Results for 'Representation of action'

980 found
Order:
  1. The Representation of Action.Anton Ford - 2017 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 80:217-233.
    For as long as there has been anything called “the philosophy of action,” its practitioners have accounted for action in terms of an associated kind of explanation. The alternative to this approach was noticed, but not adopted, by G. E. M. Anscombe. Anscombe observed that a series of answers to the reason-requesting question “Why?” may be read in reverse order as a series of answers to the question “How?” Unlike answers to the question “Why?”, answers to the question (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  16
    The representation of action in Italian Sign Language (LIS).Virginia Volterra, Pasquale Rinaldi, Chiara Bonsignori & Elena Tomasuolo - 2020 - Cognitive Linguistics 31 (1):1-36.
    The present study investigates the types of verb and symbolic representational strategies used by 10 deaf signing adults and 13 deaf signing children who described in Italian Sign Language 45 video clips representing nine action types generally communicated by five general verbs in spoken Italian. General verbs, in which the same sign was produced to refer to several different physical action types, were rarely used by either group of participants. Both signing children and adults usually produced specific depicting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Beyond embodiment : from internal representation of action to symbolic processes.Isabel Barahona da Fonseca, Jose Barahona da Fonseca & Vitor Pereira - 2012 - In Liz Stillwaggon Swan (ed.), Origins of mind. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 187-199.
    In sensorimotor integration, representation involves an anticipatory model of the action to be performed. This model integrates efferent signals (motor commands), its reafferent consequences (sensory consequences of an organism’s own motor action), and other afferences (sensory signals) originated by stimuli independent of the action performed. Representation, a form of internal modeling, is invoked to explain the fact that behavior oriented to the achievement of future goals is relatively independent from the immediate environment. Internal modeling explains (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  31
    Psychology Degree Zero? The Representation of Action in the Films of the Dardenne Brothers.Robert Pippin - 2015 - Critical Inquiry 41 (4):757-785.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Body-specific representations of action verbs: Evidence from fMRI in right-and left-handers.Daniel Casasanto, Roel Willems & Peter Hagoort - 2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. pp. 875--880.
  6.  12
    32 The Representation of Action.Scott T. Grafton & Richard B. Ivry - 2004 - In Michael S. Gazzaniga (ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences Iii. MIT Press. pp. 441.
  7.  15
    The mental representation of action.Jennifer J. Freyd - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):145-146.
  8. Elisabetta ladavas and Alessandro farne.Representations Of Space & Near Specific Body Parts - 2004 - In Charles Spence & Jon Driver (eds.), Crossmodal Space and Crossmodal Attention. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  48
    One‐year‐old infants use teleological representations of actions productively.Gergely Csibra, Szilvia Bíró, Orsolya Koós & György Gergely - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (1):111-133.
    Two experiments investigated whether infants represent goal‐directed actions of others in a way that allows them to draw inferences to unobserved states of affairs (such as unseen goal states or occluded obstacles). We measured looking times to assess violation of infants' expectations upon perceiving either a change in the actions of computer‐animated figures or in the context of such actions. The first experiment tested whether infants would attribute a goal to an action that they had not seen completed. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  10.  17
    One‐year‐old infants use teleological representations of actions productively.Michael Ramscar, Daniel Yarlett, Shimon Edelman, Nathan Intrator, Gergely Csibra, Szilvia Bıró, Orsolya Koós, György Gergely, Holk Cruse & Michael D. Lee - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (1):111-133.
    Two experiments investigated whether infants represent goal‐directed actions of others in a way that allows them to draw inferences to unobserved states of affairs (such as unseen goal states or occluded obstacles). We measured looking times to assess violation of infants' expectations upon perceiving either a change in the actions of computer‐animated figures or in the context of such actions. The first experiment tested whether infants would attribute a goal to an action that they had not seen completed. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  11.  42
    Cognitive Representation of a Complex Motor Action Executed by Different Motor Systems.Heiko Lex, Christoph Schütz, Andreas Knoblauch & Thomas Schack - 2015 - Minds and Machines 25 (1):1-15.
