Results for 'Risk aversion of order one'

994 found
Order:
  1. Nondegenerate Intervals of No-Trade Prices for Risk Averse Traders.Gerd Weinrich - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (1):79-99.
    According to the local risk-neutrality theorem an agent who has the opportunity to invest in an uncertain asset does not buy it or sell it short iff its expected value is equal to its price, independently of the agent's attitude towards risk. Contrary to that it is shown that, in the context of expected utility theory with differentiable vNM utility function, but without the assumption of stochastic constant returns to scale, nondegenerate intervals of no-trade prices may exist. With (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  37
    Benchmark values for higher order coefficients of relative risk aversion.Michel Denuit & Béatrice Rey - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (1):81-94.
    The existing literature on savings, insurance, and portfolio choices under risk has revealed that quite often comparative statics results depend, among other things, upon the values of the coefficients of relative risk aversion and relative prudence. More specifically the benchmark values for these coefficients are, respectively, one and two. Recently, several papers investigated constraints on the higher degree extensions of the coefficients of relative risk aversion and of relative prudence. The present work provides a unified (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  34
    Risk aversion, prudence, and asset allocation: a review and some new developments.Michel M. Denuit & Louis Eeckhoudt - 2016 - Theory and Decision 80 (2):227-243.
    In this paper, we consider the composition of an optimal portfolio made of two dependent risky assets. The investor is first assumed to be a risk-averse expected utility maximizer, and we recover the existing conditions under which all these investors hold at least some percentage of their portfolio in one of the assets. Then, we assume that the decision maker is not only risk-averse, but also prudent and we obtain new minimum demand conditions as well as intuitively appealing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Distinguishing indeterminate belief from “risk-averse” preferences.Katie Steele - 2007 - Synthese 158 (2):189-205.
    I focus my discussion on the well-known Ellsberg paradox. I find good normative reasons for incorporating non-precise belief, as represented by sets of probabilities, in an Ellsberg decision model. This amounts to forgoing the completeness axiom of expected utility theory. Provided that probability sets are interpreted as genuinely indeterminate belief, such a model can moreover make the “Ellsberg choices” rationally permissible. Without some further element to the story, however, the model does not explain how an agent may come to have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  18
    Second Guessing.Anonymous One - 2014 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 4 (1):9-11.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Second GuessingAnonymous OneThis is difficult for me to write because I have tremendous respect for every doctor that has been involved in my son’s care. I firmly believe that they chose and administered the highest level of care that they assessed as appropriate; that they cared for him both personally and professionally as if he were their own child; and that he was in the care of acknowledged giants (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Risk aversion and elite‐group ignorance.David Kinney & Liam Kofi Bright - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (1):35-57.
    Critical race theorists and standpoint epistemologists argue that agents who are members of dominant social groups are often in a state of ignorance about the extent of their social dominance, where this ignorance is explained by these agents' membership in a socially dominant group (e.g., Mills 2007). To illustrate this claim bluntly, it is argued: 1) that many white men do not know the extent of their social dominance, 2) that they remain ignorant as to the extent of their dominant (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  7.  15
    Risk aversion and rational choice theory do not adequately capture complexities of medical decision-making.Zeljka Buturovic - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (11):761-762.
    In his paper, ‘Patients, doctors and risk attitudes’, Makins argues that doctors, when choosing a treatment for their patient, need to follow their risk profile.1 He presents a pair of fictitious diseases facing a patient who either has ‘exemplitis’, which requires no treatment or ‘caseopathy’, which is severe and disabling and for which there is a treatment with unpleasant side effects. The doctor needs to decide whether the patient should pursue the unpleasant treatment, just in case he has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  85
    Decreasing higher-order absolute risk aversion and higher-degree stochastic dominance.Michel Denuit & Liqun Liu - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (2):287-295.
