Results for 'Maaret Karttunen'

54 found
Order:
  1.  45
    Model theoretic results for infinitely deep languages.Maaret Karttunen - 1983 - Studia Logica 42 (2-3):223 - 241.
    We define a subhierarchy of the infinitely deep languagesN described by Jaakko Hintikka and Veikko Rantala. We shall show that some model theoretic results well-known in the model theory of the ordinary infinitary languages can be generalized for these new languages. Among these are the downward Löwenheim-Skolem and o's theorems as well as some compactness properties.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Syntax and semantics of questions.Lauri Karttunen - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1):3--44.
    W. Labov's & T. Labov's findings concerning their child grammar acquisition ("Learning the Syntax of Questions" in Recent Advances in the Psychology of Language, Campbell, R. & Smith, P. Eds, New York: Plenum Press, 1978) are interpreted in terms of different semantics of why & other wh-questions. Z. Dubiel.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   306 citations  
  3. What do referential indices refer to?Lauri Karttunen - 1968 - [Santa Monica, Calif.,: Rand Corp.].
  4.  16
    Definite Descriptions with Crossing Coreference: A Study of the Bach-Peters Paradox.Lauri Karttunen - 1971 - Foundations of Language 7 (2):157-182.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Ctesias in transmission and tradition.Klaus Karttunen - 1997 - Topoi 7 (2).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  70
    Conventional Implicature. Syntax and Semantics, Volume 11, Presupposition.Lauri Karttunen, Stanley Peters, Choon-kyu Oh, David A. Dinneen, Gerald Gazdar & Janet Dean Fodor - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):412-415.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    Die Polyphonie der Wirklichkeit: Erkenntnistheorie und Ontologie in der Theologie Dietrich Bonhoeffers.Tomi Karttunen - 2004 - Joensuu: Joensuun yliopisto.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  12
    India in Early Greek Literature.A. K. Narain & Klaus Karttunen - 1992 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 112 (3):515.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  9.  25
    India and the Hellenistic World.A. K. Narain & Klaus Karttunen - 1999 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 119 (3):496.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  9
    Vidyarnavavandanam: Essays in Honour of Asko Parpola.Ludo Rocher, Klaus Karttunen & Petteri Koskikallio - 2003 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 123 (4):929.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  9
    Determinants of Supply Chain Engagement in Carbon Management.Katrina Lintukangas, Heli Arminen, Anni-Kaisa Kähkönen & Elina Karttunen - 2022 - Journal of Business Ethics 186 (1):87-104.
    To fight climate change, firms must adopt effective and feasible carbon management practices that promote collaboration within supply chains. Engaging suppliers and customers on carbon management reduces vulnerability to climate-related risks and increases resilience and adaptability in supply chains. Therefore, it is important to understand the motives and preconditions for pursuing supply chain engagement from companies that actively engage with supply chain members in carbon management. In this study, a relational view is applied to operationalize the supply chain engagement concept (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. A solution to Karttunen's Problem.Matthew Mandelkern - 2017 - In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 21.
    There is a difference between the conditions in which one can felicitously assert a ‘must’-claim versus those in which one can use the corresponding non-modal claim. But it is difficult to pin down just what this difference amounts to. And it is even harder to account for this difference, since assertions of 'Must ϕ' and assertions of ϕ alone seem to have the same basic goal: namely, coming to agreement that [[ϕ]] is true. In this paper I take on this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13. lauri karttunen/Definite Descriptions with Crossing Corefe-rence. A Study of the Bach-Peters Paradox 157 S.-Y. kuroda/Two Remarks on Pronominalization 183 earl r. maccormac/Ostensive Instances in Language Learning 199 leonharu LiPKA/Grammatical Categories, Lexical Items and. [REVIEW]Interpretative Semantics Meets Frankenstein - 1971 - Foundations of Language 7:302.