    The present study evaluates the cognitive representation of a kicking movement performed by a human and a humanoid robot, and how they are represented in experts and novices of soccer and robotics, respectively. To learn about the expertise-dependent development of memory structures, we compared the representation structures of soccer experts and robot experts concerning a human and humanoid robot kicking movement. We found different cognitive representation structures for both expertise groups under two different motor performance conditions . (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Nonconceptual representations for action and the limits of intentional control.Elisabeth Pacherie - 2011 - Social Psychology 42 (1):67-73.
    In this paper I argue that, to make intentional actions fully intelligible, we need to posit representations of action the content of which is nonconceptual. I further argue that an analysis of the properties of these nonconceptual representations, and of their relation- ships to action representations at higher levels, sheds light on the limits of intentional control. On the one hand, the capacity to form nonconceptual representations of goal-directed movements underscores the capacity to acquire executable concepts of these (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  13.  13
    Neural Representations of Task Context and Temporal Order During Action Sequence Execution.Danesh Shahnazian, Mehdi Senoussi, Ruth M. Krebs, Tom Verguts & Clay B. Holroyd - 2022 - Topics in Cognitive Science 14 (2):223-240.
    Routine action sequences critically rely on neural mechanisms maintaining contextual and temporal information to disambiguate similar tasks (e.g. making coffee or tea). In this study we show the involvement of areas in temporal and lateral prefrontal cortices in maintaining temporal and contextual information for the execution of hierarchically‐organized action sequences.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  15
    The Representation of Motor (Inter)action, States of Action, and Learning: Three Perspectives on Motor Learning by Way of Imagery and Execution.Cornelia Frank & Thomas Schack - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8:224812.
    Learning in intelligent systems is a result of direct or indirect interaction with the environment. Humans can learn by way of different states of (inter-)action such as the execution or the imagery of an action, but their unique potential to induce brain-related as well as mind-related changes in the motor action system is still being debated. The systematic repetition of different states of action (e.g., execution and imagery in terms of physical and mental practice) and their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  2
    Logic of Action from the Perspective of Knowledge Representation.Andreas Herzig, Emiliano Lorini & Elise Perrotin - 2024 - In Jacek Malinowski & Rafał Palczewski (eds.), Janusz Czelakowski on Logical Consequence. Springer Verlag. pp. 401-418.
    Taking the perspective of knowledge representation, we introduce a simple logic of agency where the agents’ actions are described by their precondition and effects and whose semantics is based on the concept of attempt. We give its syntax, semantics, and axiomatics and discuss the relation with other proposals, in particular Belnap and Horty’s ‘branching time and agent choice’ semantics (BT+AC) and Czelakowski’s relational semantics.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The inner sense of action: Agency and motor representations.Vittorio Gallese - 2000 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (10):23-40.
    Discusses the possibility of reconciling different articulations of intentionality from a neurobiological perspective. The author analyzes the relationship between agency and representation and how representation is intrinsically related to action control. The author also presents a new account of action, arguing against what is still commonly held as its proper definition, namely the final outcome of a cascade-like process that starts from the analysis of sensory data, incorporates the result of decision processes, and ends up with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  17.  28
    The Representation of an Action: Tragedy between Kant and Hegel.Andrew Cooper - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):573-594.
    Hegel's theory of tragedy has polarized critics. In the past, many philosophers have claimed that Hegel's theory of tragedy removes Kant's critical insights and returns to pre-critical metaphysics. More recently, several have argued that Hegel does not break faith with tragic experience but allows philosophy to be transformed by tragedy. In this paper I examine the strength of this revised position. First I show that it identifies Hegel's insightful critique of Kant's theoretical assumptions. Yet I then argue that it fails (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  34
    The Representation of an Action: Tragedy between Kant and Hegel.Andrew Cooper - 2016 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (4):573-594.
    Hegel's theory of tragedy has polarized critics. In the past, many philosophers have claimed that Hegel's theory of tragedy removes Kant's critical insights and returns to pre-critical metaphysics. More recently, several have argued that Hegel does not break faith with tragic experience but allows philosophy to be transformed by tragedy. In this paper I examine the strength of this revised position. First I show that it identifies Hegel's insightful critique of Kant's theoretical assumptions. Yet I then argue that it fails (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  25
    The Representation of Objects in Apraxia: From Action Execution to Error Awareness.Loredana Canzano, Michele Scandola, Valeria Gobbetto, Giuseppe Moretto, Daniela D’Imperio & Valentina Moro - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
  20.  28
    A Hegelian Logic of ‘Us’: Implicit Forms and Explicit Representations of Actions and Practices.Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer - 2019 - Hegel Bulletin 40 (3):374-397.