    Fishburn and Vickson showed that, when applied to random alternatives with an equal mean, 3rd-degree and decreasing absolute risk aversion stochastic dominances represent equivalent rules. The present paper generalizes this result to higher degrees. Specifically, higher-degree stochastic dominance rules and common preference by all decision makers with decreasing higher-order absolute risk aversion are shown to coincide under appropriate constraints on the respective moments of the random variables to be compared.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Can we turn people into pain pumps?: On the Rationality of Future Bias and Strong Risk Aversion.David Braddon-Mitchell, Andrew J. Latham & Kristie Miller - 2023 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 1:1-32.
    Future-bias is the preference, all else being equal, for negatively valenced events be located in the past rather than the future, and positively valenced ones to be located in the future rather than the past. Strong risk aversion is the preference to pay some cost to mitigate the badness of the worst outcome. People who are both strongly risk averse and future-biased can face a series of choices that will guarantee them more pain, for no compensating benefit: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Can risk aversion survive the long run?Hayden Wilkinson - 2022 - Philosophical Quarterly 73 (2):625-647.
    Can it be rational to be risk-averse? It seems plausible that the answer is yes—that normative decision theory should accommodate risk aversion. But there is a seemingly compelling class of arguments against our most promising methods of doing so. These long-run arguments point out that, in practice, each decision an agent makes is just one in a very long sequence of such decisions. Given this form of dynamic choice situation, and the (Strong) Law of Large Numbers, they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  8
    Influence of Loss Aversion and Income Effect on Consumer Food Choice for Food Safety and Quality Labels.Wenjing Nie, Huimin Bo, Jing Liu & Taiping Li - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Food safety and food quality are two closely related aspects of the food management system. The difference between the two is that one keeps consumers safe while the other keeps consumers satisfied. This study examined the differences in how consumers value food safety and food quality with a focus on the influence of loss aversion on one’s psychological level and of income effect on one’s socio-demographic level. Our findings indicate that loss aversion and income effect significantly influence the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  35
    Mixed risk aversion and preference for risk disaggregation: a story of moments. [REVIEW]Patrick Roger - 2011 - Theory and Decision 70 (1):27-44.
    In a recent article entitled “Putting Risk in its Proper Place,” Eeckhoudt and Schlesinger (2006) established a theorem linking the sign of the n-th derivative of an agent’s utility function to her preferences among pairs of simple lotteries. We characterize these lotteries and show that, in a given pair, they only differ by their moments of order greater than or equal to n. When the n-th derivative of the utility function is positive (negative) and n is odd (even), (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. Risk aversion in expected intertemporal discounted utilities bandit problems.Jean-Philippe Chancelier, Michel De Lara & André de Palma - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (4):433-440.
    We consider a situation where an individual is facing an uncertain situation, but may costly alter his knowledge of the uncertainties. We study in this context how risk aversion may modify the individual search behavior. We consider a one-armed bandit problem (where one arm is safe and the other is risky) and study how the agent risk aversion can change the sequence of arms selected. The main result is that when the utility function is more concave, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. What Is Risk Aversion?H. Orii Stefansson & Richard Bradley - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (1):77-102.
    According to the orthodox treatment of risk preferences in decision theory, they are to be explained in terms of the agent's desires about concrete outcomes. The orthodoxy has been criticised both for conflating two types of attitudes and for committing agents to attitudes that do not seem rationally required. To avoid these problems, it has been suggested that an agent's attitudes to risk should be captured by a risk function that is independent of her utility and probability (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  15.  8
    Risk aversion in expected intertemporal discounted utilities bandit problems.Jean-Philippe Chancelier, Michel Lara & André Palma - 2009 - Theory and Decision 67 (4):433-440.
    We consider a situation where an individual is facing an uncertain situation, but may costly alter his knowledge of the uncertainties. We study in this context how risk aversion may modify the individual search behavior. We consider a one-armed bandit problem (where one arm is safe and the other is risky) and study how the agent risk aversion can change the sequence of arms selected. The main result is that when the utility function is more concave, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  30
    The Effects of Beliefs Versus Risk Attitude on Bargaining Outcomes.David L. Dickinson - 2009 - Theory and Decision 66 (1):69-101.