  14.  53
    Lauri Karttunen and Stanley Peters. Conventional implicature. Syntax and semantics, Volume 11, Presupposition, edited by Choon-Kyu Oh and David A. Dinneen, Academic Press, New York, San Francisco, and London, 1979, pp. 1–56. - Gerald Gazdar. A solution to the projection problem. Syntax and semantics, Volume 11, Presupposition, edited by Choon-Kyu Oh and David A. Dinneen, Academic Press, New York, San Francisco, and London, 1979, pp. 57–89. - Janet Dean Fodor. In defense of the truth value gap. Syntax and semantics, Volume 11, Presupposition, edited by Choon-Kyu Oh and David A. Dinneen, Academic Press, New York, San Francisco, and London, 1979, pp. 199–224. - Ruth M. Kempson. Presupposition, opacity, and ambiguity. Syntax and semantics, Volume 11, Presupposition, edited by Choon-Kyu Oh and David A. Dinneen, Academic Press, New York, San Francisco, and London, 1979, pp. 283–297. - S. K. Thomason. Truth-value gaps, many truth values, and possible worlds. Syntax and semantics, Volume 11, P. [REVIEW]Tyler Burge - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):412-415.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  63
    A truth-conditional formulation of Karttunen's account of presupposition.Stanley Peters - 1979 - Synthese 40 (2):301-316.
    Karttunen's seminal 1973 article Presuppositions of compound sentences, lays the groundwork for the elegant and fruitful theory of this subject which he subsequently presented in (1974). In (1973, pp. 185–8), however, he fallaciously argued that the regularities he discovered concerning the behavior of and, or, and if ... then in English cannot be embodied in any three-valued logic giving a truth-functional interpretation to these connectives. The present paper refutes Karttunen's argument by exhibiting an interpretation with the desired properties, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  16.  27
    A Response to Karttunen on Questions.Michael Bennett - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (2):279 - 300.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  7
    India in Early Greek Literature. Klaus Karttunen. and India and the Hellenistic World. Klaus Karttunen.Chr Lindtner - 2002 - Buddhist Studies Review 19 (1):107-112.
    India in Early Greek Literature. Klaus Karttunen. Studia Orientalia 65, Helsinki 1989. vi, 295 pp. FIM 150. ISBN 951-9380-10-8. India and the Hellenistic World. Klaus Karttunen. Studia Orientalia 83, Helsinki 1997. x, 439 pp. FIM 200. ISBN 951-9380-35-3.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  32
    The Greeks and India Klaus Karttunen: India in Early Greek Literature. (Studia Orientalia, 65.) Pp. vi + 293; 3 maps. Helsinki: Finnish Oriental Society, 1989. Paper, Fmks. 150. [REVIEW]C. J. Tuplin - 1991 - The Classical Review 41 (02):385-386.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Parasitic attitudes.Emar Maier - 2015 - Linguistics and Philosophy 38 (3):205-236.
    Karttunen observes that a presupposition triggered inside an attitude ascription, can be filtered out by a seemingly inaccessible antecedent under the scope of a preceding belief ascription. This poses a major challenge for presupposition theory and the semantics of attitude ascriptions. I solve the problem by enriching the semantics of attitude ascriptions with some independently argued assumptions on the structure and interpretation of mental states. In particular, I propose a DRT-based representation of mental states with a global belief-layer and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20. Cross-linguistic semantics for questions.Maria Bittner - 1998 - Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (1):1-82.
    : The Hamblin-Karttunen approach has led to many insights about questions in English. In this article the results of this rule-by-rule tradition are reconsidered from a crosslinguistic perspective. Starting from the type-driven XLS theory developed in Bittner (1994a, b), it is argued that evidence from simple questions (in English, Polish, Lakhota and Warlpiri) leads to certain revisions. The revised XLS theory then immediately generalizes to complex questions — including scope marking (Hindi), questions with quantifiers (English) and multiple wh-questions (English, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  77
    The epistemics of presupposition projection.Jan van Eijck & Christina Unger - 2007 - In Dekker Aloni (ed.), Proceedings of the Sixteenth Amsterdam Colloquium. pp. 235-240.
    We carry out the Karttunen-Stalnaker pragmatic account of presupposition projection within a state-of-the art version of dynamic epistemic logic. It turns out that the basic projection facts can all be derived from a Gricean maxim ‘be informative’. This sheds light on a recent controversy on the appropriateness of dynamic semantics as a tool for analysing presupposition.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Must . . . stay . . . strong!Kai von Fintel & Anthony S. Gillies - 2010 - Natural Language Semantics 18 (4):351-383.
