Results for 'Singular Action Sentences'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Individual and Collective Action: Reply to Blomberg.Kirk Ludwig - 2019 - Journal of Social Ontology 5 (1):125-146.
    Olle Blomberg challenges three claims in my book From Individual to Plural Agency (Ludwig, Kirk (2016): From Individual to Plural Agency: Collective Action 1. Vols. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.). The first is that there are no collective actions in the sense in which there are individual actions. The second is that singular action sentences entail that there is no more than one agent of the event expressed by the action verb in the way required (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  21
    From Plural to Institutional Agency: Collective Action II.Kirk Ludwig - 2017 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Kirk Ludwig presents a philosophical account of institutional action, such as action by corporations and nation states, arguing that it can be understood exhaustively in terms of the agency of individuals and concepts constructed out of materials that are already at play in our understanding of individual action. He thus argues for a strong form of methodological individualism. The book provides a new account of the logical form of grammatically singular group action sentences (e.g. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3. The Ontology of Collective Action.Kirk Ludwig - 2014 - In Sara Chant Frank Hindriks & Gerhard Preyer (eds.), From Individual to Collective Intentionality: New Essays. Oxford University Press.
    What is the ontology of collective action? I have in mind three connected questions. 1. Do the truth conditions of action sentences about groups require there to be group agents over and above individual agents? 2. Is there a difference, in this connection, between action sentences about informal groups that use plural noun phrases, such as ‘We pushed the car’ and ‘The women left the party early’, and action sentences about formal or institutional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4. Plural Action Sentences and Logical Form: Reply to Himmelreich.Kirk Ludwig - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (4):800-806.
    This paper replies to Himmelreich's ‘The Paraphrase Argument Against Collective Actions’ [2017], which presents three putative counterexamples to the multiple agents analysis of plural action sentences. The paper shows that the argument from the first example, the discursive dilemma, fails because it relies crucially on a simplification of the target analysis, and that the others don't bear on the question because they turn out on examination to be about individual rather than group action sentences.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  14
    The Action–Sentence Compatibility Effect: It's All in the Timing.Kristin L. Borreggine & Michael P. Kaschak - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (6):1097-1112.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  6. From Simple to Composite Agency: On Kirk Ludwig’s From Individual to Plural Agency.Olle Blomberg - 2019 - Journal of Social Ontology 5 (1):101-124.
    According to Kirk Ludwig, only primitive actions are actions in a primary and non-derivative sense of the term ‘action’. Ludwig takes this to imply that the notion of collective action is a façon de parler – useful perhaps, but secondary and derivative. I argue that, on the contrary, collective actions are actions in the primary and non-derivative sense. First, this is because some primitive actions are collective actions. Secondly, individual and collective composites of primitive actions are also actions (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. The logical form of action sentences.Donald Davidson - 1967 - In Nicholas Rescher (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action. University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 81--95.
  8. Action-Sentence Compatibility: The Role of Action Effects and Timing.Christiane Diefenbach, Martina Rieger, Cristina Massen & Wolfgang Prinz - 2014 - In Ezequiel Morsella & T. Andrew Poehlman (eds.), Consciousness and action control. Lausanne, Switzerland: Frontiers Media SA.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  86
    Action sentences.David Widerker - 1988 - Erkenntnis 28 (2):269 - 291.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  28
    Extensionality and singular causal sentences.Dale V. Gottlieb & Lawrence H. Davis - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 25 (1):69 - 72.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  45
    Davidson on singular causal sentences.David Widerker - 1985 - Erkenntnis 23 (3):223 - 242.
  12.  18
    On Logical Form of Action Sentences.Chinmoy Goswami - 1992 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 19 (3):187.
    The purpose of this paper is to show that the logical form of action sentences are dependent upon the concept of 'agent' that one takes. A thing type of agent leads to the extensional form while a thinking type of agent leads to intentional form of action sentences. Consequently, it is important to note the locus of the describer who himself is also an agent. If the describer is someone other than theagent, the ascription of (...) is based on a tacit counterfactual. The agent could have done otherwise, implying the agent to be a being-of-the-world, who acts on the things of the world to bring about a change which could not have occurred otherwise. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. 'Could have done otherwise', action sentences and anaphora.Helen Steward - 2006 - Analysis 66 (2):95–101.
