93 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Oswald Hanfling [81]O. Hanfling [17]
  1. Philosophy and Ordinary Language: The Bent and Genius of Our Tongue.Oswald Hanfling - 2000 - New York: Routledge.
    What is philosophy about and what are its methods? _Philosophy and Ordinary Language_ is a defence of the view that philosophy is largely about questions of language, which to a large extent means _ordinary_ language. Some people argue that if philosophy is about ordinary language, then it is necessarily less deep and difficult than it is usually taken to be but Oswald Hanfling shows us that this isn't true. Hanfling, a leading expert in the development of analytic philosophy, covers a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  2.  71
    Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life.Oswald Hanfling - 2002 - New York: Routledge.
    Wittgenstein's later writings generate a great deal of controversy and debate, as do the implications of his ideas for such topics as consciousness, knowledge, language and the arts. Oswald Hanfling addresses a widespeard tendency to ascribe to Wittgenstein views that go beyond those he actually held. Separate chapters deal with important topics such as the private language argument, rule-following, the problem of other minds, and the ascription of scepticism to Wittgenstein. Describing Wittgenstein as a 'humanist' thinker, he contrasts his views (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  3.  53
    Logical positivism.Oswald Hanfling - 1981 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    This book is a compact, accessible treatment of the main ideas advanced by the positivists, including Schlick, Carnap, Ayer, and the early Wittgenstein. Oswald Hanfling discusses such ideas as the 'verification principle' ('the meaning of this statement is the method of its verification') and the 'elimination of metaphysics, ' an attempt to show that metaphysical statements, for example about God, are unverifiable and therefore meaningless.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4.  13
    Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy.Oswald Hanfling - 1989 - State University of New York Press.
    The book exposes common misunderstandings about Wittgenstein, and examines in detail the celebrated 'private language' argument.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5. Logical Positivism.Oswald Hanfling - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (3):303-306.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. Philosophical aesthetics: an introduction.Oswald Hanfling (ed.) - 1992 - Milton Keynes, UK: Open University.
    This volume contains surveys of the main issues in philosophical aesthetics, as discussed by thinkers from ancient Greece to modern times.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7.  11
    Essential readings in logical positivism.Oswald Hanfling (ed.) - 1981 - Oxford, England: Blackwell.
  8. The Quest for Meaning.Oswald Hanfling - 1993 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 33 (2):127-128.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. The Quest for Meaning.O. Hanfling - 1990 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 52 (3):563-563.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10. What is wrong with sorites arguments?O. Hanfling - 2001 - Analysis 61 (1):29-35.
  11.  50
    ‘I heard a plaintive melody’.Oswald Hanfling - 1990 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 28:117-133.
    Asked about Wittgenstein's contribution to aesthetics, one might think first of all of his discussion of ‘family resemblance’ concepts, in which he argued that the various instances of games, for example, need not have any feature or set of features in common, in virtue of which they are all called games; the concept of a game can function perfectly well without any such set of conditions. This insight was soon applied to the much debated quest for a definition of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12.  10
    Life and meaning: a reader.Oswald Hanfling (ed.) - 1987 - New York, NY, USA: B. Blackwell in association with the Open University.
    Life and Meaning surveys a variety of Philosophical answers to the question, 'What makes life worth living?' By collecting readings from a wide range of philosophical history it gives the various perspectives on the value and meaning of life. Aspects of life which appear to make it meaningless 9death, suffering, randomness) are seen in the light of their long and varied history in philosophical literature and are subjected to careful scrutiny. The texts chosen here pose these and related issues and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  6
    The quest for meaning.Oswald Hanfling - 1987 - Milton Keynes, UK: Open University.
  14. Consciousness:'The Last Mystery'.Oswald Hanfling - 2001 - In Severin Schroeder (ed.), Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Palgrave.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15. The Quest for Meaning.Oswald Hanfling - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (248):266-268.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  40
    What Is Wrong with the Paradigm Case Argument?Oswald Hanfling - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:21 - 38.
    Oswald Hanfling; II*—What is Wrong with the Paradigm Case Argument?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 21–38, http.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  71
    The institutional theory: A candidate for appreciation?Oswald Hanfling - 1999 - British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (2):189-194.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  45
    The use of 'theory' in philosophy.Oswald Hanfling - 2004 - In Erich Ammereller & Eugen Fisher (eds.), Wittgenstein at Work: Method in the Philosophical Investigations. Routledge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  45
    Loving My Neighbour, Loving Myself.Oswald Hanfling - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (264):145 - 157.
    The biblical injunction to love one's neighbour has long been regarded as a central pillar of morality. It is taken to be an ideal which gives direction to our moral aspirations, even though most of us find it difficult to live up to, owing to our selfish natures. But the difficulties I wish to raise are of a logical kind, as distinct from those depending on personal character. They fall under three headings: the first concerns the scope of ‘my neighbour’, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20. Scientific Realism and Ordinary Usage.Oswald Hanfling - 1984 - Philosophical Investigations 7 (3):187-205.