    It is a recurring mantra that epistemic must creates a statement that is weaker than the corresponding flat-footed assertion: It must be raining vs. It’s raining. Contrary to classic discussions of the phenomenon such as by Karttunen, Kratzer, and Veltman, we argue that instead of having a weak semantics, must presupposes the presence of an indirect inference or deduction rather than of a direct observation. This is independent of the strength of the claim being made. Epistemic must is therefore (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  23.  8
    What Comes First in Dynamic Semantics: A Critical Review of Linguistic Theories of Presupposition and a Dynamic Alternative.David Beaver - 2001 - Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.
    Russell and Strawson sparked a well known debate on the subject of Linguistic Presupposition inspiring many linguists and philosophers to follow suit, including Frege, whose work initiated the modern study in this area. Beaver begins with the most comprehensive overview and critical discussion of this burgeoning field published to date. He then goes on to motivate and develop his own account based on a Dynamic Semantics. This account is a recent line of theoretical work in which the Tarskian emphasis on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  24. Semantic analysis of wh-complements.Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stokhof - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (2):175 - 233.
    This paper presents an analysis of wh-complements in Montague Grammar. We will be concerned primarily with semantics, though some remarks on syntax are made in Section 4. Questions and wh-comple ments in Montague Grammar have been studied in Hamblin (1976), Bennett (1979), Karttunen (1977) and Hauser (1978) among others. These proposals will not be discussed explicitly, but some differences with Karttunen's analysis will be pointed out along the way.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  25.  16
    Intervention Effects and Additivity.Clemens Mayr - 2014 - Journal of Semantics 31 (4):fft010.
    Next SectionBy discussing a novel paradigm, it is shown that the likeliness of an operator to trigger an intervention effect in a wh-in-situ question is determined by the logical properties of that operator (contra Beck 1996a, 2006, for instance). A new empirical generalization accounting for the differences between operators in their ability to cause intervention and improving on existing analyses is suggested. This generalization is fully predictive and allows one to not have to list in the lexicon whether an intervener (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  26. Against Accommodation: Heim, van der Sandt, and the Presupposition Projection Problem.Christopher Gauker - 2008 - Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1):171 - 205.
    This paper criticizes the dominant approaches to presupposition projection and proposes an alternative. Both the update semantics of Heim and the discourse representation theory of van der Sandt have problems in explicating the presuppositions of disjunctions. Moreover, Heim's approach is committed to a conception of accommodation that founders on the problem of informative presuppositions, and van der Sandt's approach is committed to a conception of accommodation that generates over-interpretations of utterances. The present approach borrows Karttunen's idea that instead of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  27.  46
    The scope of alternatives: indefiniteness and islands.Simon Charlow - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (4):427-472.
    I argue that alternative-denoting expressions interact with their semantic context by taking scope. With an empirical focus on indefinites in English, I show how this approach improves on standard alternative-semantic architectures that use point-wise composition to subvert islands, as well as on in situ approaches to indefinites more generally. Unlike grammars based on point-wise composition, scope-based alternative management is thoroughly categorematic, doesn’t under-generate readings when multiple sources of alternatives occur on an island, and is compatible with standard treatments of binding. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  28. Presuppositions and Local Contexts.P. Schlenker - 2010 - Mind 119 (474):377-391.
    In the last thirty years, the problem of presupposition projection has been taken to provide a decisive argument for a dynamic approach to meaning, one in which expressions are not evaluated with respect to the ‘global’ context of utterance, but rather with respect to a ‘local context’ obtained by updating the global one with expressions that occur earlier in the sentence. The computation of local contexts is taken by dynamic analyses to follow from a generalization of the notion of belief (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  29.  59
    Information Structure: Afterword.Craige Roberts - 2012 - Semantics and Pragmatics 5 (7):1-19.
