48 found
Order:
  1.  7
    Rationality and Intelligence.Jonathan Baron - 1987 - British Journal of Educational Studies 35 (1):74-76.
  2.  54
    Nonconsequentialist decisions.Jonathan Baron - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):1-10.
  3.  23
    Actively open-minded thinking in politics.Jonathan Baron - 2019 - Cognition 188 (C):8-18.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4.  50
    Unsentimental ethics: Towards a content-specific account of the moral–conventional distinction.Edward B. Royzman, Robert F. Leeman & Jonathan Baron - 2009 - Cognition 112 (1):159-174.
  5.  46
    Tradeoffs among reasons for action.Jonathan Baron - 1986 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 16 (2):173–195.
  6.  33
    Challenges for the sequential two-system model of moral judgement.Burcu Gürçay & Jonathan Baron - 2017 - Thinking and Reasoning 23 (1):49-80.
    Considerable evidence supports the sequential two-system model of moral judgement, as proposed by Greene and others. We tested whether judgement speed and/or personal/impersonal moral dilemmas can predict the kind of moral judgements subjects make for each dilemma, and whether personal dilemmas create difficulty in moral judgements. Our results showed that neither personal/impersonal conditions nor spontaneous/thoughtful-reflection conditions were reliable predictors of utilitarian or deontological moral judgements. Yet, we found support for an alternative view, in which, when the two types of responses (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7.  40
    Myside bias in thinking about abortion.Jonathan Baron - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (3):221 – 235.
    College-student subjects made notes about the morality of early abortion, as if they were preparing for a class discussion. Analysis of the quality of their arguments suggests that a distinction can be made between arguments based on well-supported warrants and those based on warrants that are easily criticised. The subjects also evaluated notes made by other, hypothetical, students preparing for the same discussion. Most subjects evaluated the set of arguments as better when the arguments were all on one side than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  8.  8
    Utility, exchange, and commensurability.Jonathan Baron - 1988 - Journal of Thought 23:111-131.
  9.  21
    Correlations of trait and state emotions with utilitarian moral judgements.Jonathan Baron, Burcu Gürçay & Mary Frances Luce - 2018 - Cognition and Emotion 32 (1):116-129.
    In four experiments, we asked subjects for judgements about scenarios that pit utilitarian outcomes against deontological moral rules, for example, saving more lives vs. a rule against active killing. We measured trait emotions of anger, disgust, sympathy and empathy, asked about the same emotions after each scenario. We found that utilitarian responding to the scenarios, and higher scores on a utilitarianism scale, were correlated negatively with disgust, positively with anger, positively with specific sympathy and state sympathy, and less so with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  30
    Back to basics.Jonathan Baron - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):706-706.
  11.  28
    Second-order probabilities and belief functions.Jonathan Baron - 1987 - Theory and Decision 23 (1):25-36.
  12.  26
    Utilitarian Emotions: Suggestions from Introspection.Jonathan Baron - 2011 - Emotion Review 3 (3):286-286.
    In folk psychology and some academic psychology, utilitarian thinking is associated with coldness and deontological thinking is associated with emotion. I suggest, mostly through personal examples, that these associations are far from perfect. Utilitarians experience emotions, which sometimes derive from, and sometimes cause or reinforce, their moral judgments.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  13
    A decision analysis of consent.Jonathan Baron - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (3):46 – 52.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14. Use of a Rasch model to predict response times to utilitarian moral dilemmas.Jonathan Baron, Burcu Gürçay, Adam B. Moore & Katrin Starcke - 2012 - Synthese 189 (S1):107-117.
    A two-systems model of moral judgment proposed by Joshua Greene holds that deontological moral judgments (those based on simple rules concerning action) are often primary and intuitive, and these intuitive judgments must be overridden by reflection in order to yield utilitarian (consequence-based) responses. For example, one dilemma asks whether it is right to push a man onto a track in order to stop a trolley that is heading for five others. Those who favor pushing, the utilitarian response, usually take longer (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  26
    Social acceptability, personal responsibility, and prognosis in public judgments and transplant allocation.Peter A. Ubel, Jonathan Baron & David A. Asch - 1999 - Bioethics 13 (1):57–68.
