Results for 'Natural Goodness'

998 found
Order:
  1.  29
    The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences.David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer - 1989 - Cambridge University Press. Edited by David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer.
    Contributors; Preface; Introduction; Part I. Instruments in Experiments: 1. Scientific instruments: models of brass and aids to discovery; 2. Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of experiment; 3. A viol of water or a wedge of glass; Part II. Experiment and Argument: 4. Galileo’s experimental discourse; 5. Fresnel, Poisson and the white spot: the role of successful predictions in the acceptance of scientific theories; 6. The rhetoric of experiment; Part III. Representing and Realising: 7. ’Magnetic curves’ and the magnetic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  2.  3
    After awareness: the end of the path.Greg Goode - 2016 - Oakland, CA: Non-Duality Press, an imprint of New Harbinger Publications.
    The author offers an accessible, non-dogmatic guide to sharing secrets of the Direct Path that are rarely revealed. Rather than a prescriptive, step-by-step book, After Awareness is a presentation of how the Direct Path works, examining lesser-known aspects of the path and providing context, examples, and critiques of its methods. You'll learn how to use the tools of non-dual self-inquiry-as well as when to discard them-and find a set of less doctrinaire terms and pointers for discussing non-dual awareness and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  11
    Nature-of-science literacy in benchmarks and standards: Post-modern/relativist or modern/realist?Ron Good & James Shymansky - 2001 - Science & Education 10 (1-2):173-185.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  4.  57
    How do Scientists Reach Agreement about Novel Observations?David Gooding - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (2):205.
    I outline a pragmatic view of scientists' use of observation which draws attention to non-discursive, instrumental and social contexts of observation, in order to explain scientists' agreement about the appearance and significance of new phenomena. I argue that: observation is embedded in a network of activities, techniques, and interests; that experimentalists make construals of new phenomena which enable them communicate exploratory techniques and their outcomes, and that empirical enquiry consists of communicative, exploratory and predictive strategies whose interdependence ensures that, notwithstanding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  5.  14
    Nature in American Philosophy (review).James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (3):541-547.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  4
    The Predictive Value of the NEO-FFI Items: Parsing the Nature of Social Anhedonia Using the Revised Social Anhedonia Scale and the ACIPS.Diane C. Gooding, Emily R. Padrutt & Madeline J. Pflum - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. How Scientists Reach Agreement about New Observations.David Gooding - 1986 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986:236-244.
    I outline a pragmatic view of scientists' use of observation which draws attention to non-discursive, instrumental and social contexts of observation, in order to explain scientists' agreement about the appearance and significance of new phenomena. I argue that: observation is embedded in a network of activities, techniques, and interests; that experimentalists make construals of new phenomena which enable them communicate exploratory techniques and their outcomes, and that empirical enquiry consists of communicative, exploratory and predictive strategies whose interdependence ensures that, notwithstanding (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  22
    Images of Anarchy: The Rhetoric and Science in Hobbes’s State of Nature, written by Evrigenis, Ioannis.Nicholas Gooding - 2015 - Hobbes Studies 28 (2):175-183.
  9.  15
    Metaphysics versus measurement: The conversion and conservation of force in Faraday's physics.David Gooding - 1980 - Annals of Science 37 (1):1-29.
    SummaryFaraday's concept of force is described by six assumptions. These specify a concept that is quite distinct from ‘mechanical’ conceptions of his contemporaries and interpreters. Analysis of the role of these assumptions clarifies Faraday's weighting of experimental evidence and shows how closely-linked Faraday's chemistry and physics were to his theology. It is argued that Faraday was unable to secularize his concept of force by breaking the ties between his physics and his theology of nature. Examination of his basic assumptions also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  4
    How Scientists reach Agreement about new Observations.David Gooding - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):236-244.
    Epistemology has been socialised. Cognitive and social interactions between observers are now as important as their interventions into the course of nature. This contrasts with traditional views of how we get natural facts into our discourse about nature. These assumed the efficacy of individual observers’ causal interactions with the natural world, making their interactions with other observers irrelevant. Kant’s conclusion that empirical access depends also upon our concepts did not challenge the individualistic character of the epistemology of science. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  11
    Experiment.David C. Gooding - 2017 - In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 117–126.
    There have been many images of experiment. The contemplative narratives of Aristotle served to illustrate hypotheses and arguments. There was no expectation that they be performed. Even in Galileo's dialogues, the distinction between real experiments and imaginary ones is not sharp (see galileo). During the seventeenth century, performance and public description became essential to the probative power of experiment. These made its methods and procedures transparent, allowing any reader of the narrative to be a virtual witness of an active demonstration (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  39
    Theory and observation: The experimental nexus.David Gooding - 1990 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (2):131 – 148.