  21.  75
    A Situational Account of Knowledge.Oswald Hanfling - 1985 - The Monist 68 (1):40-56.
    The concept of knowledge, more than any other, has invited truth-functional analysis. In saying of a person that he knows that p, we are, according to many philosophers, saying no more and no less than three or four distinct things. In spite of setbacks suffered by the “traditional” analysis, the belief remains strong that there is a definitive answer to the question “What is knowledge?” in truth-functional terms. Yet the word ‘know’, like most others having to do with human beings, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  49
    Does language need rules?Oswald Hanfling - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):193-205.
  23. Learning about right and wrong: Ethics and language.Oswald Hanfling - 2003 - Philosophy 78 (1):25-41.
    The difference between right and wrong is not something that is taught; it is, necessarily, picked up by a child in the course of learning its native language, and parents have no choice about this. In learning the meaning of ‘steal’, for example, the child learns that such actions are wrong. It also develops, through a kind of conditioning, the appropriate feelings and attitudes. The very concept of a reason has a moral content; so that, in acquiring this concept, the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  80
    Paradoxes of aesthetic distance.Oswald Hanfling - 2003 - British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (2):175-186.
    A feature that contributes to the charm of much poetry is its obscurity and indirectness. We want to grasp what the poet is saying and yet, it appears, to do so only with difficulty. How is this preference to be explained? (1) It contributes to promoting an ‘aesthetic attitude’. (2) It conforms to certain general features of human psychology, including (a) a general preference for indirectness and indeterminacy and (b) the pleasure of working things out. Distance, in the relevant sense, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  73
    How we trust one another.Oswald Hanfling - 2008 - Philosophy 83 (2):161-177.
    How is the possibility of promising to be explained without circularity? Appeal is made to the role of natural inclinations in linguistic behaviour, which presupposes truth telling and promise keeping, and also to the social functions of human language which go beyond signalling and transmitting information and which are prior to any explicit conventions. Although promises are broken and lies told, we all have the right to feel resentment when these things happen.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  6
    Kant's Copernican Revolution: Moral Philosophy.Oswald Hanfling - 1972
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. What does the private language argument prove?Oswald Hanfling - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (137):468-481.
  28. A Gettier drama.Oswald Hanfling - 2003 - Analysis 63 (3):262–263.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  22
    Five kinds of distance.O. Hanfling - 2000 - British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (1):89-102.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  40
    Hume and Wittgenstein.Oswald Hanfling - 1975 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 9:47-65.
    It is well known that Wittgenstein's reading of the philosophical classics was patchy. He left unread a large part of the literature which most philosophers would regard as essential to a knowledge of their subject. Wittgenstein gave an interesting reason for his non-reading of Hume. He said that he could not sit down and read Hume, because he knew far too much about the subject of Hume's writings to find this anything but a torture. In a recent commentary, Peter Hacker (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  70
    Was Wittgenstein a sceptic?Oswald Hanfling - 1985 - Philosophical Investigations 8 (January):1-16.
    According to kripke, Wittgenstein denied certain beliefs about meaning and other minds. But who holds these beliefs? we do "not" believe that "all future applications" of a word are "determined"; nor that "i give directions to myself"; nor that something has to "constitute" meaning. Such beliefs are distortions by realist philosophers; it needs no sceptic to deny them. Wittgenstein's "sympathy with the solipsist" is an illusion, Due to misreadings (and mistranslations) of the text. Wittgenstein's position is clear and does not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  64
    Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic.Oswald Hanfling - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20:261-283.
    When, in 1979, A. J. Ayer was asked for an evaluation of his youthful Language, Truth and Logic (LTL), he replied: ‘I suppose the most important of the defects was that nearly all of it was false’. Like many of the claims in the book itself, this verdict is open to question. What was wrong with LTL was not so much that what it said was false, but that it presented philosophical issues in an excessively simple and aggressive way. Yet (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  25
    Ayer.Oswald Hanfling - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    Philosophy is one of the most intimidating and difficult of disciplines, as any of its students can attest. This book is an important entry in a distinctive new series from Routledge: The Great Philosophers . Breaking down obstacles to understanding the ideas of history's greatest thinkers, these brief, accessible, and affordable volumes offer essential introductions to the great philosophers of the Western tradition from Plato to Wittgenstein. In just 64 pages, each author, a specialist on his subject, places the philosopher (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  1
    A.J. Ayer: Analysing what We Mean.Oswald Hanfling - 1997 - Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
    According to Ayer, philosophy is an activity of analysis, not a means to truth. First principles and metaphysical truths can neither be established or denied byphilosophical enquiry. He tried to prove that verifibility (whether a proposition can be shown to be true or false) was the key principle of philosophical methodology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  31
    A Gettier drama.O. Hanfling - 2003 - Analysis 63 (3):262-263.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  18
    Alfred Jules Ayer.Oswald Hanfling - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 20:259-.