    In bargaining environments with uncertain disagreement or “impasse” outcomes (e.g., litigation or labor strike outcomes), there is an identification problem that confounds data interpretation. Specifically, the minimally acceptable settlement value from a risk-averse (risk-loving) but unbiased-belief bargainer is empirically indistinguishable from what one could get with risk-neutrality and pessimistically (optimistically) biased beliefs. This article reports results from a controlled bargaining experiment where data on both risk attitude and beliefs under uncertainty are generated in order to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Can an evidentialist be risk-averse?Hayden Wilkinson - manuscript
    Two key questions of normative decision theory are: 1) whether the probabilities relevant to decision theory are evidential or causal; and 2) whether agents should be risk-neutral, and so maximise the expected value of the outcome, or instead risk-averse (or otherwise sensitive to risk). These questions are typically thought to be independent---that our answer to one bears little on our answer to the other. But there is a surprising argument that they are not. In this paper, I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Measuring risk aversion with lists: a new bias. [REVIEW]Antoni Bosch-Domènech & Joaquim Silvestre - 2013 - Theory and Decision 75 (4):465-496.
    Various experimental procedures aimed at measuring individual risk aversion involve a list of pairs of alternative prospects. We first study the widely used method by Holt and Laury :1644–1655, 2002), for which we find that the removal of some items from the lists yields a systematic decrease in risk aversion and scrambles the ranking of individuals by risk aversion. This bias, that we call embedding bias, is quite distinct from other confounds that have been (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  16
    Context-Dependent Risk Aversion: A Model-Based Approach.Darío Cuevas Rivera, Florian Ott, Dimitrije Markovic, Alexander Strobel & Stefan J. Kiebel - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9:393268.
    Most research on risk aversion in behavioral science with human subjects has focused on a component of risk aversion that does not adapt itself to context. More recently, studies have explored risk aversion adaptation to changing circumstances in sequential decision-making tasks. It is an open question whether one can identify evidence, at the single subject level, for such risk aversion adaptation. We conducted a behavioral experiment on human subjects, using a sequential decision (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  22
    Going Boldly Where No One Has Gone Before? How Confidentiality Risk Aversion is Killing Research on Sensitive Topics.Ted Palys & John Lowman - 2010 - Journal of Academic Ethics 8 (4):265-284.
    Bernhard and Young (Journal of Academic Ethics, 7, 175-191, 2009) allege that a myth of confidentiality plagues research in North America because of the absence of statute-based legal protections and the requirements of some REBs to limit confidentiality to the extent permitted by law. In this commentary we describe statute-based protections for research confidentiality available in the United States, clarify the legal situation regarding research confidentiality in Canada, and explain that REBs that require confidentiality to be limited by law are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21. Small stakes risk aversion in the laboratory: A reconsideration.Glenn W. Harrison, Morten I. Lau, Don Ross & J. Todd Swarthout - unknown
    Evidence of risk aversion in laboratory settings over small stakes leads to a priori implausible levels of risk aversion over large stakes under certain assumptions. One core assumption in statements of this calibration puzzle is that small-stakes risk aversion is observed over all levels of wealth, or over a â sufficiently largeâ range of wealth. Although this assumption is viewed as self-evident from the vast experimental literature showing risk aversion over laboratory stakes, (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  5
    An experimental investigation of social risk preferences for health.Arthur E. Attema, Olivier L’Haridon & Gijs van de Kuilen - 2023 - Theory and Decision 95 (3):379-403.