    As a graduate student in Linguistics at UMass/Amherst in the 1980s, I was fortunate to be exposed to a number of new developments bearing on the relationship between formal semantics and pragmatics. In the 1970s under the influence of Cresswell, Lewis, Montague, and Partee, enormous progress in semantics was made possible by narrowing the focus of the field mainly to the consideration of the conventional, truth conditional content of an indicative utterance, calculated compositionally as a function of the semantic contributions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  30.  80
    A Flexible Approach to Exhaustivity in Questions.Sigrid Beck & Hotze Rullmann - 1999 - Natural Language Semantics 7 (3):249-298.
    A semantics for interrogatives is presented which is based on Karttunen's theory, but in a flexible manner incorporates both weak and strong exhaustivity. The paper starts out by considering degree questions, which often require an answer picking out the maximal degree from a certain set. However, in some cases, depending on the semantic properties of the question predicate, reference to the minimal degree is required, or neither specifying the maximum nor the minimum is sufficient. What is needed is an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  31.  38
    The scope of even.Karina Wilkinson - 1996 - Natural Language Semantics 4 (3):193-215.
    This paper is about even in downward entailing contexts. Karttunen and Peters (1979) have shown that there are two different sets of implicatures of even in such contexts. They argue that the two sets of implicatures are derived by allowing even to take scope either higher or lower than a negative polarity licenser. Rooth (1985) argues that even is lexically ambiguous, that is, there is a negative polarity even. I argue against Rooth's ambiguity theory and show that within Rooth's (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  32.  14
    ‘Who’ and ‘whether’: Towards a theory of indirect question clauses.Steven E. Boër - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (3):307-345.
    This paper shows in detail how the formal semiotic of M. J. Cresswell [6] may be extended to provide an account of indirect question clauses in English. The resulting account is compared at various points with the theory recently propounded by Karttunen [12] and is argued to have two major advantages over the latter in that (i) it accommodates the manifest teleological relativity of ‘who’-clauses, and (ii) it avoids the need for categorial segregation of sentence-taking verbs from wh-clause-taking verbs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33. Attitude verbs’ local context.Kyle Blumberg & Simon Goldstein - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 46 (3):483-507.
    Schlenker (Semant Pragmat 2(3):1–78, 2009; Philos Stud 151(1):115–142, 2010a; Mind 119(474):377–391, 2010b) provides an algorithm for deriving the presupposition projection properties of an expression from that expression’s classical semantics. In this paper, we consider the predictions of Schlenker’s algorithm as applied to attitude verbs. More specifically, we compare Schlenker’s theory with a prominent view which maintains that attitudes exhibit belief projection, so that presupposition triggers in their scope imply that the attitude holder believes the presupposition (Karttunen in Theor Linguist (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. A multi-dimensional treatment of quantification in extraordinary English.Paul Dekker - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (1):101-127.
    In this paper I revive two important formal approaches to the interpretation of natural language, that of Montague and that of Karttunen and Peters. Armed with insights from dynamic semantics (Heim, Krifka) the two turn out to stand up against age-old criticisms in an orthodox fashion. The plan is mainly methodological, as I only want to illustrate the technical feasibility of the revived proposals. Even so, there are illuminating and welcome empirical consequences on the subject of scope islands (as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  51
    UNTIL, aspect, and negation: A novel argument for two untils.Anastasia Giannakidou - manuscript
    The puzzle of English until is well-known. Karttunen 1974 argues that until is ambiguous between a durative and a punctual negative polarity (NPI) meaning. Mittwoch 1977 claims that there is no ambiguity and that the two meanings are due to scope differences: NPI-until is in fact until above negation. Mittwoch’s account relies crucially on the assumption that negation is an aspectual operator that ‘stativizes’ verb meanings (a position recently argued for in de Swart 1996, and de Swart and Molendijk (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  16
    The existential/uniqueness presupposition of wh-complements projects from the answers.Wataru Uegaki - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 44 (4):911-951.
    The projection pattern of the existential/uniqueness presupposition of a wh-complement varies depending on the predicate that embeds it. This variation poses problems for existing accounts that treat the presupposition as a semantic contribution of an operator merging with the wh-complement or of the embedding predicate. I propose that the problems can be solved if the existential/uniqueness presupposition is contributed by the propositions corresponding to the answers of the embedded question, under the Hamblin/Karttunen semantics for questions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37. Conditional Collapse.Sam Carter - 2023 - Mind 132 (528):971-1004.