    Abstract Philosophical discussions of experiment usually focus exclusively on testing predictions. In this paper I compare G. Morpurgo's experimental test of the Gell?Mann/ Zweig quark hypothesis with two neglected uses of experiment: constructing representations of new phenomena and inventing the instruments that produce such phenomena. These roles are illustrated by J. B. Biot's 1821 observations of electromagnetism and by Michael Faraday's invention of the first electromagnetic motor, also in 1821. The comparison identifies similarities between observation and experiment, showing how both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Reproductive Success.Why Do Good Hunters Have Higher - 2004 - Human Nature 15 (4):343-364.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  25
    Review: Nature in american philosophy. [REVIEW]James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (3):pp. 541-547.
    Although he had intermittently toiled over his translation of Hegel's Science of Logic for nearly half a century without finding a publisher, Henry Conrad Brokmeyer, the petulant visionary of St. Louis Hegelian fame, concluded it was naive to expect an infant nation to devote itself to philosophical reflection while it was "carving civilization out of wilderness." Brokmeyer's difficulties may have had more to do with his disdain for the grammatical and spelling conventions of the English language than he cared to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  27
    General Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture. Edited by Barry Barnes and Steven Shapin. London and Beverly Hills: Sage, 1979. pp. 225. £10.00/£4.25. [REVIEW]David Gooding - 1981 - British Journal for the History of Science 14 (1):84-86.
  16. Jean de Groot, ed., Nature in American Philosophy. [REVIEW]James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (3):541-547.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  31
    Postmodernism and Science Education: An Appraisal.Jim Mackenzie, Ron Good & James Robert Brown - 2014 - In Michael R. Matthews (ed.), International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer. pp. 1057-1086.
    Over the past 50 years, postmodernism has been a progressively growing and influential intellectual movement inside and outside the academy. Postmodernism is characterised by rejection of parts or the whole of the Enlightenment project that had its roots in the birth and embrace of early modern science. While Enlightenment and ‘modernist’ ideas of universalism, of intellectual and cultural progress, of the possibility of finding truths about the natural and social world and of rejection of absolutism and authoritarianism in politics, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  44
    Design as communication: exploring the validity and utility of relating intention to interpretation.Nathan Crilly, David Good, Derek Matravers & P. John Clarkson - unknown
    This explores the role of intention in interpreting designed artefacts. The relationship between how designers intend products to be interpreted and how they are subsequently interpreted has often been represented as a process of communication. However, such representations are attacked for allegedly implying that designers' intended meanings are somehow ‘contained’ in products and that those meanings are passively received by consumers. Instead, critics argue that consumers actively construct their own meanings as they engage with products, and therefore that designers' intentions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  53
    Women Who Know Their Place.Ariane Burke, Anne Kandler & David Good - 2012 - Human Nature 23 (2):133-148.
    Differences between men and women in the performance of tests designed to measure spatial abilities are explained by evolutionary psychologists in terms of adaptive design. The Hunter-Gatherer Theory of Spatial Ability suggests that the adoption of a hunter-gatherer lifestyle (assuming a sexual division of labor) created differential selective pressure on the development of spatial skills in men and women and, therefore, cognitive differences between the sexes. Here, we examine a basic spatial skill—wayfinding (the ability to plan routes and navigate a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  53
    On understanding without words: Communication between a deaf-blind child and her parents. [REVIEW]David A. Goode - 1990 - Human Studies 13 (1):1 - 37.
    This paper is an empirical inquiry into the nature of human communication and understanding. It is organized into three sections. First, there is an overview of the ethnomethodological critique of mainstream social scientific research methodology and the relevance of this critique to clinical behavioral research. Second, the details of an ethnomethodological study of communication practices in a family with an alingual, deaf-blind child are provided. Third, implications of the case study are presented.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Nature, Every Last Drop, is Good.Alan Holland & British Association of Nature Conservationists - 1996 - Department of Philosophy, Lancaster University.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  5
    Motor Deficits in the Ipsilesional Arm of Severely Paretic Stroke Survivors Correlate With Functional Independence in Left, but Not Right Hemisphere Damage.Shanie A. L. Jayasinghe, David Good, David A. Wagstaff, Carolee Winstein & Robert L. Sainburg - 2020 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Chronic stroke survivors with severe contralesional arm paresis face numerous challenges to performing activities of daily living, which largely rely on the use of the less-affected ipsilesional arm. While use of the ipsilesional arm is often encouraged as a compensatory strategy in rehabilitation, substantial evidence indicates that motor control deficits in this arm can be functionally limiting, suggesting a role for remediation of this arm. Previous research has indicated that the nature of ipsilesional motor control deficits vary with hemisphere of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  9
    A mechanical microcosm.Bodily Passions & Good Manners - 1998 - In Christopher Lawrence & Steven Shapin (eds.), Science Incarnate: Historical Embodiments of Natural Knowledge. University of Chicago Press. pp. 51.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  6
    Remedial Training of the Less-Impaired Arm in Chronic Stroke Survivors With Moderate to Severe Upper-Extremity Paresis Improves Functional Independence: A Pilot Study.Candice Maenza, David A. Wagstaff, Rini Varghese, Carolee Winstein, David C. Good & Robert L. Sainburg - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 15.
