Results for 'Non-reflecting stationary set of ordinals'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  29
    Reflecting stationary sets and successors of singular cardinals.Saharon Shelah - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (1):25-53.
    REF is the statement that every stationary subset of a cardinal reflects, unless it fails to do so for a trivial reason. The main theorem, presented in Sect. 0, is that under suitable assumptions it is consistent that REF and there is a κ which is κ+n -supercompact. The main concepts defined in Sect. 1 are PT, which is a certain statement about the existence of transversals, and the “bad” stationary set. It is shown that supercompactness (and even (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  2.  40
    Indestructibility and stationary reflection.Arthur W. Apter - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):228-236.
    If κ < λ are such that κ is a strong cardinal whose strongness is indestructible under κ -strategically closed forcing and λ is weakly compact, then we show thatA = {δ < κ | δ is a non-weakly compact Mahlo cardinal which reflects stationary sets}must be unbounded in κ. This phenomenon, however, need not occur in a universe with relatively few large cardinals. In particular, we show how to construct a model where no cardinal is supercompact up to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  62
    Reflecting stationary sets.Menachem Magidor - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):755-771.
    We prove that the statement "For every pair A, B, stationary subsets of ω 2 , composed of points of cofinality ω, there exists an ordinal α such that both A ∩ α and $B \bigcap \alpha$ are stationary subsets of α" is equiconsistent with the existence of weakly compact cardinal. (This completes results of Baumgartner and Harrington and Shelah.) We also prove, assuming the existence of infinitely many supercompact cardinals, the statement "Every stationary subset of ω (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  4.  38
    Dense non-reflection for stationary collections of countable sets.David Asperó, John Krueger & Yasuo Yoshinobu - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (1):94-108.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Full reflection of stationary sets below ℵω.Thomas Jech & Saharon Shelah - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):822 - 830.
    It is consistent that, for every n ≥ 2, every stationary subset of ω n consisting of ordinals of cofinality ω k, where k = 0 or k ≤ n - 3, reflects fully in the set of ordinals of cofinality ω n - 1. We also show that this result is best possible.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6.  13
    Full Reflection of Stationary Sets Below $aleph_omega$.Thomas Jech & Saharon Shelah - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):822-830.
    It is consistent that, for every $n \geq 2$, every stationary subset of $\omega_n$ consisting of ordinals of cofinality $\omega_k$, where $k = 0$ or $k \leq n - 3$, reflects fully in the set of ordinals of cofinality $\omega_{n - 1}$. We also show that this result is best possible.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  14
    Stationary sets added when forcing squares.Maxwell Levine - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (7-8):909-916.
    Current research in set theory raises the possibility that \ can be made compatible with some stationary reflection, depending on the parameter \. The purpose of this paper is to demonstrate the difficulty in such results. We prove that the poset \\), which adds a \-sequence by initial segments, will also add non-reflecting stationary sets concentrating in any given cofinality below \. We also investigate the CMB poset, which adds \ in a slightly different way. We prove (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  65
    Indestructibility and level by level equivalence and inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (1):78-85.
    If κ < λ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, it is known from [4] that {δ < κ | δ is a measurable cardinal which is not a limit of measurable cardinals and δ violates level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness}must be unbounded in κ. On the other hand, using a variant of the argument used to establish this fact, it is possible to prove that if κ < λ are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  22
    Indestructible strong compactness and level by level inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (4-5):371-377.
    If are such that δ is indestructibly supercompact and γ is measurable, then it must be the case that level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points to this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of cardinals such that κ1 is λ‐supercompact and λ is inaccessible, there is a model for level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal in which κ’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  17
    Characterizing strong compactness via strongness.Arthur W. Apter - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (4):375.
    We construct a model in which the strongly compact cardinals can be non-trivially characterized via the statement “κ is strongly compact iff κ is a measurable limit of strong cardinals”. If our ground model contains large enough cardinals, there will be supercompact cardinals in the universe containing this characterization of the strongly compact cardinals.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  18
    Level by level equivalence and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):51.