    Indicative and subjunctive conditionals are in non-complimentary distribution: there are conversational contexts at which both are licensed (Stalnaker 1975; Karttunen and Peters 1979; von Fintel 1998). This means we can ask an important, but under-explored, question: in contexts which license both, what relations hold between the two? In this paper, I’ll argue for an initially surprising conclusion: when attention is restricted to the relevant contexts, indicatives and subjunctives are co-entailing. §1 introduces the indicative/subjunctive distinction, along with a discussion of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. A preliminary case for conventional implicatures.Christopher Potts - unknown
    The history of conventional implicatures is rocky, their current status uncertain. So it seems wise to return to their source and start afresh, with an open-minded reading of the original definition (Grice 1975) and an eye open for novel factual support. Suppose the textbook examples (therefore, even, but and its synonyms) disappeared. Where would conventional implicatures be then? This book’s primary descriptive claim is that they would still enjoy widespread factual support. I match this with a theoretical proposal: if we (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Structured anaphora to quantifier domains: A unified account of quantificational and modal subordination.Adrian Brasoveanu - manuscript
    The paper proposes an account of the contrast (noticed in Karttunen 1976) between the interpretations of the following two discourses: Harvey courts a girl at every convention. {She is very pretty. vs. She always comes to the banquet with him.}. The initial sentence is ambiguous between two quantifier scopings, but the first discourse as a whole allows only for the wide-scope indefinite reading, while the second allows for both. This cross-sentential interaction between quantifier scope and anaphora is captured by (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40.  75
    On pragmatic presupposition.David S. Schwarz - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (2):247 - 257.
    I argue that (a) the phenomenon characteristic of pragmatic presupposition, is distinct from (b) the phenomenon characteristic of semantic presupposition, and that there are sentences exhibiting (a) alone. I apply this to Stalnaker's defense of van Fraassen's theory of semantic presupposition against Karttunen. I show that, since Stalmaker fails to distinguish (a) from (b), this defense amounts to an unsuccessful attempt to explain pragmatically the supposed instances of (b) in Karttunen's counter-examples. I observe that, given the distinction between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Ellipsis and Movement in the Syntax of Whether/Q...or Questions.Chung-Hye Han & Maribel Romero - unknown
    In English, a non-wh-question may have a disjunctive phrase explicitly providing the choices that the question ranges over. For example, in (1), the disjunction or not indicates that the the choice is between the positive and the negative polarity for the relevant proposition, as spelled out in the yes/no (yn)-question reading (2) and in the answers (2a,b). Another example is (3). The disjunction in (3) can be understood as providing the choices that the question ranges over, hence giving rise to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. The interpretation of indefinites in future tense sentences. A novel argument for the modality of will?Fabio Del Prete - 2014 - In Mikhail Kissine, Philippe de Brabanter & Saghie Sharifzadeh (eds.), Oxford Studies of Time in Language and Thought. Oxford University Press.
    The chapter considers two semantic issues concerning will-sentences: Stalnaker’s Asymmetry and modal subordination in Karttunen-type discourses. The former points to a distinction between will and modal verbs, seeming to show that will does not license non-specific indefinites. The latter, conversely, suggests that will-sentences involve some kind of modality. To account for the data, the chapter proposes that will is semantically a tense, hence it doesn’t contribute a quantifier over modal alternatives; a modal feature, however, is introduced in the interpretation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Rhetorically-based scalar-additivity: The view from Italian 'addirittura'.Salvatore Pistoia-Reda & Louise McNally - forthcoming - Salt 32.
    Even-like particles have widely been analyzed as inducing scalar and additive presuppositions (cf. Horn 1969; Karttunen & Peters 1979; Rooth 1992; Gast & van der Auwera 2011). However, the additivity of even has been controversial since at least Horn 1992 and increasingly called into question (see Greenberg & Umbach 2021 for references); Greenberg specifically argues that scalar even-like particles can vary in additivity. This claim is surprising in light of the typological study in Gast & van der Auwera 2011, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  56
    Evidentials and Questions in Cheyenne.Sarah E. Murray - 2010 - In Suzi Lima (ed.), Proceedings of SULA 5: Semantics of Under-Represented Languages in the Americas (2009). GLSA Publications. pp. 139--155.