    The ipsilesional arm of stroke patients often has functionally limiting deficits in motor control and dexterity that depend on the side of the brain that is lesioned and that increase with the severity of paretic arm impairment. However, remediation of the ipsilesional arm has yet to be integrated into the usual standard of care for upper limb rehabilitation in stroke, largely due to a lack of translational research examining the effects of ipsilesional-arm intervention. We now ask whether ipsilesional-arm training, tailored (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Natural goodness without natural history.Parisa Moosavi - 2022 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research:78-100.
    Neo‐Aristotelian ethical naturalism purports to show that moral evaluation of human action and character is an evaluation of natural goodness—a kind of evaluation that applies to living things in virtue of their nature and based on their form of life. The standard neo‐Aristotelian view defines natural goodness by way of generic statements describing the natural history, or the ‘characteristic’ life, of a species. In this paper, I argue that this conception of natural goodness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  65
    Natural Goodness, Sex, and the Perverted Faculty Argument.Christopher Arroyo - 2022 - Philosophy 97 (1):115-142.
    There is a longstanding and widely held view, often associated with Catholicism, that intrinsically nonprocreative human sex acts are intrinsically immoral. Some philosophers who hold this view, such as Edward Feser, claim that they can defend the view on purely philosophical grounds by relying on the perverted faculty argument. This paper argues that Feser's defense of the perverted faculty argument does not work because Feser fails to recognize the full implications of the species-dependence of natural goodness. By drawing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Natural goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Philippa Foot has for many years been one of the most distinctive and influential thinkers in moral philosophy. Long dissatisfied with the moral theories of her contemporaries, she has gradually evolved a theory of her own that is radically opposed not only to emotivism and prescriptivism but also to the whole subjectivist, anti-naturalist movement deriving from David Hume. Dissatisfied with both Kantian and utilitarian ethics, she claims to have isolated a special form of evaluation that predicates goodness and defect (...)
  28. Natural Goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (3):604-606.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   353 citations  
  29. Natural goodness and natural evil.Joseph Millum - 2006 - Ratio 19 (2):199–213.
    In Natural Goodness Philippa Foot gives an analysis of the concepts we use to describe the characteristics of living things. She suggests that we describe them in functional terms, and this allows us to judge organisms as good or defective depending on how well they perform their distinctive functions. Foot claims that we can judge intentional human actions in the same way: the virtues contribute in obvious ways to good human functioning, and this provides us with grounds for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30. Natural Goodness.Philippa Foot & Peter Geach - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):621-631.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  31.  39
    Natural Goodness.M. Slote - 2003 - Mind 112 (445):130-139.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  32. Natural goodness, rightness, and the intersubjectivity of reason: Reply to Arroyo, Cummiskey, Moland, and Bird-pollan.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (4):381-394.
    Abstract: In response to Arroyo, I explain my position on the concept of “natural goodness” and how my use of that concept compares to that of Geach and Foot. An Aristotelian or functional notion of goodness provides the material for Kantian endorsement in a theory of value that avoids a metaphysical commitment to intrinsic values. In response to Cummiskey, I review reasons for thinking Kantianism and consequentialism incompatible, especially those objections to aggregation that arise from the notion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  29
    The natural goodness of man: on the system of Rousseau's thought.Arthur M. Melzer - 1990 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    The true key to all the perplexities of the human condition, Rousseau boldly claims, is the “natural goodness of man.” It is also the key to his own notoriously contradictory writings, which, he insists, are actually the disassembled parts of a rigorous philosophical system rooted in that fundamental principle. What if this problematic claim—so often repeated, but as often dismissed—were resolutely followed and explored? Arthur M. Melzer adopts this approach in The Natural Goodness of Man. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  22
    Natural Goodness and the Normativity Challenge: Happiness Across Cultures.Sebastian Purcell - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:183-194.
    The present essay aims to respond to one of the most recent empirical challenges posed to an Aristotelian based virtue ethics. In the course of the debate concerning the existence of character traits a second and more recent challenge has emerged, which Jesse Prinz has called The Normativity Challenge. The argument in this case is that the empirical study of happiness undertaken by psychologists, sociologists and anthropologists, reveals that the end which virtues are supposed to support, namely happiness, is so (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  48
    Natural Goods in the Eudemian Ethics.Giulia Bonasio - 2021 - Ancient Philosophy 41 (1):123-142.
