66 found
Order:
Disambiguations
John Tienson [45]John L. Tienson [21]John Leander Tienson [1]
  1. The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oup Usa. pp. 520--533.
  2.  94
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1996 - MIT Press.
    In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Horgan and Tienson articulate and defend a new view of cognition.
  3.  17
    Reference and Essence.John Tienson - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1417-1419.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  4. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  5. Internal-World Skepticism and the Self-Presentational Nature of Phenomenal Consciousness.Terence Horgan, John Tienson & Graham George - 2006 - In Kriegel Uriah & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-representational Approaches to Consciousness. Bradford.
  6.  49
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.) - 1991 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  7. The phenomenology of first-person agency.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2003 - In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic. pp. 323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  8. Consciousness and intentionality.George Graham, Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 468--484.
  9. Deconstructing new wave materialism.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press. pp. 307--318.
    In the first post World War II identity theories (e.g., Place 1956, Smart 1962), mind brain identities were held to be contingent. However, in work beginning in the late 1960's, Saul Kripke (1971, 1980) convinced the philosophical community that true identity statements involving names and natural kind terms are necessarily true and furthermore, that many such necessary identities can only be known a posteriori. Kripke also offered an explanation of the a posteriori nature of ordinary theoretical identities such as that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  10.  52
    Soft laws.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):256-279.
  11.  82
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  12.  67
    Representation without rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-74.
  13. A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  14. The phenomenology of intentionality and the intentionality of phenomenology.Terry Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 520--533.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  15. Cognitive systems as dynamic systems.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Topoi 11 (1):27-43.
  16.  24
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  17. Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2009 - In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press. pp. 512--537.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  43
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):97-113.
  19.  44
    An introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):1-16.
  20.  70
    Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:127-52.
  21.  17
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):241--260.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22. Structured representations in connectionist systems?Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1991 - In S. Davis (ed.), Connectionism: Theorye and Practice. Oxford University Press.
  23.  52
    On analysing knowledge.John Tienson - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 25 (4):289 - 293.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24. The Phenomenology of Embodied Agency.Terry Horgan & John Tienson - unknown
    For the last 20 years or so, philosophers of mind have been using the term ‘qualia’, which is frequently glossed as standing for the “what-it-is-like” of experience. The examples of what-it-is-like that are typically given are feelings of pain or itches, and color and sound sensations. This suggests an identification of the experiential what-it-islike with such states. More recently, philosophers have begun speaking of the “phenomenology“ of experience, which they have also glossed as “what-it-is-like”. Many say, for example, that any (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. Introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 1:1-16.
  26.  73
    Hume on universals and general terms.John Tienson - 1984 - Noûs 18 (2):311-330.
  27. Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press. pp. 41-61.
  28.  8
    Questions for blobjectivism.John Tienson - 2002 - Facta Philosophica 2 (2):301-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  30
    Levels of Description in Nonclassical Cognitive Science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:159-188.
    David Marr provided an influential account of levels of description in classical cognitive science. In this paper we contrast Marr'ent with some alternatives that are suggested by the recent emergence of connectionism. Marr's account is interesting and important both because of the levels of description it distinguishes, and because of the way his presentation reflects some of the most basic, foundational, assumptions of classical AI-style cognitive science. Thus, by focusing on levels of description, one can sharpen foundational differences between classicism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  35
    Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):1-24.
  31.  4
    Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2017 - In William Bechtel & George Graham (eds.), A Companion to Cognitive Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 660–670.
    Contemporary cognitive science has two principal branches: the classical computational approach (sometimes called classicism) and connectionism. Rules are fundamental to theorizing about the basic units of processing in both classicism and connectionism. But we will be concerned primarily with rules that apply to representations and that determine transitions from one cognitive/representational state to the next. Such rules are fundamental to classicism, since, according to classicism, cognitive processes simply are rule‐governed cognitive state transitions. Rules that apply to representations are not a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Authors' replies.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:275-287.
