation of first‐person (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  22.  16
    Crafting marks into meanings.Joseph S. Catalano - 1996 - Philosophy and Literature 20 (1):47-60.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Crafting Marks Into MeaningsJoseph S. CatalanoIn his fascinating book about the Mayan Code, Michael D. Coe writes, “I challenge any native English speaker to avoid thinking of the word ‘twelve’ when looking at ‘12,’ or an Italian to avoid the utterance ‘dodici’ when going through the same performance.” 1 I accept the challenge, and claim that I have done just that. What shall the reply be—“I should not have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  69
    The epistemology of speaker-meaning.Steven E. Boër & George S. Pappas - 1975 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 53 (3):204 – 219.
  24. Conceptual precursors to language.Elizabeth S. Spelke & Susan J. Hespos - unknown
    Because human languages vary in sound and meaning, children must learn which distinctions their language uses. For speech perception, this learning is selective: initially infants are sensitive to most acoustic distinctions used in any language1–3, and this sensitivity reflects basic properties of the auditory system rather than mechanisms specific to language4–7; however, infants’ sensitivity to non-native sound distinctions declines over the course of the first year8. Here we ask whether a similar process governs learning of word meanings. We investigated (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25.  76
    The Spectra of Soundless Voices and Audible Thoughts: Towards an Integrative Model of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations and Thought Insertion.Clara S. Humpston & Matthew R. Broome - 2016 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 (3):611-629.
    Patients with psychotic disorders experience a range of reality distortions. These often include auditory-verbal hallucinations, and thought insertion to a lesser degree; however, their mechanisms and relationships between each other remain largely elusive. Here we attempt to establish a integrative model drawing from the phenomenology of both AVHs and TI and argue that they in fact can be seen as ‘spectra’ of experiences with varying degrees of agency and ownership, with ‘silent and internal own thoughts’ on one extreme and ‘fully (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26. Of knowledge and knowing that someone is in pain.P. M. S. Hacker - 2005 - In Alois Pichler & Simo Saatela (eds.), Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and His Works. The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen.
    1. First person authority: the received explanation Over a wide range of psychological attributes, a mature speaker seems to enjoy a defeasible form of authority on how things are with him. The received explanation of this is epistemic, and rests upon a cognitive assumption. The speaker’s word is a authoritative because when things are thus-and-so with him, then normally he knows that they are. This is held to be because the speaker has direct and privileged access to the contents (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  86
    Interrogatives, imperatives, truth, falsity and lies.Henry S. Leonard - 1959 - Philosophy of Science 26 (3):172-186.
    This paper aims to establish three major theses: (1) Not only declarative sentences, but also interrogatives and imperatives, may be classified as true or as false. (2) Declarative, imperative, and interrogative utterances may also be classified as honest or as dishonest. (3) Whether an utterance is honest or dishonest is logically independent of whether it is true or is false. The establishment of the above theses follows upon the adoption of a principle for identifying what is meant by any sentence, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  28.  30
    Speech and Phenomena. And Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of Signs. [REVIEW]R. S. - 1973 - Review of Metaphysics 27 (1):123-124.
    David Allison here translates Derrida’s booklet, La voix et le phénomène and two essays, "La forme et le vouloir-dire" and "La différance". It is a good translation, readable and accurate, even though once or twice he seems reluctant to move fully into English idiom: why not, for instance, render "la vive voix" as "speaking out loud" instead of "living vocal medium"? Derrida claims Husserl is caught in the classical metaphysics of presence, an entrapment shown by his belief that the (...) of speech can be isolated from reference or indication, at least in the privileged case of phenomenological reflection: for then we do not speak to another, only to ourselves, and no indication is needed to turn our minds towards what is discussed. In this privileged discourse we enjoy a sheer presence of meaning, with no indication or reference to anything absent, and no need for the sounding voice either. But Derrida claims that when we think we can never do without indication and sound—at least the imagined sound of inner speech—and so even the privileged presence of phenomenological reflection must involve some absences. The speaker himself is constituted only with the signs and sensuosity of speech, not by a sheer view of presence. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  16
    Speech and Phenomena. And Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of Signs. [REVIEW]S. R. - 1973 - Review of Metaphysics 27 (1):123-124.