    This paper argues that there are a number of different things that could be meant by the claim that a given agent 'could have done otherwise', because there are multiple ways of disambiguating the various anaphoric devices which are contained in the phrase. It goes on to suggest that on at least one of these disambiguations, the claim that a Frankfurtian agent could have done otherwise might be defensible, even given the presence of a counterfactual intervener who will ensure that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  45
    Ascriptions, descriptions, and action sentences.John W. Yolton - 1956 - Ethics 67 (4):307-310.
  15. Adverbials in action sentences.E. J. Borowski - 1974 - Synthese 28 (3-4):483 - 512.
  16. The logical form of negative action sentences.Jonathan D. Payton - 2016 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 46 (6):855-876.
    It is typically assumed that actions are events, but there is a growing consensus that negative actions, like omissions and refrainments, are not events, but absences thereof. If so, then we must either deny the obvious, that we can exercise our agency by omitting and refrainment, or give up on event-based theories of agency. I trace the consensus to the assumption that negative action sentences are negative-existentials, and argue that this is false. The best analysis of negative (...) sentences treats them as quantifying over omissions and refrainments, conceived of as events. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  78
    Fodor on Davidson on action sentences.Edward Wierenga - 1980 - Synthese 44 (3):347 - 359.
  18. The logical structure of action sentences (2 analytical exercises). 2.P. Kolar & V. Svoboda - 1992 - Filosoficky Casopis 40 (4):661-671.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The logical structure of action sentences 2 analytical exercises-conclusion.P. Kolar & V. Svoboda - 1992 - Filosoficky Casopis 40 (5):887-905.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  4
    The logical form of action sentences and the Anscombe thesis.David Pineda - 1993 - Enrahonar: Quaderns de Filosofía 21:51.
  21.  10
    Spatial and Motor Aspects in the “Action-Sentence Compatibility Effect”.Alberto Greco - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The Action-sentence Compatibility Effect is often taken as supporting the fundamental role of the motor system in understanding sentences that describe actions. This effect would be related to an internal “simulation,” i.e., the reactivation of past perceptual and motor experiences. However, it is not easy to establish whether this simulation predominantly involves spatial imagery or motor anticipation. In the classical ACE experiments, where a real motor response is required, the direction and motor representations are mixed. In order to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Socrates est and there-is-no-such-thing-as-pegasus-logic of singular existence sentences according to Aquinas, Thomas and Quine, w, vanorman.H. Weidemann - 1979 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 86 (1):42-59.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  22
    Time-Course of Motor Involvement in Literal and Metaphoric Action Sentence Processing: A TMS Study.Megan Reilly, Olivia Howerton & Rutvik H. Desai - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  38
    ""Why" kill" does not mean" cause to die": the semantics of action sentences.Anna Wierzbicka - 1975 - Foundations of Language 13 (4):491-528.
  25.  55
    A Problem in the Logic of Action Sentences.Linda B. Cornett - 1975 - New Scholasticism 49 (4):467-472.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  23
    Grounding Causalist Assumptions in the Grammar of Action Sentences.Henle Lauer - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:143-152.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  13
    Grounding Causalist Assumptions in the Grammar of Action Sentences.Henle Lauer - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:143-152.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  10
    Grounding Causalist Assumptions in the Grammar of Action Sentences.Henle Lauer - 1991 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33:143-152.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  21
    Comprehending Sentences With the Body: Action Compatibility in British Sign Language?David Vinson, Pamela Perniss, Neil Fox & Gabriella Vigliocco - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S6):1377-1404.