  16.  49
    Belief-Overkill in Political Judgments.Jonathan Baron - 2009 - Informal Logic 29 (4):368-378.
    When people tend toward a political decision, such as voting for the Republican Party, they are often attracted to this decision by one issue, such as the party’s stance on abortion, but then they come to see other issues, such as the party’s stand on taxes, as supporting their decision, even if they would not have thought so in the absence of the decision. I demonstrate this phenomenon with opinion poll data and with an experiment done on the World Wide (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  23
    Determinants of insensitivity to quantity in valuation of public goods: Contribution, warm glow, budget constraints, availability, and prominence.Jonathan Baron & Joshua Greene - 1996 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 2 (2):107.
  18.  81
    A Psychological View of Moral Intuition.Jonathan Baron - 1995 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 5 (1):36-40.
  19.  34
    Normative, descriptive and prescriptive responses.Jonathan Baron - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):32-42.
  20.  73
    Cognitive biases in moral judgments that affect political behavior.Jonathan Baron - 2010 - Synthese 172 (1):7 - 35.
    Cognitive biases that affect decision making may affect the decisions of citizens that influence public policy. To the extent that decisions follow principles other than maximizing utility for all, it is less likely that utility will be maximized, and the citizens will ultimately suffer the results. Here I outline some basic arguments concerning decisions by citizens, using voting as an example. I describe two types of values that may lead to sub-optimal consequences when these values influence political behavior: moralistic values (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  12
    Cognitive biases in moral judgments that affect political behavior.Jonathan Baron - 2010 - Synthese 172 (1):7-35.
    Cognitive biases that affect decision making may affect the decisions of citizens that influence public policy. To the extent that decisions follow principles other than maximizing utility for all, it is less likely that utility will be maximized, and the citizens will ultimately suffer the results. Here I outline some basic arguments concerning decisions by citizens, using voting as an example. I describe two types of values that may lead to sub-optimal consequences when these values influence political behavior: moralistic values (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  31
    Norm-Endorsement Utilitarianism and the Nature of Utility.Jonathan Baron - 1996 - Economics and Philosophy 12 (2):165.
    In this article, I shall suggest an approach to the justification of normative moral principles which leads, I think, to utilitarianism. The approach is based on asking what moral norms we would each endorse if we had no prior moral commitments. I argue that we would endorse norms that lead to the satisfaction of all our nonmoral values or goals. The same approach leads to a view of utility as consisting of those goals that we would want satisfied. In the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  12
    Protected Values and Other Types of Values.Jonathan Baron - 2017 - Analyse & Kritik 39 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  7
    Joint presentation reduces the effect of emotion on evaluation of public actions.Ilana Ritov & Jonathan Baron - 2011 - Cognition and Emotion 25 (4):657-675.
  25.  90
    Uncertainty and Probability within Utilitarian Theory.Jonathan Baron - 2017 - Diametros 53:6-25.
    Probability is a central concept in utilitarian moral theory, almost impossible to do without. I attempt to clarify the role of probability, so that we can be clear about what we are aiming for when we apply utilitarian theory to real cases. I point out the close relationship between utilitarianism and expected-utility theory, a normative standard for individual decision-making. I then argue that the distinction between “ambiguity” and risk is a matter of perception. We do not need this distinction in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  31
    Normative and prescriptive implications of individual differences.Jonathan Baron - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5):668-669.
    Stanovich & West (S&W) have two goals, one concerned with the evaluation of normative models, the other with development of prescriptive models. Individual differences have no bearing on normative models, which are justified by analysis, not consensus. Individual differences do, however, suggest where it is possible to try to improve human judgments and decisions through education rather than computers.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  15
    Deduction as an example of thinking.Jonathan Baron - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):336-337.