    In order to understand Hegel's gnomic oracle according to which the ‘I’ is a ‘We’, the notion of apersonalsubject is explained by its competence to perform personal roles in a pre-given partition of roles. Explicit divisions of labour by contractual promises are special cases that presuppose the general case of an already established social practice. On the other hand, methodological individualism is right to stress that we actualize joint intentions only via corresponding instantiations. In performing our parts, we form a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  12
    What's Shared in Movement Kinematics: Investigating Co-representation of Actions Through Movement.Matilde Rocca & Andrea Cavallo - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  17
    Neural representation of the sensorimotor speech–action-repository.Cornelia Eckers, Bernd J. Kröger, Katharina Sass & Stefan Heim - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
  23.  10
    Why it is unsurprising that ape “language training” enhances “completing incomplete (external) representations of action”.Justin Leiber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):151-151.
  24.  27
    Components of action representations evoked when identifying manipulable objects.Daniel N. Bub, Michael E. J. Masson & Terry Lin - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  25.  36
    The Mental Representation of Human Action.Sydney Levine, Alan M. Leslie & John Mikhail - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (4):1229-1264.
    Various theories of moral cognition posit that moral intuitions can be understood as the output of a computational process performed over structured mental representations of human action. We propose that action plan diagrams—“act trees”—can be a useful tool for theorists to succinctly and clearly present their hypotheses about the information contained in these representations. We then develop a methodology for using a series of linguistic probes to test the theories embodied in the act trees. In Study 1, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26. The ethics of representation and action in virtual reality.Philip Brey - 1999 - Ethics and Information Technology 1 (1):5-14.
    This essay addresses ethical aspects of the design and use of virtual reality (VR) systems, focusing on the behavioral options made available in such systems and the manner in which reality is represented or simulated in them. An assessment is made of the morality of immoral behavior in virtual reality, and of the virtual modeling of such behavior. Thereafter, the ethical aspects of misrepresentation and biased representation in VR applications are discussed.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  27.  78
    A representational theory of action.Kent Bach - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 34 (4):361 - 379.
  28.  71
    Acquisition, representation, and control of action.Bernhard Hommel & Birgit Elsner - 2009 - In Ezequiel Morsella, John A. Bargh & Peter M. Gollwitzer (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Human Action. Oxford University Press. pp. 371--398.
  29.  23
    Contribution of motor representations to action verb processing.Michael Andres, Chiara Finocchiaro, Marco Buiatti & Manuela Piazza - 2015 - Cognition 134 (C):174-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  16
    The organization of action representations in posterior parietal cortex.Scott H. Johnson-Frey - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):40-41.
    Glover suggests that representational systems for planning versus control are mapped exclusively to the inferior (IPL) versus superior (SPL) parietal lobules respectively. Yet, there is ample evidence that the IPL and SPL both contribute to action planning and control. Alternatively, I distinguish between the parietal-frontal systems involved in the representation of acquired manual skills versus nonskilled actions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  53
    The role of action representations in the dynamics of embodied cognition.Natika Newton - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (1):58-59.
    Thelen et al. present a convincing explanation of the A-not-B error, but contrary to their own claims, their explanation essentially involves mental representations. As is too common among cognitive scientists, they equate mental representations with representations of external physical objects. They clearly show, however, that representations of bodily actions on physical objects are central to the dynamical system producing the error.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  40
    Representation in action.Alec Hinshelwood - forthcoming - European Journal of Philosophy.
    When one is intentionally doing something, one represents that thing as a goal to be accomplished. One represents it practically. How should we characterize this practical representation further? In this paper, I argue that when one is intentionally doing something, one's representation of it as a goal to be accomplished must also be knowledge that one is intentionally doing that thing. And I argue that this knowledge must itself be one's intentionally doing that thing. I aim to show, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  8
    Representational Processes of Actions Toward and Away from the Body.Francesco Ruotolo, Gennaro Ruggiero, Teresa Pia Arabia, Laurent Ott, Yann Coello, Angela Bartolo & Tina Iachini - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (9):e13192.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 46, Issue 9, September 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  15
    The cognitive representation of intending not to act: Evidence for specific non-action-effect binding.Simone Kühn & Marcel Brass - 2010 - Cognition 117 (1):9-16.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Body Language: Representation in Action.Mark Rowlands - 2006 - Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.