    Previous studies show that reading sentences about actions leads to specific motor activity associated with actually performing those actions. We investigate how sign language input may modulate motor activation, using British Sign Language sentences, some of which explicitly encode direction of motion, versus written English, where motion is only implied. We find no evidence of action simulation in BSL comprehension, but we find effects of action simulation in comprehension of written English sentences by deaf native (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  34
    Action verbs are processed differently in metaphorical and literal sentences depending on the semantic match of visual primes.Melissa Troyer, Lauren B. Curley, Luke E. Miller, Ayse P. Saygin & Benjamin K. Bergen - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  31. Degrees of truthlikeness: From singular sentences to generalisations.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):371-376.
  32. Reasons explanations of actions: Causal, singular, and situational.Abraham S. Roth - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):839-874.
    Davidson held that the explanation of action in terms of reasons was a form of causal explanation. He challenged anti-causalists to identify a non-causal relation underlying reasons---explanation which could distinguish between merely having a reason and that reason being the one for which one acts. George Wilson attempts to meet Davidson’s challenge, but the relation he identifies can serve only in explanations of general facts, whereas reasons explanation is often of particular acts. This suggests that the relation underlying reasons (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  25
    Does listening to action-related sentences modulate the activity of the motor system? Replication of a combined TMS and behavioral study.Claudia Gianelli & Riccardo Dalla Volta - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  20
    Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism.Robert Brandom - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Robert B. Brandom is one of the most original philosophers of our day, whose book Making It Explicit covered and extended a vast range of topics in metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of language--the very core of analytic philosophy. This new work provides an approachable introduction to the complex system that Making It Explicit mapped out. A tour of the earlier book's large ideas and relevant details, Articulating Reasons offers an easy entry into two of the main themes of Brandom's work: (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   272 citations  
  35. Differences in action tendencies distinguish anger and sadness after comprehension of emotional sentences.Emily Mouilso, Authur M. Glenberg, D. A. Havas & Lisa M. Lindeman - 2007 - In McNamara D. S. & Trafton J. G. (eds.), Proceedings of the 29th Annual Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  43
    The essential grammar of action (and other) sentences.Gilbert Harman - 1981 - Philosophia 10 (3-4):209-215.
  37.  45
    Aristotle on the Existential Import of Singular Sentences.Michael V. Wedin - 1978 - Phronesis 23 (2):179-196.
  38. Singular Reference in Fictional Discourse?Manuel García-Carpintero - 2019 - Disputatio 11 (54):143-177.
    Singular terms used in fictions for fictional characters raise well-known philosophical issues, explored in depth in the literature. But philosophers typically assume that names already in use to refer to “moderatesized specimens of dry goods” cause no special problem when occurring in fictions, behaving there as they ordinarily do in straightforward assertions. In this paper I continue a debate with Stacie Friend, arguing against this for the exceptionalist view that names of real entities in fictional discourse don’t work there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  52
    Are Singular Causal Explanations Implicit Covering-Law Explanations?James Woodward - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):253 - 279.
    My focus in this essay is on those singular causal explanations which purport to explain the occurrence of some particular event by means of a claim of the following general sort The occurrence of event caused the occurrence of event.Examples include sentences like The short circuit caused the fire’ and The impact of the hammer caused the shattering of the glass,’ Many philosophers hold that there is a sharp distinction to be drawn between singular causal explanations and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. Actions and Events in Plural Discourse.Kirk Ludwig - 2017 - In Marija Jankovic & Kirk Ludwig (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Collective Intentionality. New York: Routledge. pp. 476-488.
    This chapter is concerned with plural discourse in the grammatical sense. The goal of the chapter is to urge the value of the event analysis of the matrix of action sentences in thinking about logical form in plural discourse about action. Among the claims advanced are that: -/- 1. The ambiguity between distributive and collective readings of plural action sentences is not lexical ambiguity, either in the noun phrase (NP) or in the verb phrase (VP), (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. Singular Propositions and Modal Logic.Christopher Menzel - 1993 - Philosophical Topics 21 (2):113-148.