    We force and construct models in which there are non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals which aren't measurable limits of strongly compact cardinals and in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds non-trivially except at strongly compact cardinals. In these models, every measurable cardinal κ which isn't either strongly compact or a witness to a certain phenomenon first discovered by Menas is such that for every regular cardinal λ > κ, κ is λ strongly compact iff κ is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  60
    Indestructibility, instances of strong compactness, and level by level inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (7-8):725-741.
    Suppose λ > κ is measurable. We show that if κ is either indestructibly supercompact or indestructibly strong, then A = {δ < κ | δ is measurable, yet δ is neither δ + strongly compact nor a limit of measurable cardinals} must be unbounded in κ. The large cardinal hypothesis on λ is necessary, as we further demonstrate by constructing via forcing two models in which ${A = \emptyset}$ . The first of these contains a supercompact cardinal κ and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  43
    Supercompactness and level by level equivalence are compatible with indestructibility for strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):155-163.
    It is known that if $\kappa < \lambda$ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, then level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points towards this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, there is a model for level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal κ in which κ’s strong compactness is indestructible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  25
    Some remarks on indestructibility and Hamkins? lottery preparation.Arthur W. Apter - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (8):717-735.
    .In this paper, we first prove several general theorems about strongness, supercompactness, and indestructibility, along the way giving some new applications of Hamkins’ lottery preparation forcing to indestructibility. We then show that it is consistent, relative to the existence of cardinals κ<λ so that κ is λ supercompact and λ is inaccessible, for the least strongly compact cardinal κ to be the least strong cardinal and to have its strongness, but not its strong compactness, indestructible under κ-strategically closed forcing.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  51
    Level by level inequivalence beyond measurability.Arthur W. Apter - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (7-8):707-712.
    We construct models containing exactly one supercompact cardinal in which level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds. In each model, above the supercompact cardinal, there are finitely many strongly compact cardinals, and the strongly compact and measurable cardinals precisely coincide.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  57
    Identity crises and strong compactness III: Woodin cardinals. [REVIEW]Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (3):307-322.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to n ∈ ω supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact and measurable Woodin cardinals to coincide precisely. In particular, it is consistent for the first n strongly compact cardinals to be the first n measurable Woodin cardinals, with no cardinal above the n th strongly compact cardinal being measurable. In addition, we show that it is consistent, relative to a proper class of supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact cardinals and the cardinals which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  16
    Separating diagonal stationary reflection principles.Gunter Fuchs & Chris Lambie-Hanson - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (1):262-292.
    We introduce three families of diagonal reflection principles for matrices of stationary sets of ordinals. We analyze both their relationships among themselves and their relationships with other known principles of simultaneous stationary reflection, the strong reflection principle, and the existence of square sequences.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  14
    Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice.Paul Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):299-306.
    Working in the context of restricted forms of the Axiom of Choice, we consider the problem of splitting the ordinals below λ of cofinality θ into λ many stationary sets, where θ < λ are regular cardinals. This is a continuation of [4].
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  22
    Reflection of stationary sets and the tree property at the successor of a singular cardinal.Laura Fontanella & Menachem Magidor - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (1):272-291.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  16
    Two Upper Bounds on Consistency Strength of $negsquare{aleph_{omega}}$ and Stationary Set Reflection at Two Successive $aleph{n}$.Martin Zeman - 2017 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (3):409-432.
    We give modest upper bounds for consistency strengths for two well-studied combinatorial principles. These bounds range at the level of subcompact cardinals, which is significantly below a κ+-supercompact cardinal. All previously known upper bounds on these principles ranged at the level of some degree of supercompactness. We show that by using any of the standard modified Prikry forcings it is possible to turn a measurable subcompact cardinal into ℵω and make the principle □ℵω,<ω fail in the generic extension. We also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  51
    Possible behaviours of the reflection ordering of stationary sets.Jiří Witzany - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):534-547.