    In this paper, we use the risk apportionment technique of Eeckhoudt, Rey and Schlesinger (2007) to study higher order risk preferences for others’ health as well as ex-ante and ex-post inequality preferences for social risky distributions, and their interaction. In an experiment on a sample of university students acting as impartial spectators, we observe risk aversion towards social health losses and a dislike of ex-ante inequality. In addition, evidence for ex-post inequality seeking is much weaker (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  73
    Positivity of bid-ask spreads and symmetrical monotone risk aversion.Moez Abouda & Alain Chateauneuf - 2002 - Theory and Decision 52 (2):149-170.
    A usual argument in finance refers to no arbitrage opportunities for the positivity of the bid-ask spread. Here we follow the decision theory approach and show that if positivity of the bid-ask spread is identified with strong risk aversion for an expected utility market-maker, this is no longer true for a rank-dependent expected utility one. For such a decision-maker only a very weak form of risk aversion is required, a result which seems more in accordance with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  86
    Valuing environmental costs and benefits in an uncertain future: risk aversion and discounting.Fabien Medvecky - 2012 - Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 5 (1):1-1.
    A central point of debate over environmental policies concerns how future costs and benefits should be assessed. The most commonly used method for assessing the value of future costs and benefits is economic discounting. One often-cited justification for discounting is uncertainty. More specifically, it is risk aversion coupled with the expectation that future prospects are more risky. In this paper I argue that there are at least two reasons for disputing the use of risk aversion as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  60
    On S-Convexity and Risk Aversion.Michel Denuit, Claude Lefèvre & Marco Scarsini - 2001 - Theory and Decision 50 (3):239-248.
    The present note first discusses the concept of s-convex pain functions in decision theory. Then, the economic behavior of an agent with such a pain function is represented through the comparison of some recursive lotteries.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  67
    Golden opportunity, reasonable risk and personal responsibility for health.Julian Savulescu - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (1):59-61.
    In her excellent and comprehensive article, Friesen argues that utilising personal responsibility in healthcare is problematic in several ways: it is difficult to ascribe responsibility to behaviour; there is a risk of prejudice and bias in deciding which behaviours a person should be held responsible for; it may be ineffective at reducing health costs. In this short commentary, I will elaborate the critique of personal responsibility in health but suggest one way in which it could be used ethically. In (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27.  93
    Separating marginal utility and probabilistic risk aversion.Peter Wakker - 1994 - Theory and Decision 36 (1):1-44.
  28.  50
    Even Risk-Averters may Love Risk.Alfred Müller & Marco Scarsini - 2002 - Theory and Decision 52 (1):81-99.
    A decision maker bets on the outcomes of a sequence of coin-tossings. At the beginning of the game the decision maker can choose one of two coins to play the game. This initial choice is irreversible. The coins can be biased and the player is uncertain about the nature of one (or possibly both) coin(s). If the player is an expected-utility maximizer, her choice of the coin will depend on different elements: the nature of the game (namely, whether she can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  28
    Willingness to Pay for Risk Reduction and Risk Aversion without the Expected Utility Assumption.Eric Langlais - 2005 - Theory and Decision 59 (1):43-50.
    By means of minimal assumptions on the individual preferences, I show that the Willingness To Pay (WTP) for both a FSD and SSD reduction of risk is the sum of a mean effect, a pure risk effect and a wealth effect. As a result, the WTP of a risk-averse decision maker may be lower than the WTP of a risk-neutral one, for a large class of individual preferences’ representation and a large class of risks.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  49
    Risk behavior for gain, loss, and mixed prospects.Peter Brooks, Simon Peters & Horst Zank - 2014 - Theory and Decision 77 (2):153-182.
    This study extends experimental tests of (cumulative) prospect theory (PT) over prospects with more than three outcomes and tests second-order stochastic dominance principles (Levy and Levy, Management Science 48:1334–1349, 2002; Baucells and Heukamp, Management Science 52:1409–1423, 2006). It considers choice behavior of people facing prospects of three different types: gain prospects (losing is not possible), loss prospects (gaining is not possible), and mixed prospects (both gaining and losing are possible). The data supports the distinction of risk behavior into (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  35
    The role of intuition and reasoning in driving aversion to risk and ambiguity.Jeffrey V. Butler, Luigi Guiso & Tullio Jappelli - 2014 - Theory and Decision 77 (4):455-484.