    This is not to say simply that these forms of acting can facilitate representation but that they are themselves representational.
  36. Empiricism, Antirealism and Representation of Human Action.G. Ramana - 2005 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 32 (3).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  8
    Collective Action and the "Representation" of African Women: A Liberian Case Study.Mary H. Moran - 1989 - Feminist Studies 15 (3):443.
  38. Persistence of Internal Representations of Alternative Voluntary Actions.Elisa Filevich & Patrick Haggard - 2014 - In Ezequiel Morsella & T. Andrew Poehlman (eds.), Consciousness and action control. Lausanne, Switzerland: Frontiers Media SA.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  7
    Corrigendum: The role of action representations in thematic object relations.Konstantinos Tsagkaridis, Christine E. Watson, Steven A. Jax & Laurel J. Buxbaum - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  40.  8
    Uncovering Hidden Representations of Performers Physical Action in Applied Theater.Ilana Gorban - 2012 - Mind and Matter 10 (2):195-214.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  84
    Separate visual representations in the planning and control of action.Scott Glover - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):3-24.
    Evidence for a dichotomy between the planning of an action and its on-line control in humans is reviewed. This evidence suggests that planning and control each serve a specialized purpose utilizing distinct visual representations. Evidence from behavioral studies suggests that planning is influenced by a large array of visual and cognitive information, whereas control is influenced solely by the spatial characteristics of the target, including such things as its size, shape, orientation, and so forth. Evidence from brain imaging and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  42. Egocentric Spatial Representation in Action and Perception.Robert Briscoe - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (2):423-460.
    Neuropsychological findings used to motivate the "two visual systems" hypothesis have been taken to endanger a pair of widely accepted claims about spatial representation in conscious visual experience. The first is the claim that visual experience represents 3-D space around the perceiver using an egocentric frame of reference. The second is the claim that there is a constitutive link between the spatial contents of visual experience and the perceiver's bodily actions. In this paper, I review and assess three main (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  43.  46
    Close to me: Multisensory space representations for action and pre-reflexive consciousness of oneself-in-the-world.Dorothée Legrand, Claudio Brozzoli, Yves Rossetti & Alessandro Farnè - 2007 - Consciousness and Cognition 16 (3):687-699.
    Philosophical considerations as well as several recent studies from neurophysiology, neuropsychology, and psychophysics converged in showing that the peripersonal space is structured in a body-centred manner and represented through integrated sensory inputs. Multisensory representations may deserve the function of coding peripersonal space for avoiding or interacting with objects. Neuropsychological evidence is reviewed for dynamic interactions between space representations and action execution, as revealed by the behavioural effects that the use of a tool, as a physical extension of the reachable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  44.  52
    Springs of Action: Understanding Intentional Behavior.Alfred R. Mele - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Tackling some central problems in the philosophy of action, Mele constructs an explanatory model for intentional behavior, locating the place and significance of such mental phenomena as beliefs, desires, reasons, and intentions in the etiology of intentional action. In the first part, Mele illuminates the connection between desire and action and defends detailed characterizations of irresistible desires and reasons for action. Mele argues for the viability of a causal approach to the explanation of intentional action (...)
  45.  1
    On the media representation of the universal category of culture "sinfulness".Elena Aleksandrovna Semukhina & Svetlana Vladimirovna Shindel - forthcoming - Philosophy and Culture (Russian Journal).
    This article aims to analyze the manifestation of the universal axiological cultural category of sinfulness in the media space. The study's subject was this category's properties and functions, which are actualized when represented in digital media. In accordance with this goal, we used such methods as continuous sampling and observation of the facts of the representation of cultural categories, which allowed us to determine the linguistic material for analysis and a statistical method for quantitative analysis. The content analysis of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    The Structure of Agentive Awareness in Kent Bach’s Representational Theory of Action.Artem S. Yashin - 2023 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 60 (2):133-150.