  36. The natural goodness of humanity.Joshua Cohen - 1997 - In Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman, Christine M. Korsgaard & John Rawls (eds.), Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls. Cambridge University Press. pp. 102--39.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37.  15
    ‘Normal’, ‘natural’, ‘good’ or ‘good‐enough’ birth: examining the concepts.Susanne Darra - 2009 - Nursing Inquiry 16 (4):297-305.
    In the face of increasing intervention in childbirth, ‘normal birth’ is currently being promoted by the World Health Organization, national governments, professional bodies and other organisations throughout the world. This paper takes a postmodernist stance and explores the idea of the ‘normal’ before going on to analyse normal childbirth, referring to concepts of the normal and the natural. It refers to historical developments in childbearing and lay organisations along with research relating to women’s views of childbirth, to question the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. From Biological Functions to Natural Goodness.Parisa Moosavi - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    Neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism aims to place moral virtue in the natural world by showing that moral goodness is an instance of natural goodness—a kind of goodness supposedly also found in the biological realm of plants and non-human animals. One of the central issues facing neo-Aristotelian naturalists concerns their commitment to a kind of function ascription based on the concept of the flourishing of an organism that seems to have no place in modern biology. In this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39. Is Nature Good? A Conversation.John Dewey - 1908 - Hibbert Journal 7:827.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  32
    "Natural Goodness" di Philippa Foot. Discussione.Piergiorgio Donatelli, Mario Ricciardi & Michael Thompson - 2003 - Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 16 (1):179-200.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. "All in Their Nature Good": Descartes on the Passions of the Soul.Marie Jayasekera - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (1):71-92.
    Descartes claims that the passions of the soul are “all in their nature good” even though they exaggerate the value of their objects, have the potential to deceive us, and often mislead us. What, then, can he mean by this? In this paper, I argue that these effects of the passions are only problematic when we incorrectly take their goodness to consist in their informing us of harms and benefits to the mind-body composite. Instead, the passions are good in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Natural goodness and abandoning the economy of value: Ron Sandler's character and environment.Allen Thompson - 2008 - Ethics, Place and Environment 11 (2):218-226.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  13
    Natural goodness and the political form of human life.Jan Müller - 2015 - Filozofija I Društvo 26 (3):565-592.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Three degrees of natural goodness.Michael Thompson - manuscript
    Philippa Foot’s Natural Goodness is among the most beautiful and moving works of moral philosophy yet produced in the analytic tradition. It is so much an integral whole that it will seem barbaric to do as I propose briefly to do, and put it to the scalpel. But Natural Goodness propounds a complex theory with many levels or strata, some of which even the author fails completely to distinguish. I will distinguish three strata, each depending logically (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  45. Natural Goods and Moral Beauty.Stephen Clark - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  9
    The natural goodness of man: On the system of Rousseau's thought.Susan M. Shell - 1994 - History of European Ideas 18 (4):623-624.
  47. Species Concepts and Natural Goodness.Judith K. Crane & Ronald Sandler - 2011 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Matthew H. Slater (eds.), Carving Nature at its Joints: Natural Kinds in Metaphysics and Science. MIT Press. pp. 289.
    This chapter defends a pluralist understanding of species on which a normative species concept is viable and can support natural goodness evaluations. The central question here is thus: Since organisms are to be evaluated as members of their species, how does a proper understanding of species affect the feasibility of natural goodness evaluations? Philippa Foot has argued for a form of natural goodness evaluation in which living things are evaluated by how well fitted they (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Three Degrees of Natural Goodness (Discussion note, Iride).Michael Thompson - unknown
    Philippa Foot’s Natural Goodness is among the most beautiful and moving works of moral philosophy yet produced in the analytic tradition. It is so much an integral whole that it will seem barbaric to do as I propose briefly to do, and put it to the scalpel. But Natural Goodness propounds a complex theory with many levels or strata, some of which even the author fails completely to distinguish. I will distinguish three strata, each depending logically (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  5
    Natural Goodness[REVIEW]Jennifer Welchman - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):874-875.
    Natural Goodness is an important new book from Phillippa Foot, a central figure in the revival of ethical naturalism and character-based ethics. A longstanding critic of the emotivist and prescriptivist theories that arose following twentieth-century analytic philosophy’s linguistic turn, Foot attacked reigning versions of noncognitivism according to which moral language and judgment made no meaningful claims about moral agents or their actions but were instead misleading expressions of a speaker’s attitudes. In classic papers such as “Moral Beliefs,” “Virtues (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  35
    Natural Goodness[REVIEW]H. O. Mounce - 2002 - International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (3):397-399.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 998