  33.  1
    Settling Into a New Paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):97-113.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  24
    Innate Ideas.John Tienson - 1978 - Noûs 12 (3):337-343.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  22
    A Conception of Metaphysics.John L. Tienson - 1989 - American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1):63 - 71.
  36.  56
    Kasimir Twardowski on the content of presentations.John Tienson - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (3):485-499.
    In On the Content and Object of Presentations, Kasimir Twardowski presents an interesting line of thought concerning the content of a presentation and its relation to the object of that presentation. This way of thinking about content is valuable for understanding phenomenal intentionality, and it should also be important for the project of “naturalizing” the mental (or at least for discovering the neural correlates of the phenomenal). According to this view, content is that by virtue of which a presentation of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  6
    Consciousness and Intentionality.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2017 - In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 519–535.
    Consciousness and intentionality help to define the mental qua mental. Consciousness and intentionality, insist some philosophers, although perhaps often co‐occurring, are mutually independent or separable. Consciousness and intentionality, insist others, are interdependent or inseparable. This chapter discusses an important aspect of inseparatism: the relation between phenomenal character and intentional content. The contemporary philosophers and theorists have developed inseparatist or nearly inseparatist theses in various ways. The chapter mentions some of this work, and the philosophers responsible for it. It discusses two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Cognition needs syntax but not rules.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2006 - In Robert J. Stainton (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 147--158.
    Human cognition is rich, varied, and complex. In this Chapter we argue that because of the richness of human cognition (and human mental life generally), there must be a syntax of cognitive states, but because of this very richness, cognitive processes cannot be describable by exceptionless rules. The argument for syntax, in Section 1, has to do with being able to get around in any number of possible environments in a complex world. Since nature did not know where in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  47
    Editors' Introduction.Terry Horgan, John Tienson & Matjaž Potrč - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1):7-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  48
    Levels of description in nonclassical cognitive science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Philosophy 34:159-188.
    David Marr provided an influential account of levels of description in classical cognitive science. In this paper we contrast Marr'ent with some alternatives that are suggested by the recent emergence of connectionism. Marr's account is interesting and important both because of the levels of description it distinguishes, and because of the way his presentation reflects some of the most basic, foundational, assumptions of classical AI-style cognitive science . Thus, by focusing on levels of description, one can sharpen foundational differences between (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  26
    Pr cis of connectionism and the philosophy of psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):337 – 356.
    Connectionism was explicitly put forward as an alternative to classical cognitive science. The questions arise: how exactly does connectionism differ from classical cognitive science, and how is it potentially better? The classical “rules and representations” conception of cognition is that cognitive transitions are determined by exceptionless rules that apply to the syntactic structure of symbols. Many philosophers have seen connectionism as a basis for denying structured symbols. We, on the other hand, argue that cognition is too rich and flexible to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  55
    Resisting the tyranny of terminology: The general dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):643-643.
    What van Gelder calls the dynamical hypothesis is only a special case of what we here dub the general dynamical hypothesis. His terminology makes it easy to overlook important alternative dynamical approaches in cognitive science. Connectionist models typically conform to the general dynamical hypothesis, but not to van Gelder's.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Spindel Conference 1987 Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1988 - Dept. Of Philosophy, Memphis State University.
  44. Spindel Conference 2001 Origins: The Common Sources of the Analytic and Phenomenological Traditions.E. M. Horgan, John Tienson & Matjaz Potrc - 2002 - University of Memphis.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  20
    About competence.John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Papers 19 (1):19-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  3
    Oblique Contexts.John Tienson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):821-822.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  24
    An argument concerning quantification and propositional attitudes.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (2):145 - 168.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  60
    An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. After all, we might (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  12
    An observation on common names and proper.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):73-76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name.This contrast is misleading. After all, we might have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  80
    Brains are not conscious.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Papers 16 (November):187-93.
1 — 50 / 66