    According to many actualists, propositions, singular propositions in particular, are structurally complex, that is, roughly, (i) they have, in some sense, an internal structure that corresponds rather directly to the syntactic structure of the sentences that express them, and (ii) the metaphysical components, or constituents, of that structure are the semantic values — the meanings — of the corresponding syntactic components of those sentences. Given that reference is "direct", i.e., that the meaning of a name is its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  42.  16
    Different time courses of integrative semantic processing for plural and singular nouns: implications for theories of sentence processing.Shelia M. Kennison - 2005 - Cognition 97 (3):269-294.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Fictional singular imaginings.Manuel Garcia-Carpintero - 2010 - In Robin Jeshion (ed.), New Essays on Singular Thought. Oxford University Press. pp. 273--299.
    In a series of papers, Robin Jeshion has forcefully criticized both Donnellan's and Evans’ claims on the contingent a priori, and she has developed an “acquaintanceless” account of singular thoughts as an alternative view. Jeshion claims that one can fully grasp a singular thought expressed by a sentence including a proper name, even if its reference has been descriptively fixed and one’s access to the referent is “mediated” by that description. But she still wants to reject “semantic instrumentalism”, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  44.  73
    Sentence-internal different as quantifier-internal anaphora.Adrian Brasoveanu - 2011 - Linguistics and Philosophy 34 (2):93-168.
    The paper proposes the first unified account of deictic/sentence-external and sentence-internal readings of singular different . The empirical motivation for such an account is provided by a cross-linguistic survey and an analysis of the differences in distribution and interpretation between singular different , plural different and same (singular or plural) in English. The main proposal is that distributive quantification temporarily makes available two discourse referents within its nuclear scope, the values of which are required by sentence-internal uses (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  45. Singular Terms, Predicates and the Spurious ‘Is’ of Identity.Danny Frederick - 2013 - Dialectica 67 (3):325-343.
    Contemporary orthodoxy affirms that singular terms cannot be predicates and that, therefore, ‘is’ is ambiguous as between predication and identity. Recent attempts to treat names as predicates do not challenge this orthodoxy. The orthodoxy was built into the structure of modern formal logic by Frege. It is defended by arguments which I show to be unsound. I provide a semantical account of atomic sentences which draws upon Mill's account of predication, connotation and denotation. I show that singular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    Manifestar a Dios en el ser y en el obrar: la creación como orden jerárquico en el Comentario a las Sentencias de Sto. Tomás de Aquino / The Manifestation of God in Being and in Action: Creation as Hierarchical Order in the Commentary on the Sentences of Thomas Aquinas.Álvaro Perpere Viñuales - 2014 - Revista Española de Filosofía Medieval 21:105.
    In the Commentary on the Sentences of Thomas Aquinas, creation is conceived as a “hierarchical order”. This idea, which he takes from Dionysius the Areopagite, is related to the concept of similitude used to explain the relation between God and his creation, and to the idea that he create d it to manifest his goodness. In this article I show the importance that this idea of hierarchical order has when it is applied to creation in this early work of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  50
    Non-singular reference: Some preliminaries.F. Jeffry Pelletier - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (4):451-465.
    One of the goals of a certain brand of philosopher has been to give an account of language and linguistic phenomena by means of showing how sentences are to be translated into a "logically perspicuous notation" (or an "ideal language"—to use passe terminology). The usual reason given by such philosophers for this activity is that such a notational system will somehow illustrate the "logical form" of these sentences. There are many candidates for this notational system: (almost) ordinary first-order (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  48.  35
    On the nature of hand-action representations evoked during written sentence comprehension.Daniel N. Bub & Michael E. J. Masson - 2010 - Cognition 116 (3):394-408.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49. Beyond Singular Propositions?Scott Soames - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (4):515 - 549.
    Propositional attitudes, like believing and asserting, are relations between agents and propositions. Agents are individuals who do the believing and asserting; propositions are things that are believed and asserted. Propositional attitude ascriptions are sentences that ascribe propositional attitudes to agents. For example, a propositional attitude ascription α believes, or asserts, that S is true iff the referent of a bears the relation of believing, or asserting, to the proposition expressed by s. The questions I will address have to do (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  50. Adverbs of Action and Logical Form.Kirk Ludwig - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Blackwell.
    This article discusses the logical form of action sentences with particular attention to the role of adverbial modification, reviewing and extending the event analysis of action sentences.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000