    Using a large sample of retail investors as well as experimental data we find that risk and ambiguity aversion are positively correlated. We provide evidence that a common link is decision mode: intuitive thinkers tolerate more risk and ambiguity than effortful reasoners. One interpretation is that intuitive thinking confers an advantage in risky or ambiguous situations. We present supporting lab and field evidence that intuitive thinkers outperform others in uncertain environments. Finally, we find that risk and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  22
    The Hundred Schools of Thought and Three Issues (11).Social Order - 2002 - Contemporary Chinese Thought 33 (4):37-63.
    After the three families divided up the state of Jin and the Tian family took over Qi, the political situation in the fourth century B.C.E. appeared even more chaotic. Wei conquered Chu's Luyang and Qin's Xihe, Qin defeated Wei at Shimen , and again at Shaoliang , and Wei moved its capital to Daliang. During the mid-Warring States period, Qin became dominant in the west, Qi in the east, Chu in the south, and Wei in the center. Rapid changes occurred (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Moment characterization of higher-order risk preferences.Sebastian Ebert - 2013 - Theory and Decision 74 (2):267-284.
    This article presents a characterization of higher-order risk preferences such as prudence or temperance in terms of statistical moments. Our results, which are generalizations of Roger :27–44, 2011) and Ekern, 329–333, 1980), give a better understanding of how higher-order risk preferences relate to skewness preference and kurtosis aversion. While they are not based on expected utility theory, an implication within that theory is that all commonly used utility functions exhibit skewness preference and kurtosis aversion.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  6
    On the elusiveness of higher-order risk attitudes.Jasper Debrabander - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (11):748-748.
    Makins1 formulates a deference principle which states that patients’ attitudes towards the health outcomes associated with different treatment options should drive decision-making and not physicians’ attitudes towards these health outcomes. Although this deference principle is widely agreed on, it is less obvious which role patients’ risk attitudes should play. Makins takes patients’ attitudes towards health outcomes to be sufficiently analogous to patients’ risk attitudes in order to extend his deference principle. His extended deference principle states that patients’ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Taking Risks on Behalf of Another.Johanna Thoma - 2023 - Philosophy Compass 18 (3):e12898.
    A growing number of decision theorists have, in recent years, defended the view that rationality is permissive under risk: Different rational agents may be more or less risk-averse or risk-inclined. This can result in them making different choices under risk even if they value outcomes in exactly the same way. One pressing question that arises once we grant such permissiveness is what attitude to risk we should implement when choosing on behalf of other people. Are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  36.  3
    Research on the Tournament Incentive Mechanism of the Safety Behavior for Construction Workers: Considering Multiple Heterogeneity.Liuyang Ji, Wenyao Liu & Yifan Zhang - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The unsafe behavior of construction workers is one of the most important and direct causes of safety accidents. Managers usually develop effective incentives aimed at regulating worker safety behavior. Due to the large number of workers in construction projects, there are multiple differences in fairness preference, risk preference and ability level, which will lead to the complex effect of the traditional mechanism to regulate workers’ safety behavior. In order to improve the effectiveness of incentive measures for worker safety (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. A Review and Systematization of the Trolley Problem.Stijn Bruers & Johan Braeckman - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (2):251-269.
    The trolley problem, first described by Foot (1967) and Thomson (The Monist, 59, 204–217, 1976), is one of the most famous and influential thought experiments in deontological ethics. The general story is that a runaway trolley is threatening the lives of five people. Doing nothing will result in the death of those persons, but acting in order to save those persons would unavoidably result in the death of another, sixth person. It appears that, depending on the situation, we have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  38. Accuracy, Risk, and the Principle of Indifference.Richard Pettigrew - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (1):35-59.