    David Allison here translates Derrida’s booklet, La voix et le phénomène and two essays, "La forme et le vouloir-dire" and "La différance". It is a good translation, readable and accurate, even though once or twice he seems reluctant to move fully into English idiom: why not, for instance, render "la vive voix" as "speaking out loud" instead of "living vocal medium"? Derrida claims Husserl is caught in the classical metaphysics of presence, an entrapment shown by his belief that the (...) of speech can be isolated from reference or indication, at least in the privileged case of phenomenological reflection: for then we do not speak to another, only to ourselves, and no indication is needed to turn our minds towards what is discussed. In this privileged discourse we enjoy a sheer presence of meaning, with no indication or reference to anything absent, and no need for the sounding voice either. But Derrida claims that when we think we can never do without indication and sound—at least the imagined sound of inner speech—and so even the privileged presence of phenomenological reflection must involve some absences. The speaker himself is constituted only with the signs and sensuosity of speech, not by a sheer view of presence. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  16
    Speech Acts.Mitchell S. Green - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 58–66.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Speech Acts, Acts of Speech, and Performatives Acts and Their Contents Speech Acts, What is Said, and Speaker Meaning Misfires, Abuses, and How Saying Makes It So Illocutions, Perlocutions, and Implicature Direct and Indirect Speech Acts References Further reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  74
    Using Variability to Guide Dimensional Weighting: Associative Mechanisms in Early Word Learning.Keith S. Apfelbaum & Bob McMurray - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (6):1105-1138.
    At 14 months, children appear to struggle to apply their fairly well-developed speech perception abilities to learning similar sounding words (e.g., bih/dih; Stager & Werker, 1997). However, variability in nonphonetic aspects of the training stimuli seems to aid word learning at this age. Extant theories of early word learning cannot account for this benefit of variability. We offer a simple explanation for this range of effects based on associative learning. Simulations suggest that if infants encode both noncontrastive information (e.g., cues (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  12
    Modern Poetry and the Idea of Language. [REVIEW]S. R. - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):745-747.
    This book is of considerable interest to philosophers. Bruns studies poetry from two perspectives: as hermetic and as orphic. In the first, a poem is considered as a self-sufficient whole, admirable and analyzable in itself, the world-reference of its words suspended; in the second, a poem is considered much as Heidegger takes the work of poets, as establishing a world in which meaning can be found, as instituting a condition in which words and being are indistinguishable. Of the book’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  51
    Rules Versus Statistics: Insights From a Highly Inflected Language.Jelena Mirković, Mark S. Seidenberg & Marc F. Joanisse - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (4):638-681.
    Inflectional morphology has been taken as a paradigmatic example of rule-governed grammatical knowledge (Pinker, 1999). The plausibility of this claim may be related to the fact that it is mainly based on studies of English, which has a very simple inflectional system. We examined the representation of inflectional morphology in Serbian, which encodes number, gender, and case for nouns. Linguists standardly characterize this system as a complex set of rules, with disagreements about their exact form. We present analyses of a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  15
    When your heart is in your mouth: the effect of second language use on negative emotions.Alexandra S. Dylman & Anna Bjärtå - 2019 - Cognition and Emotion 33 (6):1284-1290.
    ABSTRACTResearch on bilingualism and emotions has shown stronger emotional responses in the native language compared to a foreign language. We investigated the potential of purposeful second language use as a means of decreasing the experience of psychological distress. Native Swedish speakers read and answered questions about negative and neutral texts in their L1 and their L2 and were asked to rate their level of distress before or after the questions. The texts and associated questions were either written in the same, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Lost in Translation? The Upaniṣadic Story about “Da” and Interpretational Issues in Analytic Philosophy.Don Dcruz, Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay & Venkata Raghavan - 2015 - Apa Newsletter on Asian and Asian-American Philosophers and Philosophies 2 (14):15-18.
    In the Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad, one of the principal Upaniṣads, we find a venerable and famous story where the god Prajāpati separately instructs three groups of people (gods, humans, and demons) simply by uttering the syllable “Da.” In this paper, our concern is not with ethics but theories of meaning and interpretation: How can all divergent interpretations of a single expression be correct, and, indeed, endorsed by the speaker? As an exercise in cross-cultural philosophical reflection, we consider some of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  38
    The Semantics of Prosody: Acoustic and Perceptual Evidence of Prosodic Correlates to Word Meaning.Lynne C. Nygaard, Debora S. Herold & Laura L. Namy - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (1):127-146.