    If S, T are stationary subsets of a regular uncountable cardinal κ, we say that S reflects fully in $T, S , if for almost all α ∈ T (except a nonstationary set) S ∩ α is stationary in α. This relation is known to be a well-founded partial ordering. We say that a given poset P is realized by the reflection ordering if there is a maximal antichain $\langle X_p; p \in P\rangle$ of stationary subsets of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  9
    Forcing axioms, approachability, and stationary set reflection.Sean D. Cox - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):499-530.
    We prove a variety of theorems about stationary set reflection and concepts related to internal approachability. We prove that an implication of Fuchino–Usuba relating stationary reflection to a version of Strong Chang’s Conjecture cannot be reversed; strengthen and simplify some results of Krueger about forcing axioms and approachability; and prove that some other related results of Krueger are sharp. We also adapt some ideas of Woodin to simplify and unify many arguments in the literature involving preservation of forcing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  6
    Two-Cardinal Derived Topologies, Indescribability and Ramseyness.Brent Cody, Chris Lambie-Hanson & Jing Zhang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-29.
    We introduce a natural two-cardinal version of Bagaria’s sequence of derived topologies on ordinals. We prove that for our sequence of two-cardinal derived topologies, limit points of sets can be characterized in terms of a new iterated form of pairwise simultaneous reflection of certain kinds of stationary sets, the first few instances of which are often equivalent to notions related to strong stationarity, which has been studied previously in the context of strongly normal ideals. The non-discreteness of these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  28
    The stationary set splitting game.Paul B. Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (2):187-193.
    The stationary set splitting game is a game of perfect information of length ω1 between two players, unsplit and split, in which unsplit chooses stationarily many countable ordinals and split tries to continuously divide them into two stationary pieces. We show that it is possible in ZFC to force a winning strategy for either player, or for neither. This gives a new counterexample to Σ22 maximality with a predicate for the nonstationary ideal on ω1, and an example (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  39
    Splitting stationary sets in.Toshimichi Usuba - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):49-62.
    Let A be a non-empty set. A set $S\subseteq \mathcal{P}(A)$ is said to be stationary in $\mathcal{P}(A)$ if for every f: [A] <ω → A there exists x ∈ S such that x ≠ A and f"[x] <ω ⊆ x. In this paper we prove the following: For an uncountable cardinal λ and a stationary set S in \mathcal{P}(\lambda) , if there is a regular uncountable cardinal κ ≤ λ such that {x ∈ S: x ⋂ κ ∈ (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  68
    A relative of the approachability ideal, diamond and non-saturation.Assaf Rinot - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (3):1035-1065.
    Let λ denote a singular cardinal. Zeman, improving a previous result of Shelah, proved that $\square _{\lambda}^{\ast}$ together with 2 λ = λ⁺ implies $\lozenge _{S}$ for every S ⊆ λ⁺ that reflects stationarily often. In this paper, for a set S ⊆ λ⁺, a normal subideal of the weak approachability ideal is introduced, and denoted by I[S; λ]. We say that the ideal is fat if it contains a stationary set. It is proved: 1. if I[S; λ] is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  17
    Covering theorems for the core model, and an application to stationary set reflection.Sean Cox - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (1):66-93.
    We prove covering theorems for K, where K is the core model below the sharp for a strong cardinal, and give an application to stationary set reflection.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28.  13
    The usefulness of the useless.Nuccio Ordine - 2017 - Philadelphia: Paul Dry Books.
    “A little masterpiece of originality and clarity.”—George Steiner “A necessary book.”—Roberto Saviano “A wonderful little book that will delight you.”—François Busnel International Best Seller / Now in English for the First Time In this thought-provoking and extremely timely work, Nuccio Ordine convincingly argues for the utility of useless knowledge and against the contemporary fixation on utilitarianism—for the fundamental importance of the liberal arts and against the damage caused by their neglect. Inspired by the reflections of great philosophers and writers (e.g., (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  14
    The Diagonal Strong Reflection Principle and its Fragments.C. O. X. Sean D. & Gunter Fuchs - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (3):1281-1309.