    In Bayesian epistemology, the problem of the priors is this: How should we set our credences (or degrees of belief) in the absence of evidence? That is, how should we set our prior or initial credences, the credences with which we begin our credal life? David Lewis liked to call an agent at the beginning of her credal journey a superbaby. The problem of the priors asks for the norms that govern these superbabies. -/- The Principle of Indifference gives a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  39. Ambiguity aversion: the explanatory power of indeterminate probabilities.Horacio Arló-Costa & Jeffrey Helzner - 2010 - Synthese 172 (1):37-55.
    Daniel Ellsberg presented in Ellsberg (The Quarterly Journal of Economics 75:643–669, 1961) various examples questioning the thesis that decision making under uncertainty can be reduced to decision making under risk. These examples constitute one of the main challenges to the received view on the foundations of decision theory offered by Leonard Savage in Savage (1972). Craig Fox and Amos Tversky have, nevertheless, offered an indirect defense of Savage. They provided in Fox and Tversky (1995) an explanation of Ellsberg’s two-color (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  9
    Surprised Divide.Anonymous One - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (2):70-71.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Surprised DivideAnonymous OneAnonymous OneNot long after our daughter was born, my wife and I were expecting a son. We were busy new parents, so her pregnancy with our second child went by quickly and without a lot of the fuss that a first pregnancy brings. To our surprise, our son was born a few weeks early but aside from a little jaundice he was a happy, healthy baby.My parents (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  9
    On the predictions of cumulative prospect theory for third and fourth order risk preferences.Ivan Paya, David A. Peel & Konstantinos Georgalos - 2023 - Theory and Decision 95 (2):337-359.
    In this paper, we analyse higher-order risky choices by the representative cumulative prospect theory (CPT) decision maker from three alternative reference points. These are the status quo, average payout and maxmin. The choice tasks we consider in our analysis include binary risks, and are the ones employed in the experimental literature on higher order risk preferences. We demonstrate that the choices made by the representative subject depend on the reference point. If the reference point is the status (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  41
    On second order probabilities and the notion of epistemic risk.Nils-Eric Sahlin - unknown
    Second or higher order probabilities have commonly been viewed with scepticism by those working within the realm of probability and decision theory. The aim of the present note is to show how the notion of second order probabilities can add to our understanding of judgmental and decision processes and how the traditional framework of Bayesian decision theory can be extended in a fruitful way by taking such entities into account. Section one consists of a brief account of arguments (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43.  16
    You Can Ask Me If You Really Want to Know What I Think.Sarah Te One, Rebecca Blaikie, Michelle Egan-Bitran & Zoey Henley - 2014 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 46 (9):1052-1068.
    Recent social policy discourses in Aotearoa New Zealand focus on vulnerable children’s well-being and the detrimental, long-term and costly impacts of child poverty. The discourse pervading much of the policy labels children and young people as ‘vulnerable’ or ‘at risk’ or ‘in crisis’, a view, which we argue, is both disempowering and marginalising. We propose a shift in focus which views children and young people as agentic, capable and competent. Drawing on several small-scale research projects and reports we demonstrate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  20
    The micro‐fascism of Plato’s good citizen: producing (dis)order through the construction of risk.Patrick O.?Byrne & Dave Holmes - 2007 - Nursing Philosophy 8 (2):92-101.
    The human body has come to be seen as forever susceptible to both external and internal hazards, which in many circumstances require immediate, heroic, and expensive intervention. In response to this, there has been a shift from a treatment‐based healthcare model to one of prevention wherein nurses play an integral role by identifying and assessing risks for individuals, communities, and populations. This paper uses Deborah Lupton’s outline of the spectrum of risk and applies the theoretical works of Foucault and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. "My Place in the Sun": Reflections on the Thought of Emmanuel Levinas.Committee of Public Safety - 1996 - Diacritics 26 (1):3-10.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Martin Heidegger and OntologyEmmanuel Levinas (bio)The prestige of Martin Heidegger 1 and the influence of his thought on German philosophy marks both a new phase and one of the high points of the phenomenological movement. Caught unawares, the traditional establishment is obliged to clarify its position on this new teaching which casts a spell over youth and which, overstepping the bounds of permissibility, is already in vogue. For once, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Is risk aversion irrational? Examining the “fallacy” of large numbers.H. Orri Stefánsson - 2020 - Synthese 197 (10):4425-4437.