    This investigation examined whether speakers produce reliable prosodic correlates to meaning across semantic domains and whether listeners use these cues to derive word meaning from novel words. Speakers were asked to produce phrases in infant‐directed speech in which novel words were used to convey one of two meanings from a set of antonym pairs (e.g., big/small). Acoustic analyses revealed that some acoustic features were correlated with overall valence of the meaning. However, each word meaning also displayed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  37. Rule-Following Scepticism and the Individuation of Speaker's Meaning.Isaac Nevo - 1988 - Dissertation, University of California, Santa Barbara
    In this work I bring a conception of language and meaning as a shared institution to bear upon rule-following scepticism, i.e., upon the sceptical problem concerning the semantic determinacy of expressions involving infinite or indefinitely large and open extensions. Such scepticism proceeds from the observation that the extensions of expressions of this kind are not uniquely determined by epistemically accessible facts, to conclude that the expressions in question are indeterminate in point of extension, and that their meaning must (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  5
    Vowel acoustics of Nungon child-directed speech, adult dyadic conversation, and foreigner-directed monologues.Hannah S. Sarvasy, Weicong Li, Jaydene Elvin & Paola Escudero - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    In many communities around the world, speech to infants and small children has increased mean pitch, increased pitch range, increased vowel duration, and vowel hyper-articulation when compared to speech directed to adults. Some of these IDS and CDS features are also attested in foreigner-directed speech, which has been studied for a smaller range of languages, generally major national languages, spoken by millions of people. We examined vowel acoustics in CDS, conversational ADS, and monologues directed to a foreigner in the Towet (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  5
    Taking a Stance: An Account for Persons and Institutions.Jeffrey S. Helmreich - 2019 - In Alessandro Capone, Marco Carapezza & Franco Lo Piparo (eds.), Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy: Part 2 Theories and Applications. Springer Verlag. pp. 513-534.
    Certain commissive speech acts, such as “I forgive you,” “I’m in favor,” “Thank you” and “Sorry,” are often characterized as “expressives,” utterances whose primary function is to express a psychological state. In contrast, I argue here that such utterances are stance-takings: speech acts that commit the speaker to behave towards others in light of a normative position she accepts. I argue that stance-taking, as developed here, makes better sense of these utterances than the standard expressivist account, in terms of their (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Speaker's reference, semantic reference, sneaky reference.Eliot Michaelson - 2022 - Mind and Language 37 (5):856-875.
    According to what is perhaps the dominant picture of reference, what a referential term refers to in a context is determined by what the speaker intends for her audience to identify as the referent. I argue that this sort of broadly Gricean view entails, counterintuitively, that it is impossible to knowingly use referential terms in ways that one expects or intends to be misunderstood. Then I sketch an alternative which can better account for such opaque uses of language, or what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  69
    Implicature. [REVIEW]Mitchell S. Green - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1):241-244.
    I recall reading a critical notice of Grices’ Studies in the Way of Words, in which the author remarked that while Grice’s analysis of speaker meaning is the subject of considerable controversy, Grice’s account of conversational implicature is, “…money in the philosophical bank.” This assessment was optimistic at best: Grice’s remarks on implicature offer a program not a theory, and in relation to the amount of discussion it has received in philosophy and allied disciplines such as linguistics and psycholinguistics, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  20
    Shy individuals’ interpretations of counterfactual verbal irony.Tracy A. Mewhort-Buist & Elizabeth S. Nilsen - 2017 - Metaphor and Symbol 32 (4):262-275.
    Counterfactual verbal irony, an evaluative form of figurative language wherein a speaker’s intended meaning is opposite to the literal meaning of his or her words, is used to serve many social goals. Despite recent calls for theoretical accounts to include the factors that influence irony interpretation, few studies have examined the individual differences that may impact verbal irony interpretation. The present study examined whether adults with elevated shyness would generate more negative interpretations of ironic statements. University students (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  22
    Playing with fire: effects of negative mood induction and working memory on vocabulary acquisition.Zachary F. Miller, Jessica K. Fox, Jason S. Moser & Aline Godfroid - 2017 - Cognition and Emotion 32 (5):1105-1113.
    ABSTRACTWe investigated the impact of emotions on learning vocabulary in an unfamiliar language to better understand affective influences in foreign language acquisition. Seventy native English speakers learned new vocabulary in either a negative or a neutral emotional state. Participants also completed two sets of working memory tasks to examine the potential mediating role of working memory. Results revealed that participants exposed to negative stimuli exhibited difficulty in retrieving and correctly pairing English words with Indonesian words, as reflected in a lower (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  29
    Brain Computer Interfaces and Communication Disabilities: Ethical, Legal, and Social Aspects of Decoding Speech From the Brain.Jennifer A. Chandler, Kiah I. Van der Loos, Susan Boehnke, Jonas S. Beaudry, Daniel Z. Buchman & Judy Illes - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16:841035.