    On one view, the point of an assertion is to update the common ground (Stalnaker 1978, Karttunen 1974). On another, the point of an assertion is to propose an update to the com- mon ground (Groenendijk 2009, Mascarenhas 2009, and related work on the structure of discourse, e.g., Ginzburg 1996, Roberts 1996, Gunlogson 2001). In Murray (to appear), I merge these two views. I argue based on evidence from declarative sentences with eviden- tials that assertion has two components: what (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Modes of Predication and Implied Adverbial Complements.Robert W. Wilkinson - 1976 - Foundations of Language 14 (2):153-194.
    Constructions having the surface form NP be ADJ enough to VP are examined. It is shown that when ADJ in this construction belongs to a small class of adjectives including lucky or to a larger class including wise, a structural ambiguity appears in the complement of enough which is related to the distinction between implied and non-implied complements made in Karttunen . The underlying syntactic structure of NP be ADJ enough to VP when ADJ is lucky or wise is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  20
    Principles of presupposition in development.Athulya Aravind, Danny Fox & Martin Hackl - 2023 - Linguistics and Philosophy 46 (2):291-332.
    This paper brings a developmental perspective to the discussion of a longstanding issue surrounding the proper characterization of presuppositions. On an influential view (Stalnaker in Synthese 22(1–2):272–289, 1970; Stalnaker, in Milton, Unger (eds) Semantics and philosophy, New York University Press, New York, 1974; Karttunen in Theor Linguist 1:181–194, 1974), formal presuppositions reflect admittance conditions: an utterance of a sentence which presupposes _p_ is admitted by a conversational context _c_ only if _p_ is common ground in _c_. The theory distinguishes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  28
    On the distribution of NPIs in Korean.Duk-Ho An - 2007 - Natural Language Semantics 15 (4):317-350.
    In this paper, I offer a novel solution to the well-known problem concerning two polarity items in Korean, amu-(N)-to and amu-(N)-rato, that show a complementary distribution within the set of typical NPI-licensing contexts. I present a uniform analysis of the distribution of these NPIs, where the complementary distribution follows from the opposite scope properties of the emphatic particles to and rato contained in the NPIs in question. As the- oretical background, I adopt Karttunen and Peters’s (1979, Syntax and Semantics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Representations, Attitudes, and Factivity Evaluations: An Epistemically-Based Analysis of Lexical Selection.Daniel Dor - 1996 - Dissertation, Stanford University
    The thesis concerns itself with the selection constraints governing the basic distributional patterns of five complement constructions in English--the bare clause, the that-clause, the interrogative, the concealed question construction and the exclamative complement--across a wide array of knowledge, belief and communication predicates. The relevant distributional phenomena--which predicates are capable of embedding which complement types--have traditionally been captured by stipulative grammatical markings such as subcategorization frames, semantic selection frames and case-theoretic lexical markings. These theoretical tools, even to the extent that they (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. What ‘must’ adds.Matthew Mandelkern - 2019 - Linguistics and Philosophy 42 (3):225-266.
    There is a difference between the conditions in which one can felicitously use a ‘must’-claim like and those in which one can use the corresponding claim without the ‘must’, as in 'It must be raining out' versus 'It is raining out. It is difficult to pin down just what this difference amounts to. And it is difficult to account for this difference, since assertions of 'Must p' and assertions of p alone seem to have the same basic goal: namely, communicating (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  50. Structured anaphora to quantifier domains: A unified account of quantificational & modal subordination and exceptional wide scope.Adrian Brasoveanu - manuscript
    The paper proposes a novel analysis of quantificational subordination, e.g. Harvey courts a woman at every convention. {She is very pretty. vs. She always comes to the banquet with him.} (Karttunen 1976), in particular of the fact that the indefinite in the initial sentence can have wide or narrow scope, but the first discourse as a whole allows only for the wide scope reading, while the second discourse allows for both readings. The cross-sentential interaction between scope and anaphora is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 54