    A diagonal version of the strong reflection principle is introduced, along with fragments of this principle associated with arbitrary forcing classes. The relationships between the resulting principles and related principles, such as the corresponding forcing axioms and the corresponding fragments of the strong reflection principle, are analyzed, and consequences are presented. Some of these consequences are “exact” versions of diagonal stationary reflection principles of sets of ordinals. We also separate some of these diagonal strong reflection principles from related (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  19
    Guessing and non-guessing of canonical functions.David Asperó - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 146 (2):150-179.
    It is possible to control to a large extent, via semiproper forcing, the parameters measuring the guessing density of the members of any given antichain of stationary subsets of ω1 . Here, given a pair of ordinals, we will say that a stationary set Sω1 has guessing density if β0=γ and , where γ is, for every stationary S*ω1, the infimum of the set of ordinals τ≤ω1+1 for which there is a function with ot)<τ for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  49
    On splitting stationary subsets of large cardinals.James E. Baumgartner, Alan D. Taylor & Stanley Wagon - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):203-214.
    Let κ denote a regular uncountable cardinal and NS the normal ideal of nonstationary subsets of κ. Our results concern the well-known open question whether NS fails to be κ + -saturated, i.e., are there κ + stationary subsets of κ with pairwise intersections nonstationary? Our first observation is: Theorem. NS is κ + -saturated iff for every normal ideal J on κ there is a stationary set $A \subseteq \kappa$ such that $J = NS \mid A = (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  32.  18
    The order of reflection.Juan P. Aguilera - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (4):1555-1583.
    Extending Aanderaa’s classical result that $\pi ^{1}_{1} < \sigma ^{1}_{1}$, we determine the order between any two patterns of iterated $\Sigma ^{1}_{1}$ - and $\Pi ^{1}_{1}$ -reflection on ordinals. We show that this order of linear reflection is a prewellordering of length $\omega ^{\omega }$. This requires considering the relationship between linear and some non-linear reflection patterns, such as $\sigma \wedge \pi $, the pattern of simultaneous $\Sigma ^{1}_{1}$ - and $\Pi ^{1}_{1}$ -reflection. The proofs involve linking the lengths (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  33
    Canonical structure in the universe of set theory: Part two.James Cummings, Matthew Foreman & Menachem Magidor - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 142 (1):55-75.
    We prove a number of consistency results complementary to the ZFC results from our paper [J. Cummings, M. Foreman, M. Magidor, Canonical structure in the universe of set theory: part one, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 129 211–243]. We produce examples of non-tightly stationary mutually stationary sequences, sequences of cardinals on which every sequence of sets is mutually stationary, and mutually stationary sequences not concentrating on a fixed cofinality. We also give an alternative proof for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  34.  44
    Intuitionistic sets and ordinals.Paul Taylor - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):705-744.
    Transitive extensional well founded relations provide an intuitionistic notion of ordinals which admits transfinite induction. However these ordinals are not directed and their successor operation is poorly behaved, leading to problems of functoriality. We show how to make the successor monotone by introducing plumpness, which strengthens transitivity. This clarifies the traditional development of successors and unions, making it intuitionistic; even the (classical) proof of trichotomy is made simpler. The definition is, however, recursive, and, as their name suggests, the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  17
    Characterizations of ordinal analysis.James Walsh - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (4):103230.
    Ordinal analysis is a research program wherein recursive ordinals are assigned to axiomatic theories. According to conventional wisdom, ordinal analysis measures the strength of theories. Yet what is the attendant notion of strength? In this paper we present abstract characterizations of ordinal analysis that address this question. -/- First, we characterize ordinal analysis as a partition of $\Sigma^1_1$-definable and $\Pi^1_1$-sound theories, namely, the partition whereby two theories are equivalent if they have the same proof-theoretic ordinal. We show that no (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  35
    Strong Compactness and Stationary Sets.John Krueger - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):767 - 777.