    A moderately risk averse person may turn down a 50/50 gamble that either results in her winning $200 or losing $100. Such behaviour seems rational if, for instance, the pain of losing $100 is felt more strongly than the joy of winning $200. The aim of this paper is to examine an influential argument that some have interpreted as showing that such moderate risk aversion is irrational. After presenting an axiomatic argument that I take to be the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  15
    Higher-order desires, risk attitudes and respect for autonomy.Alice Elizabeth Kelley - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (11):753-754.
    Nicholas Makins makes a valuable contribution to the literature on medical decision-making, highlighting the role that risk attitudes play in deliberation and subsequently arguing that, in medical choices under uncertainty, if considerations of autonomy and beneficence support deference to patient values and outcome preferences then they also support deference to patients’ attitudes to risk.1 Crucially, however, Makins suggests that it is not simply first-order risk attitudes that are the appropriate target of deference but, rather, patients’ higher- (...) risk attitudes. In other words, Makins argues that if considerations of autonomy and beneficence support deference in medical decision-making, this deference should include the risk attitudes that individuals desire to have or reflectively endorse. This commentary draws out a morally relevant and overlooked distinction between: (1) deferring to patients’ higher-order attitudes that endorse the first-order risk attitudes they currently hold. and (2) deferring to patients’ higher-order attitudes that endorse risk attitudes that are at odds with the first-order risk attitudes they currently hold (which equates to a higher-order desire to change one’s first-order risk-attitudes). I agree with Makins that if respect for autonomy and beneficence support deference to patient preferences, then these considerations may also support deference to at least some higher-order risk attitudes, namely, those of type (1). But I think that whether they support deference to those of type (2) is less clear. In particular, it does not …. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  13
    Menschliche Vielfalt im Lichte der Friedensförderung.Christophe Germann - 2015 - Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 101 (2):164-190.
    A new cosmopolitan world order founded on peace-related diversity of human expressions is likely to strengthen the weaker individual. Such order remains nevertheless meritocratic because it would contribute to materialize enhanced equality between individuals belonging to human groups of different strengths with respect to access to power, wealth or popularity. Therefore, in comparison to existing orders, it would arguably create a better basis for freedom and solidarity as well as for peace between human groups, including states. The originality (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. India and the Risk of Psychoanalysis.Lakshmi Kapani, Jeanne Ferguson & François Chenet - 1986 - Diogenes 34 (135):63-78.
    Because of the widespread feminine priority that makes it the receptacle of śakti, India is definitely “one of the last bastions of the Mother,” as is pointed out in a recent book. If in fact there is a “maternalistic” culture it is certainly that of India, in spite of the legal regime, in which the element of affectionate magic characterizing all life and all organic intimacy is affirmed through the warm symbiosis of mother-child love. A miracle of that absolute love (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  41
    Genealogies of Oppression: A Response to Ladelle McWhorter’s Racism and Sexual Oppression in Anglo-America: A Genealogy.Chloë Taylor - 2012 - philoSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism 2 (2):207-215.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Genealogies of OppressionA Response to Ladelle McWhorter’s Racism and Sexual Oppression in Anglo-America: A GenealogyChloë TaylorLadelle McWhorter introducesRacism and Sexual Oppression inAnglo-America with an account of her experiences during the days between the attack on and the death of Matthew Shepard. On sabbatical near Pennsylvania State University in October 1998, McWhorter describes following these events as they were covered by the media and discussed on a Penn State University (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994