    Alfred Jules Ayer was born in London and educated at Eton and Christ Church, Oxford. He attended sessions of the logical positivist ‘Vienna Circle’ in 1932, and taught at Oxford from 1933 until joining the Army in 1940. His Language, Truth and Logic was published in 1936, and The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge in 1940. After war service he returned to Oxford in 1945, and became Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic at University College, London, the following (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  15
    Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic.Oswald Hanfling - 1986 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20:261-283.
    When, in 1979, A. J. Ayer was asked for an evaluation of his youthful Language, Truth and Logic (LTL), he replied: ‘I suppose the most important of the defects was that nearly all of it was false’. Like many of the claims in the book itself, this verdict is open to question. What was wrong with LTL was not so much that what it said was false, but that it presented philosophical issues in an excessively simple and aggressive way. Yet (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  2
    Causes and effect.Oswald Hanfling - 1973 - [Milton Keynes]: Open University Press.
  39.  85
    Fact, fiction and feeling.Oswald Hanfling - 1996 - British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (4):356-366.
    I consider and reject two kinds of solution of the problem of feelings about fictional objects: that the relevant beliefs are not really different as between fiction and fact; and that the relevant feelings are not 'really the same'. The problem should be seen in the context of different phases in acquiring the relevant feeling-concepts and I distinguish three such phases. The first is necessarily 'presentational': the child is presented with suitable objects or pictures and responds with appropriate feelings, without (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  5
    Fact, Fiction And Feeling.Oswald Hanfling - 1996 - British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (4):356-366.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  4
    Fundamental problems in philosophy.Oswald Hanfling (ed.) - 1972 - Oxford,: Blackwell.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  27
    Hume and Wittgenstein.Oswald Hanfling - 1975 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 9:47-65.
    It is well known that Wittgenstein's reading of the philosophical classics was patchy. He left unread a large part of the literature which most philosophers would regard as essential to a knowledge of their subject. Wittgenstein gave an interesting reason for his non-reading of Hume. He said that he could not sit down and read Hume, because he knew far too much about the subject of Hume's writings to find this anything but a torture. In a recent commentary, Peter Hacker (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  22
    ‘Is’, ‘Ought’ and the Voluntaristic Fallacy.Oswald Hanfling - 1997 - Philosophy 72 (282):537.
    The view that ‘ought’ cannot be deduced from ‘is’, credited to Hume as a major insight into the nature of morality, is surprisingly easy to refute. What they are doing is evil. Therefore, they ought not to do it. Here we have a case of deducing ‘ought’ from ‘is’. The conclusion follows, because ‘ought not’ is analytic to ‘evil’. ‘Ah, but that's just what is wrong with the example: the premise is not a pure “is”; it contains an “ought”, though (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    Life and Meaning: A Philosophical Reader.Oswald Hanfling (ed.) - 1987 - New York, NY, USA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Life and Meaning surveys a variety of Philosophical answers to the question, 'What makes life worth living?' By collecting readings from a wide range of philosophical history it gives the various perspectives on the value and meaning of life. Aspects of life which appear to make it meaningless 9death, suffering, randomness) are seen in the light of their long and varied history in philosophical literature and are subjected to careful scrutiny. The texts chosen here pose these and related issues and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  2
    Thought and Reality: Central Themes in Wittgenstein's Philosophy] Course Team. central themes in Wittgenstein's philosophy. Language and the privacy of experience.Oswald Hanfling - 1976
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Logical Positivism, Essential Readings in Logical Positivism.O. Hanfling - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 172 (1):103-104.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  54
    Machines as Persons?Oswald Hanfling - 1991 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 29:25-34.
    The subject of this symposium is sometimes introduced by asking whether machines could think. This way of introducing it may be misleading, for it may seem as if it were merely about a particular activity, called ‘thinking’. The question would then seem to have the same character as ‘Can machines make a noise?’. But thinking is not something that can be treated in isolation from other personal qualities. What we need to consider is whether, or to what extent, a machine (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Mental images.Oswald Hanfling - 1969 - Analysis 30 (April):166-173.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Mental images.O. Hanfling - 1969 - Analysis 29 (5):166.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Moral knowledge and moral uncertainty.Oswald Hanfling - 2008 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (2):105–123.
    Applying a broadly Wittgensteinian view of knowledge and its relation to the conditions in which the word “know” is ordinarily used, the paper defends the claim that there can be knowledge in moral matters and rejects the idea that a cross‐culturally homogeneous moral language is a necessary condition for this. However, the fact that moral knowledge is available sometimes does not imply that it is available always. Taking issue in particular with Ronald Dworkin, the paper also argues that where moral (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 93