    We construct a model in which there is a strongly compact cardinal κ such that the set $S(\kappa,\kappa ^{+})=\{a\in P_{\kappa}\kappa ^{-}\colon o,t(a)=(a\cap \kappa)^{+}\})$ is non-stationary.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  14
    New methods in forcing iteration and applications.Rahman Mohammadpour - 2023 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 29 (2):300-302.
    The Theme. Strong forcing axioms like Martin’s Maximum give a reasonably satisfactory structural analysis of $H(\omega _2)$. A broad program in modern Set Theory is searching for strong forcing axioms beyond $\omega _1$. In other words, one would like to figure out the structural properties of taller initial segments of the universe. However, the classical techniques of forcing iterations seem unable to bypass the obstacles, as the resulting forcings axioms beyond $\omega _1$ have not thus far been strong enough! However, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  52
    Destructibility of stationary subsets of Pκλ.Sakaé Fuchino & Greg Piper - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (6):560-569.
    For a regular cardinal κ with κ<κ = κ and κ ≤ λ , we construct generically a subset S of {x ∈ Pκλ : x ∩ κ is a singular ordinal} such that S is stationary in a strong sense but the stationarity of S can be destroyed by a κ+-c. c. forcing ℙ* which does not add any new element of Pκλ . Actually ℙ* can be chosen so that ℙ* is κ-strategically closed. However we show that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  13
    Sigma-Prikry forcing II: Iteration Scheme.Alejandro Poveda, Assaf Rinot & Dima Sinapova - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 22 (3):2150019.
    In Part I of this series [A. Poveda, A. Rinot and D. Sinapova, Sigma-Prikry forcing I: The axioms, Canad. J. Math. 73(5) (2021) 1205–1238], we introduced a class of notions of forcing which we call [Formula: see text]-Prikry, and showed that many of the known Prikry-type notions of forcing that center around singular cardinals of countable cofinality are [Formula: see text]-Prikry. We showed that given a [Formula: see text]-Prikry poset [Formula: see text] and a [Formula: see text]-name for a non- (...) stationary set [Formula: see text], there exists a corresponding [Formula: see text]-Prikry poset that projects to [Formula: see text] and kills the stationarity of [Formula: see text]. In this paper, we develop a general scheme for iterating [Formula: see text]-Prikry posets and, as an application, we blow up the power of a countable limit of Laver-indestructible supercompact cardinals, and then iteratively kill all non-reflecting stationary subsets of its successor. This yields a model in which the singular cardinal hypothesis fails and simultaneous reflection of finite families of stationary sets holds. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  10
    Sigma-Prikry forcing II: Iteration Scheme.Alejandro Poveda, Assaf Rinot & Dima Sinapova - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 22 (3).
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Volume 22, Issue 03, December 2022. In Part I of this series [A. Poveda, A. Rinot and D. Sinapova, Sigma-Prikry forcing I: The axioms, Canad. J. Math. 73(5) (2021) 1205–1238], we introduced a class of notions of forcing which we call [math]-Prikry, and showed that many of the known Prikry-type notions of forcing that center around singular cardinals of countable cofinality are [math]-Prikry. We showed that given a [math]-Prikry poset [math] and a [math]-name for a non- (...) stationary set [math], there exists a corresponding [math]-Prikry poset that projects to [math] and kills the stationarity of [math]. In this paper, we develop a general scheme for iterating [math]-Prikry posets and, as an application, we blow up the power of a countable limit of Laver-indestructible supercompact cardinals, and then iteratively kill all non-reflecting stationary subsets of its successor. This yields a model in which the singular cardinal hypothesis fails and simultaneous reflection of finite families of stationary sets holds. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  14
    Square below a non-weakly compact cardinal.Hazel Brickhill - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (3-4):409-426.