    This paper analyzes Kent Bach’s representational theory of action, one of the causal theories of action. Bach’s theory sets requirements not only for the cause of an action, but also for how it unfolds in time and transitions into another action. These requirements suggest a sequential emergence of two components of the agent’s action awareness: the representation of the prepared movement and the perception of its sensory consequences. Bach introduces the concepts of “effective (...)” (ER) and “receptive representation” (RR) to denote these components of awareness. According to representational theory, action has a cyclic three-step causal structure, where ER is the cause of a movement, the movement is the cause of RR, and RR is the cause of ER of subsequent movement. In constructing his theory, Bach tries to take into account the problem of deviant causal chains and to introduce the so-called minimal actions into the purview of the philosophy of action. Relying on the behavioral data on blindfolded deafferentated patients, in this paper I argue that RRs are not a necessary element of action. I also analyze Bach’s distinction between ER and RR and compare it with J. Searle’s approach, placing Bach’s theory within the context of studies of the structure of intentional states. I show that Bach’s theory occupies a unique position among views on the structure of action awareness. At the same time, I conclude that the frameworks of Bach and Searle are insufficient for describing the metaphysical difference between the two kinds of intentional states, and I also point out the difficulties facing the notion of ER. Based on this reasoning and the data on deafferentated patients, I propose a modification of the causal structure of action proposed by Bach, making a remark about the inadequate definition of ER. In the proposed modification, RR and the agent’s prior intention serve as alternative components of action awareness. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    Neurophysiological States and Perceptual Representations: The Case of Action Properties Detected by the Ventro-Dorsal Visual Stream.Gabriele Ferretti - 2006 - In Lorenzo Magnani & Claudia Casadio (eds.), Model Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Logical, Epistemological, and Cognitive Issues. Springer Verlag.
    Philosophers and neuroscientists often suggest that we perceptually represent objects and their properties. However, they start from very different background assumptions when they use the term “perceptual representation”. On the one hand, sometimes philosophers do not need to properly take into consideration the empirical evidence concerning the neural states subserving the representational perceptual processes they are talking about. On the other hand, neuroscientists do not rely on a meticulous definition of “perceptual representation” when they talk about this empirical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48. Computational Representation of Practical Argument.Katie Atkinson, Trevor Bench-Capon & Peter McBurney - 2006 - Synthese 152 (2):157-206.
    In this paper we consider persuasion in the context of practical reasoning, and discuss the problems associated with construing reasoning about actions in a manner similar to reasoning about beliefs. We propose a perspective on practical reasoning as presumptive justification of a course of action, along with critical questions of this justification, building on the account of Walton. From this perspective, we articulate an interaction protocol, which we call PARMA, for dialogues over proposed actions based on this theory. We (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  49.  11
    The representation of illness manifestation during the first psychiatric interview with patients preliminary diagnosed with depressive illness.Justyna Ziółkowska - 2011 - Polish Psychological Bulletin 42 (3):123-128.
    The representation of illness manifestation during the first psychiatric interview with patients preliminary diagnosed with depressive illness The aim of the study is the analysis of patients' and doctors' discursive representation of mental health problems during the first psychiatric interview. The data comes from 16 initial psychiatric interviews recorded by doctors in three psychiatric hospitals in Poland. Assuming the discursive character of representation the analysis of the data has shown that the representation of illness manifestations in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Cinematic Representations of Facial Anomalies Across Time and Cultures.Connor Wagner, Clifford Ian Workman, Mariola Paruzel-Czachura, Satvika Kumar, Lauren Salinero, Carlos Barrero, Matthew Pontell, Jesse Taylor & Anjan Chatterjee - forthcoming - PsyArXiv Preprint:1-32.
    The “scarred villain” trope, where facial differences like scars signify moral corruption, is ubiquitous in film (e.g., Batman’s The Joker). Strides by advocacy groups to undermine the trope, however, suggest cinematic representations of facial differences could be improving with time. This preregistered study characterized facial differences in film across cultures (US vs. India) and time (US: 1980-2019, India: 2000-2019). Top-grossing films by country and decade were screened for characters with facial differences. We found that the scarred villain trope has actually (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 980