    A brain-computer interface technology that can decode the neural signals associated with attempted but unarticulated speech could offer a future efficient means of communication for people with severe motor impairments. Recent demonstrations have validated this approach. Here we assume that it will be possible in future to decode imagined (i.e., attempted but unarticulated) speech in people with severe motor impairments, and we consider the characteristics that could maximize the social utility of a BCI for communication. As a social interaction, communication (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  10
    What Is Experimental Research in the Philosophy of Language and Epistemology?Raisa E. Barash & Petr S. Kusliy - 2023 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 60 (2):94-113.
    Philosophy is an abstract theoretical discipline. However, a new trend that develops experimental methods in philosophical research has recently been gaining popularity extending to the fields of philosophical research that have not seen experimental methods earlier. This article addresses the question of whether it is possible to investigate philosophical questions with empirical methods. Two areas of research are considered – philosophy of language and semantics and epistemology. In these subfields of philosophy, the application of experimental methods has recently lead to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    Quantitatively characterizing reflexive responses to pitch perturbations.Elaine Kearney, Alfonso Nieto-Castañón, Riccardo Falsini, Ayoub Daliri, Elizabeth S. Heller Murray, Dante J. Smith & Frank H. Guenther - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16:929687.
    BackgroundReflexive pitch perturbation experiments are commonly used to investigate the neural mechanisms underlying vocal motor control. In these experiments, the fundamental frequency–the acoustic correlate of pitch–of a speech signal is shifted unexpectedly and played back to the speaker via headphones in near real-time. In response to the shift, speakers increase or decrease their fundamental frequency in the direction opposing the shift so that their perceived pitch is closer to what they intended. The goal of the current work is to develop (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  55
    The Interplay Between the Speaker's and the Hearer's Perspective.Petra Hendriks, Helen Hoop & Henriëtte Swart - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (1):1-5.
    The neutralization of contrasts in form or meaning that is sometimes observed in language production and comprehension is at odds with the classical view that language is a systematic one-to-one pairing of forms and meanings. This special issue is concerned with patterns of forms and meanings in language. The papers in this special issue arose from a series of workshops that were organized to explore variants of bidirectional Optimality Theory and Game Theory as models of the interplay between the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  46
    The Interplay Between the Speaker’s and the Hearer’s Perspective.Petra Hendriks, Helen de Hoop & Henriëtte de Swart - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (1):1-5.
    The neutralization of contrasts in form or meaning that is sometimes observed in language production and comprehension is at odds with the classical view that language is a systematic one-to-one pairing of forms and meanings. This special issue is concerned with patterns of forms and meanings in language. The papers in this special issue arose from a series of workshops that were organized to explore variants of bidirectional Optimality Theory and Game Theory as models of the interplay between the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  58
    Book Review Section 4. [REVIEW]Timothy Boggs, Charles B. Keely, John P. Sikula, Elliott S. M. Gatner, Dwight W. Allen, Frederick H. Stutz, Dan Landis, David A. Potter, Joseph M. Scandura, Larry S. Bowen, Jay M. Smith, Gerald Kulm, Barak Rosenshine, Lawrence M. Knolle, Jacquelin A. Stitt, Joan K. Smith, Nicholas F. Rayder, B. R. Bugelski, Karen F. Swoope, Joan Duff Kise, Robert S. Means, Gladys H. Means, Stanley H. Rude & James E. Ysseldyke - 1974 - Educational Studies: A Jrnl of the American Educ. Studies Assoc 5 (1):78-97.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  29
    Book Review Section 4. [REVIEW]Timothy Boggs, Charles B. Keely, John P. Sikula, Elliott S. M. Gatner, Dwight W. Allen, Frederick H. Stutz, Dan Landis, David A. Potter, Joseph M. Scandura, Larry S. Bowen, Jay M. Smith, Gerald Kulm, Barak Rosenshine, Lawrence M. Knolle, Jacquelin A. Stitt, Joan K. Smith, Nicholas F. Rayder, B. R. Bugelski, Karen F. Swoope, Joan Duff Kise, Robert S. Means, Gladys H. Means, Stanley H. Rude & James E. Ysseldyke - 1974 - Educational Studies: A Jrnl of the American Educ. Studies Assoc 5 (1&2):78-97.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000