    In his seminal paper introducing the fine structure of L, Jensen proved that under \ any regular cardinal that reflects stationary sets is weakly compact. In this paper we give a new proof of Jensen’s result that is straight-forward and accessible to those without a knowledge of Jensen’s fine structure theory. The proof here instead uses hyperfine structure, a very natural and simpler alternative to fine structure theory introduced by Friedman and Koepke.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  21
    Rado's Conjecture implies that all stationary set preserving forcings are semiproper.Philipp Doebler - 2013 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 13 (1):1350001.
    Todorčević showed that Rado's Conjecture implies CC*, a strengthening of Chang's Conjecture. We generalize this by showing that also CC**, a global version of CC*, follows from RC. As a corollary we obtain that RC implies Semistationary Reflection and, i.e. the statement that all forcings that preserve the stationarity of subsets of ω1 are semiproper.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  53
    Non‐saturation of the non‐stationary ideal on Pκ (λ) with λ of countable cofinality.Pierre Matet - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (1-2):38-45.
    Given a regular uncountable cardinal κ and a cardinal λ > κ of cofinality ω, we show that the restriction of the non-stationary ideal on Pκ to the set of all a with equation image is not λ++-saturated . We actually prove the stronger result that there is equation image with |Q| = λ++ such that A∩B is a non-cofinal subset of Pκ for any two distinct members A, B of Q, where NGκ, λ denotes the game ideal on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  48
    Large cardinals and definable counterexamples to the continuum hypothesis.Matthew Foreman & Menachem Magidor - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76 (1):47-97.
    In this paper we consider whether L(R) has “enough information” to contain a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis. We believe this question provides deep insight into the difficulties surrounding the continuum hypothesis. We show sufficient conditions for L(R) not to contain such a counterexample. Along the way we establish many results about nonstationary towers, non-reflecting stationary sets, generalizations of proper and semiproper forcing and Chang's conjecture.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  45.  19
    Stationary logic of ordinals.Alan H. Mekler - 1984 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 26 (1):47-68.
  46.  42
    μ-complete Souslin trees on μ+.Menachem Kojman & Saharon Shelah - 1993 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 32 (3):195-201.
    We prove thatµ=µ <µ , 2 µ =µ + and “there is a non-reflecting stationary subset ofµ + composed of ordinals of cofinality <μ” imply that there is a μ-complete Souslin tree onµ +.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  41
    Simultaneous stationary reflection and square sequences.Yair Hayut & Chris Lambie-Hanson - 2017 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 17 (2):1750010.
    We investigate the relationship between weak square principles and simultaneous reflection of stationary sets.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  48.  15
    Non‐circular, non‐well‐founded set universes.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):454-460.
    We show that there are universes of sets which contain descending ϵ-sequences of length α for every ordinal α, though they do not contain any ϵ-cycle. It is also shown that there is no set universe containing a descending ϵ-sequence of length On. MSC: 03E30; 03E65.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  12
    Higher indescribability and derived topologies.Brent Cody - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 24 (1).
    We introduce reflection properties of cardinals in which the attributes that reflect are expressible by infinitary formulas whose lengths can be strictly larger than the cardinal under consideration. This kind of generalized reflection principle leads to the definitions of [Formula: see text]-indescribability and [Formula: see text]-indescribability of a cardinal [Formula: see text] for all [Formula: see text]. In this context, universal [Formula: see text] formulas exist, there is a normal ideal associated to [Formula: see text]-indescribability and the notions of [Formula: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  14
    Countable OD sets of reals belong to the ground model.Vladimir Kanovei & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (3-4):285-298.
    It is true in the Cohen, Solovay-random, dominaning, and Sacks generic extension, that every countable ordinal-definable set of reals belongs to the ground universe. It is true in the Solovay collapse model that every non-empty OD countable set of sets of reals consists of \ elements.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000