  28.  42
    Why do groups cooperate more than individuals to reduce risks?Min Gong, Jonathan Baron & Howard Kunreuther - 2013 - Theory and Decision 75 (1):101-116.
    Previous research has discovered a curious phenomenon: groups cooperate less than individuals in a deterministic prisoner’s dilemma game, but cooperate more than individuals when uncertainty is introduced into the game. We conducted two studies to examine three possible processes that might drive groups to be more cooperative than individuals in reducing risks: group risk concern, group cooperation expectation, and pressure to conform to social norms. We found that ex post guilt aversion and ex-post blame avoidance cause group members to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  47
    The problem of global warming from a decision‐theoretic perspective.Jonathan Baron & Jay Schulkin - 1995 - Social Epistemology 9 (4):353 – 368.
  30. Decision-making and the threat of global warming.Jonathan Baron & Jay Schulkin - forthcoming - Social Epistemology.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  29
    Kuhn`s The Skills of Argument.Jonathan Baron - 1992 - Informal Logic 14 (1).
  32.  26
    Optimality as an evaluative standard in the study of decision-making.Jonathan Baron - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):216-216.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  35
    Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy, Robert E. Goodin. Cambridge University Press, 1995, 352 + xii pages.Jonathan Baron - 1998 - Economics and Philosophy 14 (1):151.
  34.  28
    A theory of social decisions.Jonathan Baron - 1995 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 25 (2):103–114.
  35.  17
    Criteria and explanations.Jonathan Baron - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):287.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  14
    Schools of Thought: How the Politics of Literacy Shape Thinking in the Classroom. [REVIEW]Jonathan Baron - 1991 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 8 (1):17-19.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  17
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “A Decisional Analysis of Consent”.Jonathan Baron - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (3):W51-W53.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  12
    Situated cognition, prescriptive theory, evolution, and something.Jonathan Baron - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):324-326.
  39.  10
    Some thinking is irrational.Jonathan Baron - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):486-487.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  18
    Rationality and illusion.Jonathan Baron - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (2):252-253.
    Commitment to a pattern of altruism or self-control may indeed be learnable and sometimes rational. Commitment may also result from illusions. In one illusion, people think that their present behavior causes their future behavior, or causes the behavior of others, when really only correlation is present. Another happy illusion is that morality and self-interest coincide, so that altruism appears self-interested.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  5
    Schools of Thought: How the Politics of Literacy Shape Thinking in the Classroom. [REVIEW]Jonathan Baron - 1991 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 8 (1):17-19.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  7
    Reliability and g.Jonathan Baron - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):220-221.
  43.  19
    Stimuli and subjects in one-tailed tests.Jonathan Baron - 1975 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 6 (6):608-610.
  44.  3
    No Title available: Reviews.Jonathan Baron - 1998 - Economics and Philosophy 14 (1):151-157.
  45.  13
    Biting the utilitarian bullet.Jonathan Baron - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4):545-546.
    The heuristics-and-biases approach requires a clear separation of normative and descriptive models. Normative models cannot be justified by intuition, or by consensus. The lack of consensus on normative theory is a problem for prescriptive approaches. One solution to the prescriptive problem is to argue contingently: if you are concerned about consequences, here is a way to make them better.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  1
    Book Review. [REVIEW]Jonathan Baron - 1998 - Economics and Philosophy 14 (1):151-157.
  47.  1
    Semantic components and conceptual development.Jonathan Baron - 1973 - Cognition 2 (3):299-317.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  8
    Purposes and methods.Jonathan Baron - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (3):403-403.
    The methods of experiments in the social sciences should depend on their purposes. To support this claim, I attempt to state some general principles relating method to purpose for three of the issues addressed. (I do not understand what is not a script, so I will omit that issue.) I illustrate my outline with examples from psychological research on judgment and decision making (JDM).
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation